Against Rigidity. an Investigation of the Semantics and Pragmatics Of

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Against Rigidity. an Investigation of the Semantics and Pragmatics Of Against Rigidity An investigation of the semantics and pragmatics of indexicality , by Mary Lou Grimberg Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of the University of London 1996 Department of Phonetics and Linguistics University College London ProQuest Number: 10017222 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. uest. ProQuest 10017222 Published by ProQuest LLC(2016). Copyright of the Dissertation is held by the Author. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 Abstract Saul Kripke, for whom the paradigmatic de jure rigid designator is the proper name, suggests that the link between such a name and its designatum is first established at an 'initial baptism' and that the link thus established is maintained by means of a 'causal chain'. One of the most significant properties claimed for such a designator is that its propositional meaning is exhausted by its referent. A second claim is the more mysterious one concerning the transworld identity of objects designated in this way. David Kaplan prefers to use the expression 'directly referential' to describe the semantic function of such terms. For him the paradigmatic directly referential term of natural language is the pronoun used indexically. He claims that such terms are also de jure rigid designators which contribute objects, not descriptions, to propositions. These two theses are closely associated, and it is against them both that I wish to argue as they give rise to a range of problems. In chapter one, some of the traditional philosophical problems are introduced. It is also suggested that there are additional, linguistic, reasons for believing the theses of rigid designation and direct reference to be mistaken. In chapter two certain problems arising from the assumption that indexically occurring pro-terms are directly referential are investigated in greater detail. In chapter three an alternative analysis of indexical reference, developed from Geoffrey Nunberg's model of indexicality, is presented. In chapter four the distinction between indexicality and deixis is investigated, and in chapter five I argue that the analysis of indexical interpretation developed in the previous chapters may be extended to include anaphoric reference also, thus providing a unitary semantic model for all the functions of pro-terms. Finally, the viability of this model is tested with respect to well-known problem utterances. The results of these tests are encouraging. Contents Abstract 2 Acknowledgements 8 Introduction. So. chapter one - Prologue on proper names 9 1. Introduction 9 2. The Millian perspective 9 3. The traditional problems 12 3.1 Frege's puzzle 12 3.2 Russell's puzzle 14 3.3 Kripke's puzzle 15 4. Kripke's'picture' 17 4.1 The causal chain 17 4.2 Possible worlds and rigidity 20 4.3 Individual identity 23 4.4 Descriptive names 29 4.4.1 Donnellan's objection 30 4.5 Further doubts concerning rigidity 32 5. Eponymy 32 5.1 Eponymie morphology 34 5.1.1 Semantic coherence 3 5 5.1.2 Morphological rules 36 6. Proper names, pronouns and indexicals 38 6.1 Lexicalisation 41 7. The meaning of proper names 43 8. Defining rigidity 47 8.1 Kripke's definition 47 8.2 Various views of rigidity 49 8.3 The problems 50 chapter two - A problem with stipulation 58 1. On stipulation 58 1.1 Non-overt stipulation 58 1.2 Modal stipulation 59 1.3 Lexical stipulation 59 2. Rigidity and direct reference 60 2.1 Defining rigidity without worlds 62 2.2 Defining direct reference 63 2.2.1 Recanati and Kaplan 63 2.3 Kripke and de jure rigidity 71 2.4 Kaplan and character 73 2.5 Summary 79 3. The ambiguity thesis 80 4. Challenging the ambiguity thesis 88 4.1 Distinguishing anaphora from deixis 88 4.2 Determining REF-values 91 4.2.1 Difficulties in determining REF-values 95 4.3 The agreement hierarchy 10 8 4.4 Summary 118 5. Testing the ambiguity thesis 119 chapter three - Deferred reference 124 1. Introduction 124 2. Meaning and indexicality 125 2.1 Indicative and descriptive meaning 126 2.2 Conditions of indexicality 128 2.3 Nunberg's challenge 129 3. An alternative model of indexical interpretation 130 3.1 Index 131 3.1.1 Kaplan and the logician’s account of an index 131 3.1.2 Indices and the contingent a priori 136 3.1.3 Nunberg and the Peircean index 137 3.1.4 Nunberg’s indexless indexicals 139 3.2 Deixis 140 3.2.1 Bühler’s approach 141 3.2.2 Nunberg’s approach 142 3.3 Deferred reference 143 3.3.1 Semantic types 144 3.3.1.1 Participant terms 144 3.3.1.2 Nonparticipant terms 145 3.3.2 The semantic complexity of indexical expressions 146 3.3.2.1 The deictic component 146 3.3.2.2 The classificatory component 146 3.3.2.3 Classificatory or deictic? 