The Skill of Virtue

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Skill of Virtue THE SKILL OF VIRTUE Matthew Stichter A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY August 2007 Committee: Daniel Jacobson, Advisor Michael Zickar Graduate Faculty Representative David Copp Fred Miller David Sobel © 2006 Matthew Stichter All Rights Reserved iii ABSTRACT Daniel Jacobson, Advisor The revival of virtue ethics brought the ancient Greek concepts of ‘virtue’ and ‘the virtuous person’ back into prominence. Contemporary virtue ethicists present an attractive picture of virtue, for the virtuous person knows how to act in a morally appropriate way and is reliable in acting accordingly. This portrait of the virtuous person appears to be the type of person one should aspire to be, but problems arise with many of the details. Often, only the end state of the virtuous person is described, and it is left mysterious how an average person could ever achieve such an idealized state. Accounts of virtue have left readers with the impression that the virtuous person is an unattainable ideal or psychologically implausible. This dissertation argues that reviving the ancient Greek idea that virtues are like practical skills, which is rarely discussed in contemporary literature, can help provide a more plausible account of the virtuous person. The moral knowledge of the virtuous person is analogous to the practical knowledge of the expert in a skill. Learning a skill is a process of acquiring practical knowledge, that is, the knowledge of how to do something, like building a house or driving a car. With virtue, the practical knowledge is the knowledge of how to act well, like acting brave or just. The few current discussions of the skill analogy rely on a reconstruction of the ancient account of skills for a comparison to virtue. There are advantages, however, to using a modern account of skill acquisition that has had the benefit of research and iv application. This dissertation adapts an account of skills developed by Hubert and Stuart Dreyfus in their research on artificial intelligence. The Dreyfus account displays the features of skills that were relevant in the ancient analogy to virtue: a progress from novice to expert, which begins with following rules and then progresses to being sensitive to the relevant features of particular situations. The skill model of virtue offers the most promising direction for contemporary virtue theory, because it can ground a plausible account of the moral knowledge of the virtuous person. v To Beth, who inspires me to be a better person vi ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would like to thank my parents, who have supported me through so many years of study. I owe thanks to my undergraduate professors who stimulated my interest in philosophy, particularly professors Teloh and Tlumak. I would also like to thank the faculty at Bowling Green, for such a rewarding graduate experience. My deepest thanks goes to my committee: to Daniel Jacobson, for all his patience and guidance as my advisor; to David Copp, for his continued help despite the long distance; to David Sobel, for all his interest and encouragement since I first arrived at B.G.S.U.; and to Fred Miller, for the wealth of feedback from all of our discussions. vii TABLE OF CONTENTS Page CHAPTER 1: OVERVIEW……………………………………………………………………….1 1.1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………..1 1.2 Chapter Summaries………………………………………………………………………..4 CHAPTER 2: ARISTOTLE ON VIRTUE AND SKILL………………………………………..14 2.1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………14 2.2 Virtues as Habits…………………………………………………………………………15 2.3 Doing What is Virtuous………………….………………………………………………18 2.4 Virtues as a Mean……………………………………………………………………...…20 2.5 Acting for the Sake of the Noble………………………………………………………...21 2.6 Conclusion…….…………………………………………………………………………24 CHAPTER 3: ANNAS ON VIRTUE AS A SKILL……………………………………………..25 3.1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………25 3.2 Annas’s Account of Skills………………………………………………….……………27 3.3 Is Annas’s Account of Skills Counterintuitive?.…………………………………………31 3.4 Intellectualist versus Empiricist view of Skills...…………………………………...……33 3.5 Which Account of Skills Does Aristotle Endorse?………………………………………36 3.6 Which Account of Skills is Best?..........