Sewall Wright's Adaptive Landscape: Philosophical Reflections on Heuristic Value

Sewall Wright's Adaptive Landscape: Philosophical Reflections on Heuristic Value

Dartmouth College Dartmouth Digital Commons Dartmouth Scholarship Faculty Work 1-1-2015 Sewall Wright's Adaptive Landscape: Philosophical Reflections on Heuristic Value Michael Dietrich Dartmouth College Robert A. Skipper Jr. University of Cincinnati Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.dartmouth.edu/facoa Part of the Biology Commons Dartmouth Digital Commons Citation Dietrich, Michael and Skipper, Robert A. Jr., "Sewall Wright's Adaptive Landscape: Philosophical Reflections on Heuristic alueV " (2015). Dartmouth Scholarship. 6. https://digitalcommons.dartmouth.edu/facoa/6 This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Work at Dartmouth Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dartmouth Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Dartmouth Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. OUP CORRECTED PROOF– FINAL, 3/5/2012, SPi CHAPTER 2 Sewall Wright’s Adaptive Landscape: Philosophical Reflections on Heuristic Value Robert A. Skipper, Jr. and Michael R. Dietrich 2.1 Introduction lished in the proceedings as “The Roles of Mutation, Inbreeding, Crossbreeding and Selection in Evolu- Sewall Wright’s 1932 Adaptive Landscape diagram tion” (Wright 1932). The Adaptive Landscape was is arguably the most influential visual heuristic in first publicly presented in the 1932 paper. evolutionary biology, yet the diagram has met with Wright’s aim in the 1931/1932 papers was to criticism from biologists and philosophers since its determine the ideal conditions for evolution to origination. In our view, the diagram is a valu- occur given specific assumptions about the relation- able evaluation heuristic for assessing the dynam- ship between Mendelian heredity and the adaptive ical behavior of population genetics models (Skip- value of gene complexes (Wright 1931, 1932). In per 2004). Although Wright’s particular use of it Wright’s 1932 paper, he used the Adaptive Land- is of dubious value, other biologists have estab- scape diagram to demonstrate his solution (see lished the diagram’s positive heuristic value for Chapter 5). evaluating dynamical behavior. In what follows, we According to Wright (1932), accurately represent- will survey some of the most influential biologi- ing the population genetics of the evolutionary cal and philosophical work considering the role of process requires thousands of dimensions. This is the Adaptive Landscape in evolutionary biology. because the field of possible gene combinations of We will build on a distinction between models, a population is vast (approximately 101000). Wright metaphors, and diagrams to make a case for why used the two-dimensional graphical depiction of Adaptive Landscapes as diagrams have heuristic an Adaptive Landscape in Fig. 2.1a as a way of value for evolutionary biologists. intuitively conveying what can only be accurately represented in thousands of dimensions. Wright’s interpretation of his diagrams is confusing, as we 2.2 Sewall Wright’s Adaptive Landscape will discuss later in this chapter. The surface of the E. M. East invited the architects of theoretical pop- landscape is typically understood as representing ulation genetics, R. A. Fisher, J. B. S. Haldane, populations with each point on the landscape repre- and Sewall Wright, to present their work at the senting a unique combined set of allele frequencies. 1932 Sixth International Congress of Genetics. They Each point or population is then graded for adap- were to present compact and accessible forms tive value. Presumably, populations with very sim- of their seminal but mathematically intimidating ilar sets of alleles at similar frequencies will have work on evolutionary theory. Wright’s principal similar adaptive values and so the adaptive sur- evolutionary paper was his 1931, “Evolution in face will show relatively gradual transitions from Mendelian Populations” (Wright 1931). The paper low to high adaptive value, although this is not a Wright delivered at the congress in 1932 was, basi- necessary condition. The surface of the landscape cally, a distillation of the 1931 paper, and was pub- is very “hilly,” says Wright, because of epistatic 16 OUP CORRECTED PROOF– FINAL, 3/5/2012, SPi WRIGHT’S ADAPTIVE LANDSCAPE: PHILOSOPHICAL REFLECTIONS ON HEURISTIC VALUE 17 nearest local peak regardless of its adaptive value. In Wright’s 1931 paper, he demonstrated mathe- matically the statistical distributions of genes under alternative assumptions of population size, muta- tion rate, migration rate, selection intensity, etc. In the 1932 paper, the graphs displaying the results appear, and he uses them in combination with the landscape diagram to argue for his three-phase shifting balance model of the evolutionary process (window F in Fig. 2.1b) as the solution to his prob- lem of peak shifts via assessments of alternative models of the process (windows A–E in Fig. 2.1b). Wright’s view was that his “shifting balance” pro- cess of evolution satisfied the ideal conditions for evolution to occur. Evolution in the shifting balance process occurs in three phases: Phase I—random genetic drift causes subpopulations semi-isolated within the global population to lose fitness; Phase II—selection on complex genetic interaction sys- tems raises the fitness of those subpopulations; Phase III—interdemic selection then raises the fit- ness of the large or global population. 