147 3.3.2.4 The relational component 150 3.4 The process of interpretation 153 3.4.1 The semantics of ’we' 158 3.4.2 The semantics of indexical self-reference 158 3.4.3 The relational component o f’we’ 162 3.4.4 The semantics of T 167 3.4.4.1 Who am I? 172 4. Objections and responses 176 4.1 Kaplan’s objection 177 4.1.1 Cross-sortal mismatches 179 4.2 Recanati’s objection 182 4.2.1 The semantics o f’tomorrow’ 182 4.2.2 The pragmatics o f’tomorrow’ 187 5. The status of GRC* 190 chapter four - Indexicality and deixis 192 1. Introduction 192 2. Contextual 192 2.1 Non-demonstrative'he' 193 2.1.1 Extended inferencing 204 2.2 Non-indicative terms 211 2.2.1 Indexicality and 'pure' deixis 216 2.2.2 Deixis 221 2.2.3 The truth-conditional involvement of the speaker 222 2.2.4 Deictic shift and deictic projection 235 2.3 Ago 237 3. The distinction between indexicality and deixis 240 4. Conclusion 244 chapter five - Anaphora 246 1. Extending Nunberg's model 246 1.1 Semantics or pragmatics 249 1.2 Indices and anaphora 252 2. Terminology in the extended model 258 3. Deixis and anaphora 266 3.1 Deixis in anaphora 266 3.2 The semantics of distality and proximality 271 3.3 Coincident and simultaneous functions 274 3.4 Anaphora or deixis? 277 3.5 Donkey anaphora and parametric variation 279 3.6 The anaphora-deixis continuum 280 4. Pragmatically controlled anaphora 281 4.1 Unheralded pronouns 285 5. Cornish's antecedent-trigger 286 6. Semantic solutions to syntactic problems 289 6.1 Paycheck sentences 290 6.2 Pronominal contradiction 292 6.3 Possessive quantifiers 294 7. Conclusion 296 Bibliography 299 Acknowledgements First of all, I must acknowledge my debt to my supervisor. Professor Neil Smith; he encouraged me to start, and with mulish obstinacy he insisted that I finish, and he bore the lengthening gap between these two poles with fortitude and good humour, although he did once remark that he thought I would complete my thesis in a geriatric ward. I think what worried him was the thought that he might be in a neighbouring ward, still waiting for chapter five. Well, it's complete now, and v^thout the benefit of Neil's extensive knowledge and wisdom I never would have made it. Above all, he made me laugh. Thanks Neil. I would also like to thank all the lecturers in the linguistics department, as each one has at some point been both supportive and encouraging. It really has been a privilege to be a part of this department. The philosophy department at UCL has also been helpful and welcoming. I am particularly indebted to Tim CraTLG and Michael Martin, both of whom gave their time generously to this wandering linguist, as did Gabriel Segal of the philosophy department at King's. I must also acknowledge my indebtedness to Saul Kripke, David Kaplan and François Recanati, whose writings inspired my research. My greatest debt in this respect, however, is to Geoffrey Nunberg, on whose theory of indexical reference my own thesis is based. At this point, I must add the usual disclaimer. None of the above-mentioned linguists or philosophers is to blame for any shortcomings in what follows. The mistakes are mine. Lastly, I must thank my family, some of whom have grown up while I have been working my passage to that geriatric ward. They have always encouraged me, and I'm grateful. Introduction As should be apparent from the title, the avowed aim of this thesis is to question the validity of the doctrine of rigid designation. The challenge, however, is of a limited nature. I do not question the claim that it is possible to construct formal languages with respect to which the free variables denote - as is required of rigid designators - the same entity across worlds or, as Kaplan might say, in all circumstances of evaluation. I do, however, question the ancillaiy claim that the free variables of logic may be analogised in the relevant respect to the pronouns, and other pro-terms, of natural language. Furthermore, although the problems which I associate with the thesis of rigid designation are introduced in the context of their relation to proper names, the subsequent argument is not pursued at this level.