…………………………………………………38 3.7 Is the Skill Model Still Suitable for Virtue?..……………………………………………42 3.8 Conclusion………………………………………………………………….……………44 CHAPTER 4: THE DREYFUS SKILL MODEL………………………………………………..46 4.1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………46 viii 4.2 The First Stage – Novice…………………………………………………………………49 4.3 The Second Stage – Advanced Beginner...………………………………………………50 4.4 The Third Stage – Competent Performer...………………………………………………52 4.5 The Fourth Stage – Proficient Performer...………………………………………………53 4.6 The Fifth Stage – Expert…………………………………………………………………54 4.7 Conclusion……………………………………………………….………………………59 CHAPTER 5: NEO-ARISTOTELIAN VIRTUE………………………………………………..60 5.1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………60 5.2 The Dreyfus Skill Model and Aristotle’s Account of Virtue…….………………………61 5.3 The Dreyfus Skill Model and Neo-Aristotelian Accounts of Virtue…….………………64 5.4 Are perceptual metaphors a sign of a bogus epistemology?..……………………………65 5.5 Does the silencing of reasons make the virtuous person a moral fanatic?.………………68 5.6 Should a non-virtuous person always try to act as the virtuous person acts?……………71 5.7 Can the knowledge of the virtuous person be codified?…………………………………73 5.8 Limits of the Skill Model of Virtue………...……………………………………………76 5.9 Conclusion…………………...………………………………………..…………………77 CHAPTER 6: PRACTICAL WISDOM…………………………………………………………78 6.1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………78 6.2 Practical Wisdom as an Intellectual Excellence…………………………………………79 6.3 Practical Wisdom and Deliberation…...…………………………………………………86 6.4 Natural Virtue versus Genuine Virtue………………………………………...…………88 6.5 Eudaimonia and the Unity of the Virtues..………………………………………………92 6.6 Conclusion...………………………………………………………………..……………95 ix CHAPTER 7: THE UNITY OF THE VIRTUES………………………………………………..97 7.1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………97 7.2 The Strong Unity Thesis………………………………………………………..………101 7.3 The Moderate Unity Thesis…………….………………………………………………102 7.4 Objections to the Strong and Moderate Unity Theses.…………………………………103 7.5 The Weak Unity Thesis...………………………………………………………………106 7.6 Objections to the Weak Unity Thesis…………………………………..………………107 7.7 The Minimal Unity Thesis…………………………………..………….………………109 7.8 Objections to the Minimal Unity Thesis……………………………………………..…111 7.9 Conclusion………………………………………………………………………...……116 CHAPTER 8: HONESTY AS A SKILL……………………………………………………….118 8.1 Introduction……………………………………………………………………………..118 8.2 The Simple View of Honesty…………………………………………...………………118 8.3 Rejecting the Simple View of Honesty…………………………………………………120 8.4 What Might Honesty Require?…………………………………………………………122 8.5 Honesty in Business Practices………………………………………………….………124 8.6 Complex Cases – Not wanting to be told the Truth…………………….………………126 8.7 Complex Cases – Negotiation……………………………………………………..……128 8.8 Conclusion……………………………………………………………………………...131 CHAPTER 9: EPILOGUE……………………………………………………………………...132 9.1 Incompleteness of the Skill Model of Virtue…………………………………...………132 9.2 Further Applications of the Skill Model of Virtue……...………………………………134 9.3 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………………...…138 x BIBLIOGRAPHY………………………………………………………………………………139 1 CHAPTER 1: OVERVIEW 1.1 Introduction The revival of virtue ethics has brought the ancient Greek concepts of ‘virtue’ and the ‘virtuous person’ back into prominence in ethical discussion. According to Rosalind Hursthouse (2003), a virtue “is the concept of something that makes its possessor good: a virtuous person is a morally good, excellent or admirable person who acts and feels well, rightly, as she should.” A person with the virtue of kindness, says John McDowell (1998), “can be relied on to behave kindly when that is what the situation requires,” because “a kind person knows what it is like to be confronted with a requirement of kindness” (p. 51). Hursthouse and McDowell present an attractive picture of virtue, for the virtuous person knows how to act in a morally appropriate way and is reliable in acting accordingly. This portrait of the virtuous person appears to be the kind of person one should aspire to be, at least from the moral point of view. When one looks closer, however, problems arise with some of the details. Although passages like the ones quoted above give a good indication of what it would be like to possess a virtue like kindness, it