2.3 Models, metaphors, and diagrams Wright’s 1931 exposition of his shifting balance theory relied on a series of mathematical models. Figure 2.1 Wright’s (1932, pp. 161–163) key figures. (a) Wright’s Adaptive Landscape diagram. (b) Diagrams depict evolution occurring on When he presented his work for a general biolog- the Adaptive Landscape under alternative assumptions. Genetics by ical audience in 1932, he chose to describe the ele- GENETICS SOCIETY OF AMERICA. Copyright 1932. Reproduced with ments, behaviors, and consequences of these mod- permission of GENETICS SOCIETY OF AMERICA. els by developing a metaphor and interpretations of a series of diagrams. These different entities, i.e. relations between genes, the consequences of which models, metaphors, and diagrams, are recognized (for Wright) are that genes adaptive in one combina- by philosophers of science and some biologists as tion are likely to be maladaptive in another. Given having importantly different features and signifi- Wright’s view of epistasis and the vastness of the cantly different roles in the manufacture of scientific field of gene combinations in a field of gene fre- knowledge. quencies, Wright estimates the number of adaptive Diagrams are visual representations that use spa- “peaks” separated by adaptive “valleys” at 10800. tial configurations within an image to convey infor- Peaks are represented by “+”; valleys are repre- mation (Perini 2004, 2005). Understanding how sented by “–.” the form of a representation assigns meaning or The Adaptive Landscape diagram sets up content is a major topic among scholars inter- Wright’s signature problem, viz., the problem of ested in visual representation (Lynch and Wool- peak shifts (see Chapter 6). That is, given that the gar 1990). Extracting the meaning of some images Adaptive Landscape is hilly, the ideal conditions may involve interpreting an image symbolically for evolution to occur must allow a population to in terms of conventions that associate a particular shift from peak to peak to find the highest peak. form and a particular meaning. For other images, Otherwise, a population would remain fixed at the their meaning can be interpreted in terms of the OUP CORRECTED PROOF– FINAL, 3/5/2012, SPi 18 PART I HISTORICAL BACKGROUND AND PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES resemblance of the form to the object represented. relationships better by way of analogy (Lewontin For propositionally-oriented philosophers though, 1963). The didactic function of the Adaptive Land- images are one of many forms for conveying infor- scape as a metaphor depends on our familiarity mation and so seem like they ought to be replace- with actual hilly landscapes and their representa- able by linguistic descriptions (Ruse 1996; Perini tion as topographical maps. 2005). Other philosophers eager to explain why We are convinced that the metaphor of the Adap- images are so prevalent in science, see them as a tive Landscape has been didactically useful in gen- particularly concise and effective way of communi- erating novel theoretical and empirical paths of cating complex information, such as the functional inquiry. In the remainder of this essay, we justify relationships between different molecular struc- our claim by evaluating influential criticisms of the tures to form the active site of an enzyme (Perini usefulness of the metaphor, analyzing a series of 2005). criticisms of Wright’s version of the Adaptive Land- Models, like many diagrams, are extralin- scape, and describing the way in which we under- guistic representations. However, the relation- stand the didactic role of the metaphor. ships between the variables and parameters of a model are articulated linguistically and mathemat- 2.4 Questioning value of the Adaptive ically (Lloyd 1988). Philosophers advocating the Landscape diagram semantic approach to theories have developed a sophisticated understanding of the features of bio- There is considerable agreement among biologists logical models in terms of rules of coexistence, inter- and philosophers that Wright’s particular version action, and temporal succession for the variables

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    11 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us