Recommended publications
  • Download (4MB)
    : l The Semantics and Metaphysics of Rigid Designators by Parvaneh Ghazineghad A thesis submitted to the School of Graduate Studies In partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy Memorial University of Newfoundland June 2010 St.John's Newfoundland Abstract The aim of this research is to evaluate the relationship between Kripke' s semantical doctrines about proper names and his metaphysical doctrines about essence . Throughout Naming and Necessity, Kripke claims that his semantical doctrines have substantive metaphysical consequences. The assessment of this relationship is important, since the metaphysical consequences of semantics and vice versa are often regarded with suspicion. Semantics concerns the relationship between language and the world, and metaphysics is about the world itself. The claim that the way we picture the world imposes some constraints on the world i odd enough to deserve suspicion. My aim in thi work i try to how how the relationship between semantics and the metaphysics of essence can be explained by the concept of a rigid designator. ii TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION 5 I. RIGID DESIGN A TORS AND PROPER NAMES 1.1. Definition 8 1.2. Some Primary Remarks 10 1.3. Different Kinds of Rigid Designators 11 1.3.1. Strong and Weak Rigidity 11 1.3.2. De jure and de facto Rigidity 11 1.3.3. Obstinate and Persistent Rigidity 12 1.4. Rigidity and Proper Names 13 1.4.1. The basis of Kripke's Claim on the Rigidity of Proper Names 15 1.5. Intuitive Test for Rigidity 17 1.6.
    [Show full text]
  • DESIGNATION and IDENTITY* If an Object Can Be Identified in One Set Of
    DESIGNATION AND IDENTITY* MARIO F. DEL CARRIL Georgetown University Washington, D. C. If an object can be identified in one set of circumstances according to one criterion of identity, for example, spatio- temporal continuity, and it can be identified in another set of circumstances according to another criterion of identity, for example having the same parts in the same relative place, can a proper name that designates that object designate the same object in all possible worlds in which it designates? It has been suggested that this is not possihle," largue in this paper that this suggestion is wrong. Context sensitive criteria of identity do not generate hypothetical situ- ations that are incompatible with Saul Kripke's semantical account of proper names, However, the suggestion I am con- testing is based on an intuition as to how we would use proper names in hypothetical circumstances that involve dominant and recessive criteria of identity. I try to explain the basis of this intuition, and I also try to show why it should lead us to accept a "referential" or "quasidemostrative" account of some uses of a proper name. An account which is similar in some respects to Keith Donnellan's concept of a referential use of a definite description. I According to Kripke definite descriptions and proper names designate in different ways. In the case of definite descrip- • 1 am grateful to Howard Rolston for his helpful criticisms of this papero 1 Hugh S. Chandler, "Rigid Designation", The Iournal 01 Philo&ophy, No. 13, JuIy 1975. 57 tions truth conditions both establish and maintain the relation of designation," Not so in the case of proper names.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Rigid Designation Cannot Stand on Scientific Ground
    Why Rigid Designation Cannot Stand on Scientific Ground Erik Curiel ABSTRACT I do not think the notion of rigidity in designation can be correct, at least not in any way that can serve to ground a semantics that purports both to be fundamental in a semiotical sense and to respect the best science of the day. A careful examination of both the content and the character of our best scientific knowledge not only cannot support anything like what the notion of rigidity requires, but actually shows the notion to be, at bottom, incoherent. In particular, the scientific meaning of natural kind terms can be determined only within the context of a fixed scientific framework and not sub specie æternitatis. Along the way, I provide grounds for the rejection of essentialist views of the ontology of natural kinds, and discuss the dangers of the casual deployment of thought experiments in philosophy. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Rigidity 3 3 Water and H2O 4 3.1 What Is Water?.......................................4 3.2 What Is H2O?........................................6 4 Water Is Not H2O; H2O Is Not H2O 7 4.1 Twin Earth Is Not Possible................................8 4.2 An Embarrassment of Theories.............................. 11 4.3 Earth Is Silicates, Calcites, Carbonates and Nitrates.................. 15 4.4 A Place for Natural Kinds................................. 18 5 The Scientific Taha¯fut al-Fala¯sifa; Or, The Perfidy of Examples 19 1 Why Rigid Designation Cannot Stand Rationalists, wearing square hats, Think, in square rooms, Looking at the floor, looking at the ceiling. They confine themselves To right-angled triangles.