is unclear how the kind person came to have knowledge about when a situation requires kindness. Often, only the end state of the virtuous person is described, and it is left mysterious how an average person could ever achieve such an idealized state. Accounts of the virtuous person have often left readers with the impression that the virtuous person is an unattainable ideal, a moral fanatic, or just psychologically implausible. This dissertation argues that reviving the ancient Greek idea that virtues are like practical skills can help provide a more plausible account of the virtuous person. The moral knowledge of the virtuous person is analogous to the practical knowledge of the expert in a skill. Applying the 2 skill model to virtue is an attempt to take up Aristotle’s suggestion that “we should use as evidence what is apparent for the sake of what is obscure” (Nicomachean Ethics 1104a14-15).1 Aristotle uses this methodology in the frequent analogies he draws between virtues and practical
Recommended publications
  • I-Ii, Question 55, Article 4
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-16578-6 — Commentary on Thomas Aquinas's Virtue Ethics J. Budziszewski Excerpt More Information i-ii, question 55, article 4 Whether Virtue Is Suitably Dei ned? TEXT PARAPHRASE [1] Whether virtue is suitably dei ned? Is the traditional dei nition of virtue i tting? “Virtue is a good quality of the mind that enables us to live in an upright way and cannot be employed badly – one which God brings about in us, with- out us.” St. Thomas respectfully begins with this widely accepted dei nition because it would be arrogant to dismiss the result of generations of inquiry without examination. The ultimate source of the view which it encapsulates is St. Augustine of Hippo, but Augustine did not use precisely this wording. His more diffuse remarks had been condensed into a formula by Peter Lombard, 2 and the formula was then further sharpened by the Lombard’s disciples. Although St. Thomas begins with the tradition, he does not rest with it – he goes on to consider whether the received dei nition is actually correct. The i rst two Objections protest calling virtue a good quality. The third protests calling it a quality of the mind . The fourth objects to the phrase that it enables us to live rightly and the i fth to the phrase that it cannot be employed badly . Finally, the sixth protests the statement that God brings it about in us, without us . Although, in the end, St. Thomas accepts the dei nition, he does not accept it quite in the sense in which some of his predecessors did.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Love and Friendship
    ARISTOTLE ON LOVE AND FRIENDSHIP DAVID KONSTAN Philia is exceptional among ancient Greek value terms for the number of still unre- solved, or at least intensely debated, questions that go to the heart of its very nature.1 Does it mean “friendship”, as it is most commonly rendered in discussions of Aris- totle, or rather “love”, as seems more appropriate in some contexts? Whether it is love, friendship, or something else, is it an emotion, a virtue, or a disposition? The same penumbra of ambiguity surrounds the related term philos, often rendered as “friend” but held by some to include kin and other relations, and even to refer chiefly to them. Thus, Elizabeth Belfiore affirms that “the noun philos surely has the same range as philia, and both refer primarily, if not exclusively, to relationships among close blood kin” (2000: 20). In respect to the affective character of philia, Michael Peachin (2001: 135 n. 2) describes “the standard modern view of Roman friendship” as one “that tends to reduce significantly the emotional aspect of the relationship among the Ro- mans, and to make of it a rather pragmatic business”, and he holds the same to be true of Greek friendship or philia. Scholars at the other extreme maintain that ancient friendship was based essentially on affection. As Peachin remarks (ibid., p. 7), “D. Konstan [1997] has recently argued against the majority opinion and has tried to inject more (modern-style?) emotion into ancient amicitia”. Some critics, in turn, have sought a compromise between the two positions, according to which ancient friend- ship involved both an affective component and the expectation of practical services.
    [Show full text]
  • THE CARDINAL VIRTUE of JUSTICE in a TIME of PANDEMIC This Is the Second in a Series of Four Reflections on the Cardinal Virtues, Presented by Fr
    THE CARDINAL VIRTUE OF JUSTICE IN A TIME OF PANDEMIC This is the second in a series of four reflections on the Cardinal Virtues, presented by Fr. Anthony Barratt, STL, PHD, ChD, from the Upstate New York Area We continue our reflections on the four cardinal virtues; remembering that they are called “cardinal” virtues because everything hinges on them (the word cardinal originally means a hinge or foundation). This time, let us explore the virtue of justice. It may seem strange to think of justice as a virtue, since we often think of justice as more of a thing or entity, or as a system or process. Two things may help us here. The root of the word justice comes from the Latin “ius”; a word that means “right” or “making right”: That is right as in being correct or true (rather than making a right turn, or even our human rights). Furthermore, the Catechism (n. 1807) defines the virtue of justice as “the moral virtue that consists in the constant and firm will to give their due to God and neighbor.” It is a much needed virtue, especially with all the stresses and strains of our uncertain times and the ongoing pandemic. For example, I think that many of us often find ourselves saying that there is no respect anymore; whether it be how people are treated, rudeness, a lack of respect for life, all the negativity and animus in politics, road rage, or whatever. What we are really talking about though is a lack of the virtue of justice.
    [Show full text]
  • Summary Or St. Augustine's City of God | Augustine of Hippo | Virtue
    City of God St. Augustine Book I Preface Augustine explains how he wants to tackle the “glorious city of God” in his work. By this he means he wants to defend his God is the only true God and to show others who believe in other deities that they need to change their views. He praises God and all his works. Chapter 1 He gives a very brief history of Roman times as it relates to worshipping God. Additionally, he goes on to discuss how many people take God and his works for granted. Chapter 16 Here we see some of the first shades of Augustine’s beliefs. He writes: “the only difficulty is so to treat the subject as to satisfy at once modesty and reason” showing his focus on the need for modest means. He goes on to say how the true virtuous life is in the soul and not worldly pleasures. The body and its desires and needs are secondary to those of the soul. Chapter 18 In this section he discusses the contradictions between the body and the soul when controlled by others. He writes that even though the body many be controlled by others (that is, even though you may be forced to do something by another person), no one can ever control your will. He focuses on “purity” of the soul and writes on that matter: “If, on the other hand, it belongs to the soul, then not even when the body is violated is it lost.” As long as the soul remains pure and virtuous then nothing that happens with the body matters.
    [Show full text]
  • What Do We Mean by Virtue?
    What Do We Mean by Virtue? Robert Watts Thornburg This university chaplain takes a pragmatic approach to the ques - tion, “Can virtue be taught in the university? ”, which may seem cynical at first glance. There are significant difficulties in answering the question, including the lack of an adequate definition of terms, the overwhelming influence of Christian and western approaches to the question, the “unvirtue” experienced by many learners and the innate resistance of stu - dents to hearing the word “virtue.” Constructive solutions include avoid - ing theoretical propositional approaches, fostering moral seriousness, making discussion immediate and relevant to learners and, finally, creat - ing communities in which to pursue the search. Not “Virtue” but “virtues” are possible to teach and are already evident in student populations. VIRTUE: what a sweet romantic word! The very notion of putting the words “virtue” and “university” in the same sentence strikes many folks I know as an oxymoron. When, as a University Chaplain, I mention the word “virtue” to students or staff, they give me the quiet benign smile that says: “That’s the kind of thing you people (translate: clergy) always want us to talk about.” Therein lies the problem, and my own difficulty in dis - cussing the question of teaching virtue in any university setting. The word itself carries much baggage, a great variety of meanings springing from Robert Watts Thornburg has just retired after 23 years as dean of Marsh Chapel and university chaplain at Boston University. Educated at DePaul University and Garrett-Evangelical Theological Seminary, he also studied with Paul Tillich at Union Theological Seminary.