    [Show full text]
  • Rigidity and Direct Reference
    FRANCOIS RECANATI RIGIDITY AND DIRECT REFERENCE (Received in revised form 18 November, 1986) What is it for a singular term, or for a use of a singular term, to be referential in the strong sense, i.e. "purely" or "directly" referential? This is the question I will try to answer in this paper. The intuitive (and largely metaphorical) notion of referentiality that is current in the philosophical literature emerges from the following set of statements: A referential term is a term that serves simply to refer. It is devoid of descriptive content, in the sense at least that what it contributes to the proposition expressed by the sentence where it occurs is not a concept, but an object. Such a sentence is used to assert of the object referred to that it falls under the concept expressed by the predicate expression in the sentence. Proper names and demonstrative expressions are supposed to be referential in this sense; and although definite descriptions are not intrinsically referential, they have a referential use. That such a notion exists in contemporary philosophy is beyond question. But many philosophers do not like it. I suspect that there are two reasons why this is so. First, it is thought that the intuitive notion of referentiality is too vague and metaphorical to be of any use; and second, assuming that a definite view does emerge from the set of statements above, it is thought that there are serious objections to this view. I do not share this pessimism. I think that the notion of referen- tiality can be satisfactorily defined, and that the objections raised to the referentiality theory can be met.
    [Show full text]
  • Kripke's Naming and Necessity: Lecture II
    Kripke’s Naming and Necessity: Lecture II PHIL 83104 October 12, 2011 1. Varieties of descriptivism (end of Lecture I) ....................................................................1 2. Kripke’s arguments against descriptivism (71-90) ...........................................................2 2.1. The modal argument (48-49, 71-77) 2.1.1. Rigidified descriptions 2.1.2. Wide-scoping descriptions 2.2. The semantic argument (78-85) 2.3. The epistemic argument (86-87) 3. Kripke’s alternative picture of reference (91-97) ..............................................................5 4. Identity sentences and the necessary a posteriori (97-105) ..............................................7 4.1. The necessity of identity 4.2. A prioricity and qualitatively identical situations 4.3. Some sources of skepticism about Kripke’s claim 4.3.1. Contingent identities? 4.3.2. The illusion of contingency 4.3.3. Millianism about names 1. VARIETIES OF DESCRIPTIVISM (END OF LECTURE I) We’ve already seen two distinctions Kripke makes between different versions of descriptivism: • The distinction between descriptivist views which let a single description do the work, and those which rely on a cluster of descriptions • The distinctiopn between views according to which a description gives the meaning of a name, and those according to which it merely fixes the reference of the name Here Kripke introduces a third distinction: between circular and non-circular descriptivist views. This distinction is not like the others; it is less a distinction between varieties of descriptivism than a constraint on descriptivist views. What exactly is this constraint? Suppose we identified the meaning of the name “Aristotle” with the meaning of the description “the person called ‘Aristotle’” or “the referent of ‘Aristotle.’” These would be examples of descriptivist views which fail to meet the non-circularity condition, since to determine what object satisfies the description, we must first know which object is the referent of the name in question.
    [Show full text]
  • David Lewis's Place in Analytic Philosophy Scott Soames by The
    David Lewis’s Place in Analytic Philosophy Scott Soames By the early 1970s, and continuing through 2001, David Lewis and Saul Kripke had taken over W.V.O. Quine’s leadership in metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of language, and philosophical logic in the English-speaking world. Quine, in turn, had inherited his position in the early 1950s from Rudolf Carnap, who had been the leading logical positivist -- first in Europe, and, after 1935, in America. A renegade positivist himself, Quine eschewed apriority, necessity, and analyticity, while (for a time) adopting a holistic version of verificationism. Like Carnap, he placed philosophical logic and the philosophy of science at the center of philosophy. While not entirely avoiding metaphysics and epistemology, he tried to “naturalize” both. By contrast, Lewis and Kripke embraced the modalities Quine rejected.1 They also had no sympathy for his early verificationism, or his twin flights from intension and intention. As for philosophy of science, it was transforming itself into specialized philosophies of the several sciences, and did not lend itself to unified treatment. Although Lewis had deep interests in scientific issues, and was commendably realist about science in general, science itself was not the center of own distinctive approach to philosophy. Despite similarities in their opposition to Quine, the differences between Lewis and Kripke were large – especially in the semantics and metaphysics of modality. They also had different philosophical styles. Whereas Lewis was a wide-ranging thinker who pieced together a systematic philosophical world view, Kripke gave little thought to system, focusing instead on a few central topics. There is, therefore, no conflict between the two on many of the issues on which Kripke was silent.
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Philosophy Fall 2008 Tuesdays and Thursdays
    Philosophy 355: Contemporary Philosophy Hamilton College Fall 2008 Russell Marcus Tuesdays and Thursdays, 9am - 10:15am [email protected] Class 17 - Kripke and Intuitions I. Intuitions Descartes, famously, tried to ground all of our knowledge on indubitable foundations. His project ran adrift on the problem of circularity. The empiricist’s project of founding all of knowledge on direct apprehension of sense data faltered as well. It seems that there is no unassailable notion of direct experience. Alternatives to foundationalism, though, are all unsatisfying. Coherent theories may lack connections to reality. Inferences to the best explanation beg the question of whether our best explanations are any good. We seem led to a Humean, or worse, skepticism. But, skepticism misrepresents our undeniable ability to know lots of things. All arguments must start somewhere. Quine argues that we start with sensations, but that the theories we build out of them are not founded in these incorrigible sensations. We are like the sailor, adrift on the sea, repairing our ship. We stand in one place, to fix another. No one position is privileged, but we always have some place to start. As scientists, we start with observations, not unassailable apprehension of the external world, but fallible impingement of our sense organs. As philosophers, we often start with intuitions. The central questions at which we have been looking in the philosophy of mind are questions about possibility: Are zombies possible? Would the Chinese nation, or other homunculi-headed robots, have qualia? Is it possible to reduce mental states to neural states? The problem with arguments which rely on possibility is that they inevitably rely on our intuitions about what kinds of cases are possible, and what kinds of cases are not possible.
    [Show full text]
  • A Descriptivist Refutation of Kripke's Modal Argument and of Soames's
    bs_bs_banner THEORIA, 2012, 78, 225–260 doi:10.1111/j.1755-2567.2012.01136.x A Descriptivist Refutation of Kripke’s Modal Argument and of Soames’s Defencetheo_1136 225..260 by CHEN BO Peking University, China Abstract: This article systematically challenges Kripke’s modal argument and Soames’s defence of this argument by arguing that, just like descriptions, names can take narrow or wide scopes over modalities, and that there is a big difference between the wide scope reading and the narrow scope reading of a modal sentence with a name. Its final conclusions are that all of Kripke’s and Soames’s arguments are untenable due to some fallacies or mistakes; names are not “rigid designators”; if there were rigid designators, description(s) could be rigidified to refer fixedly to objects; so names cannot be distinguished in this way from the corresponding descriptions. A descriptivist account of names is still correct; and there is no justification for Kripke’s theory of rigid designation and its consequences. Keywords: modal argument, rigid designator, name, narrow scope, wide scope, rigid description, descriptivism, Kripke, Soames TO DEFEAT DESCRIPTIVISM about names, and to prove his own thesis that names are rigid designators, while most descriptions are non-rigid designators, Kripke con- structs three types of arguments: epistemic, semantic, and modal.1 Although these arguments seem to have been accepted by many philosophers as sound, I still have serious and systematic objections to them. In this article I will focus only on Kripke’s modal argument and Soames’s defence of that argument, developing some challenges and refutations, and reaching a negative conclusion: all of these arguments are untenable.2 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Proper Names As Traces
    The Magic of Reference: Proper Names as Traces HS “The Problem of Representation”, HS , Philipp Blum, November , The need for a metaphysical account of rigidity Emphasis on the question how cognitive significance is mediated by modes of presentation has made it appear mysterious how we can have genuine de re thought. What is it that allows us to reach out to an object, even in the absence of any descriptive information about it. Our answer should be clear: its name. It is its name that ties us to the object, through a chain of entia successiva from the original baptism to our use of it. Terminology: • names: whatever non-descriptive and non-syncategorematic words there are (if any) • reference: whatever relation holds between names and the world (if any) • referent: whatever stands in that relation on the world-side (things and pluralities thereof) • semantic value: that in virtue of which a world stands in the language-world relations it does • rigid designation: a reference relation that is modally invariant How do the non-syncategorematic words of our language relate to the world? • predicates (quantifiers? mass terms?): by describing it • names: by referring to it Suppose word X has semantic value Y. Two different questions, two different answers: • The predicate X has semantic value Y because Y effects the distinction X represents. Two degrees of arbitrarity: (i) Saussurean ‘arbitrarity of the sign’: another predicate Z =6 X could have been bestowed with semantic value Y; (ii) world-relativity: Y could have effected another distinction than it in fact does. • The name X has semantic value Y because Y is what X represents.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Kinds and the Identity of Property*