    [Show full text]
  • Rosalind Hursthouse, on Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999
    Rosalind Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. Pp. x, 275. Reviewed by Gilbert Harman, Department of Philosophy, Princeton Univer- sity Virtue ethics is atype of ethicaltheory in which the notion of virtue or good character plays a central role. This splendid new book describes a “program” for the development of a particular (“Aristotelian”) form of virtue ethics. The book is intended to be used as a textbook, but should be read by anyone interested in moral philosophy. Hursthouse has been a major contributor to the development of virtue ethics and the program she describes, while making use of the many contributions of others, is very much her program, with numerous new ideas and insights. The book has three parts. The first dispels common misunderstandings and explains how virtue ethics applies to complex moral issues. The sec- ond discusses moral motivation, especially the motivation involved in doing something because it is right. The third explains how questions about the objectivity of ethics are to be approached within virtue ethics. Structure Hursthouse’s virtue ethics takes as central the conception of a human be- ing who possesses all ethical virtues of character and no vices or defects of character—”human being” rather than “person” because the relevant char- acter traits are “natural” to the species. To a first approximation, virtue ethics says that a right action is an action among those available that a perfectly virtuous human being would charac- teristically do under the circumstances. This is only a first approximation because of complications required in order accurately to describe certain moral dilemmas.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics Kanfan Ethics Uflitarian Ethics Communitarian/Virtue Ethics Computers And
    3/17/14 A Brief History of Western Philosophy “To know the good is to desire the good.” Socrates 400 BC Plato virtue “Weakness of the will” Ethics Aristotle 350 BC “the good life” (1200: Thomas Aquinas makes Aristotelian philosophy the core of Catholic theology.) “Categorical axiomatic imperative” Kant 1750 utilitarian Bentham 1800 “Veil of ignorance” Mill 1850 “Virtues come from Rawls 1970 MacIntyre 1980 social practices” “The greatest good for the greatest number” Social Implicaons of Computers Kan4an ethics U4litarian ethics • Categorical Imperave: • The greatest good for the greatest number. – Treat people as ends, not means. • Ac4ons are judged by (probable) results, not purposes. – Ac4ons must be universalizable. – A good act has good results, on balance, for everyone. • Everything else can be derived from these • U4litarian philosophers like to pose dilemmas: axioms. – “Your spouse and your child are thrown overboard and you only have 4me to save one of them. Which one?” – Example: Telling lies isn’t universalizable because if everyone did it, nobody would believe the lies. • People today who don’t think very hard tend to become u4litarians by accident. Don’t do that. • Rawls: the Veil of Ignorance – If you’re a u4litarian, it should be because you’ve chosen – Imagine you don’t know whether you’ll be rich or to. poor; black, white, or brown; male or female; etc. Communitarian/Virtue ethics • The goal of ethical philosophy isn’t to judge individual ac4ons, but to live “the good life” overall. • Ac4ng well comes from good habits–the virtues–not from deliberaon on the spot.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue and Happiness: a Philosophical Inquiry
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Wits Institutional Repository on DSPACE VIRTUE AND HAPPINESS: A PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY Muhammad Assadallah Schuitema 320900 A Research Report submitted to the Faculty of Humanities, University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg, in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts, Applied Ethics for Professionals University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg, 16th March 2015 1 Abstract The position that holds that virtue, as a good, is sufficient for happiness has had illustrious exponents in the past. We will refer to this position as the sufficiency thesis. In recent times however this position has fallen into disfavour. This is largely due to the strong intuition that certain goods other than virtue are necessary for happiness. We will refer to this as the problem of external goods. The point of this paper is to respond to the problem of external goods by articulating an understanding of virtue as involving the ability to occupy a “distanced perspective” within which the virtuous agent becomes detached from external goods insofar as he comes to view them as indifferent. My articulation of this understanding of virtue will be based upon what I take to be the core of the Stoic description of virtue. 2 Declaration I declare that this research report is my own unaided work. It is submitted for the degree of Master of Arts in the University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg. It has not been submitted before for any other degree or examination in any other university.
    [Show full text]
  • Revised New Summary of Philebus
    New Summary of Philebus REVISED 1. (11) Philebus maintains that pleasure, enjoyment, rejoicing, and their kind, are the best things for all animals, while Socrates maintains, for those able to partake of them, wisdom, mind, memory, and their kind, are the best. Each side must agree that it is a condition and disposition of soul that produces happiness. Stipulation: if some other life superior to both is found, then the victor will be he whose champion is closer to this hypothetical best life. a. (12c) Problem: are pleasure and likewise knowledge, both like and unlike themselves, because they each have various aspects and shapes? And are some of these shapes bad and some good? b. (14c) We must investigate this question with the aid of the principle that the one is many and the many are one. This is obvious and common property when applied to things that come to be and perish, but when applied to things like man, ox, beauty, and good, there are perplexities. i. (15b) The perplexities (there is unclarity about exactly what these three questions are): 1. Do such unities exist? 2. How do they, while remaining themselves, enter the domain of becoming? 3. How are they both one and many? ii. (15d) The identification of the one with the many arises everwhere from the nature of discourse itself—it entrances the young. iii. (16c) A gift of the gods: all things contain limit and the unlimited. We must not pass from the one to the infinite too quickly or slowly, but instead note all the intermediate numbers.
    [Show full text]
  • Vegetarianism and Virtue: Does Consequentialism Demand Too Little?
    WellBeing International WBI Studies Repository 1-2002 Vegetarianism and Virtue: Does Consequentialism Demand Too Little? Nathan Nobis University of Rochester Follow this and additional works at: https://www.wellbeingintlstudiesrepository.org/acwp_aafhh Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Other Anthropology Commons, and the Other Nutrition Commons Recommended Citation Nobis, N. (2002). Vegetarianism and Virtue: Does consequentialism Demand Too Little?. Social Theory & Practice, 28(1), 135-156. This material is brought to you for free and open access by WellBeing International. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Vegetarianism and Virtue: Does Consequentialism Demand Too Little? Nathan Nobis Department of Philosophy, University of Rochester I will argue that each of us personally ought to be a vegetarian.1 Actually, the conclusion I will attempt to defend concerns more than one's eating habits in that I will argue that we should be "vegans." Not only should we not buy and eat meat, but we should also not purchase fur coats, stoles, and hats, or leather shoes, belts, jackets, purses and wallets, furniture, car interiors, and other traditionally animal-based products for which there are readily available plant-based or synthetic alternatives. (Usually these are cheaper and work just as well, or better, anyway.) I will argue that buying and eating most eggs and dairy products are immoral as well. (Since it's much easier
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOTLE and the IMPORTANCE of VIRTUE in the CONTEXT of the POLITICS and the NICOMACHEAN ETHICS and ITS RELATION to TODAY Kyle Brandon Anthony Bucknell University
    Bucknell University Bucknell Digital Commons Honors Theses Student Theses 2010 ARISTOTLE AND THE IMPORTANCE OF VIRTUE IN THE CONTEXT OF THE POLITICS AND THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS AND ITS RELATION TO TODAY Kyle Brandon Anthony Bucknell University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.bucknell.edu/honors_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Anthony, Kyle Brandon, "ARISTOTLE AND THE IMPORTANCE OF VIRTUE IN THE CONTEXT OF THE POLITICS AND THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS AND ITS RELATION TO TODAY" (2010). Honors Theses. 21. https://digitalcommons.bucknell.edu/honors_theses/21 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Theses at Bucknell Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Bucknell Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Table of Contents Introduction 1 Chapter 1 What does it mean to live a good life? 7 The virtuous life 8 Ethical virtue 13 Bravery as an ethical virtue 20 Justice 22 Chapter 2 The Politics and the ideal polis 28 Development of a polis 29 Features of an ideal polis 32 What does it mean to be a citizen of a polis? 40 Aristotle’s views on education 42 Social groups in a polis who are not recognized as citizens 45 Non-ideal political systems 51 Chapter 3 Connections between the Politics and the Ethics 57 Chapter 4 Difficulties in applying Aristotle’s theories to a modern setting 68 Conclusion Where do we go from here? 87 Bibliography 89 iv Acknowledgements First off, I have to thank God, as He helped me endure this project and gave me the courage to press on when I became frustrated, angry, and ready to quit.
    [Show full text]