    Teorema Vol. XVII/1, 1998, pp. 00-00 Natural Kinds and the Identity of Property* Chang-Seong Hong RESUMEN El argumento de Kripke de la designación rígida de los términos de género natural es falaz porque no distingue los géneros naturales de las propiedades funcionales de se- gundo orden. Al aclarar los conceptos de género natural y de propiedad funcional pode- mos mostrar que si bien los términos de género natural designan sus referentes rígidamente, los términos de propiedad funcional no son designadores rígidos. Mis dis- cusiones de las propiedades funcionales ayudarán también a disipar la preocupación so- bre la existencia de supuestos casos de identidad contingente entre los enunciados teóricos de la ciencia. No hay ninguna identidad contingente, ni siquiera en la forma de la lógica de segundo orden: la identidad de propiedades es también una identidad nece- saria. El principio de la identidad necesaria gobierna sin interrupción. ABSTRACT Kripke’s argument for the rigid designation of natural kind terms is fallacious because he does not distinguish natural kinds from second-order functional properties; by clarifying the concepts of natural kind and functional property, we can show that natural kind terms do designate their referents rigidly, but that functional property terms are not rigid designators. My discussions of functional property will also help dispel the worry about the alleged cases of contingent identity with regard to theoreti- cal statements in science. There is no contingent identity even in the form of second- order logic: Property identity is also a necessary identity. The principle of necessary identity rules relentlessly. Natural kinds are by definition, roughly, naturally emerging kinds such as biological species, elements, and molecules.
    [Show full text]
  • Solving Frege's Substitution Puzzle: Analyzing It in Light of Descriptivism and Direct Reference Theory
    Acta Cogitata Volume 4 Article 6 Solving Frege’s Substitution Puzzle: Analyzing it in Light of Descriptivism and Direct Reference Theory Ayesha Rehman City College of New York Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.emich.edu/ac Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Rehman, Ayesha () "Solving Frege’s Substitution Puzzle: Analyzing it in Light of Descriptivism and Direct Reference Theory," Acta Cogitata: Vol. 4 , Article 6. Available at: http://commons.emich.edu/ac/vol4/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@EMU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Acta Cogitata by an authorized editor of DigitalCommons@EMU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Ayesha Rehman Analyzing Frege’s Substitution Puzzle Solving Frege’s Substitution Puzzle: Analyzing it in Light of Descriptivism and Direct Reference Theory Ayesha Rehman, City College of New York Abstract Although replacing one proper name with another that refers to the same person does not change the truth-value of a declarative statement, it affects the truth-value of propositional attitude reports, which are cognitive relations that people hold towards propositions. Frege’s Substitution Puzzle about propositional attitude reports essentially asks an important question: if two proper names co-refer in a certain linguistic community, then why does their intersubstitutability produce propositional attitude reports (that contain those proper names) with opposite truth-values? This paper attempts to explain how Description Theory of Names and Direct Reference Theory, two theories of proper names, solve Frege’s Substitution Puzzle. According to the Description Theory of Names, a proper name has both a sense and a reference.
    [Show full text]
  • Against the Necessity of Identity Statements
    Against the Necessity of Identity Statements Philip D. Miller Denison University n Naming and Necessity, Saul Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. For Kripke, a term "rigidly designates" an object if it picks out that object wherever it exists, in all I possible worlds. Additionally, to employ David Bostock's analysis, Kripke argues 1/ that identity-statements in which both terms are rigid designators are necessarily true if they are true at all" (313). Here Kripke has in mind statements of the sort /I a is b," in which the verb, is, has the character of identity (as opposed to predication, etc.), e.g. "a square is a parallelogram having four equal sides and four right angles." Kripke writes that philoso­ phers have been interested in identity statements of three sorts: those employing descriptions, identity statements between names, and theoretical statements in science. He contends that identity statements involving descriptions, e.g., "the first Post­ master General of the United States is the inventor of bifocals/' are contingent. Of names and theoretical statements in science, however, true identity statements of this sort are true necessarily so. Initially in this essay, I will provide an account of Kripke's claim regarding the necessity of identity statements. I will give a systematic analysis of the structure of Kripke's argument, facili­ tating an examination of the mechanics of the argument and my critique thereof. My criticism lies in the challenge to Kripke's intuitive claim that proper names are rigid designators, and that therefore the relation expressed in an identity statement between a name and the object it picks out is a necessmy one.
    [Show full text]