Journal of Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487

The expert Neandertal mind

Thomas Wynna*, Frederick L. Coolidgeb

a Department of Anthropology, University of Colorado, Colorado Springs, CO 80933-7150, USA b Department of Psychology, University of Colorado, Colorado Springs, CO 80933-7150, USA

Received 15 September 2003; accepted 31 January 2004

Abstract

Cognitive neuropsychology, cognitive anthropology, and cognitive are combined to yield a picture of Neandertal cognition in which expert performance via long-term working memory is the centerpiece of problem solving. This component of Neandertal cognition appears to have been modern in scope. However, Neandertals’ working memory capacity, which is the ability to hold a variety of information in active attention, may not have been as large as that of modern . This characteristic helps us understand features of the archaeological record, such as the rarity of innovation, and allows us to make empirically based speculations about Neandertal personality.  2004 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Neandertal; Long-term working memory; Expert performance; Levallois

Introduction formed the centerpiece of Neandertal problem solving. As a corollary, we further suggest that This article presents an attempt to describe modern human problem solving arose through an some of the components of Neandertal thinking, enhancement of working memory that enabled cognition, and personality. Our argument is innovative and experimental thinking. We will also grounded in established cognitive theory, both speculate about Neandertals’ personality charac- psychological and anthropological, and supported teristics based upon the archaeological record by direct archaeological evidence for structured and studies in cognitive psychology and clinical Neandertal activity, the Levallois reduction neuropsychology. strategy in particular. Our hypothesis is that Neandertals relied on a form of expert cognition Premises known as long-term working memory, that this ability was essentially modern in scope, and that it Our characterization of the Neandertal mind rests on four premises, each of which is argu- able. However, we believe that each is sufficiently * Corresponding author. Tel.: +1-719-262-3126; fax: +1-719- 262-3146 established to warrant what follows. E-mail addresses: [email protected] (T. Wynn), (1) Modern humans replaced Neandertals. By [email protected] (F.L. Coolidge). this we mean simply that after the arrival of

0047-2484/04/$ - see front matter  2004 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.jhevol.2004.01.005 468 T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of 46 (2004) 467–487 anatomically and behaviorally modern humans in 1996) argument for lack of cognitive fluidity, Europe, sometime after 50 Ka, Neandertals dis- Dennett’s (Dennett, 1991) argument for rolling appeared as a distinct population. There remains consciousness, and Donald’s (Donald, 1991) considerable disagreement in paleoanthropology argument for mythic culture. about how this replacement occurred, but there is (3) This cognitive difference cannot have been general consensus that the replacement did occur. dramatic. Here we agree with Hayden: (2) It appears necessary to posit a cognitive/ There may certainly have been some changes neurological difference between Neandertals and in mental capacity and composition from modern humans; superiority of or Neandertal to fully modern human forms (cor- culture cannot alone account for the success of responding to many excavators’ intuitive feeling modern humans. We derive this premise from that there is “something” intangibly different two seemingly inconsistent features of the paleo- about Neandertal behavior). However, at the anthropological record. First, at least in the initial level of biological capacities, these appear to be stages of contact (late and early very subtle; neither the relative change in brain ), modern and Neandertal technology size nor morphology indicates that this was a were not dramatically different. Both were based very significant change.. Neandertals may on stone , projectiles, fire, shelter, and so on; not have been quite capable of doing nuclear there were differences in style to be sure, but no physics or calculus; however, it is a travesty of qualitative difference in control of energy (e.g., no the available data to argue that they did not use of animal traction or other external power have the full complement of basic human source) or efficiency of technology (we maintain, faculties or act in recognizably modern fashions for example, that the significance of prismatic (Hayden, 1993: 137). technology has long been overstated). More- over, modern and Neandertal foraging were also Neandertals did compete on a par with ana- similar—hunting and gathering, including some tomically modern humans for thousands of years specialized hunting of single species (Marean and and may even have out-competed them for several Assefa, 1999; Grayson and Delpech, 2002; Steele, millennia in the Levant (Arsuaga, 2001; Shea, 2003). Superficially, at least, the two cultures do 2003). Had they possessed a dramatically less not appear to have been radically different; they powerful intelligence, this situation is unlikely to were both stone-age hunters and gatherers, have occurred. Comparisons of Neandertal and certainly no more distinct from one another than modern behavior have tended either to over- the most different modern cultures. This makes emphasize the differences (Binford, 1981) or over- the second of the paleoanthropological emphasize the similarities (d’Errico et al., 1998). A record a true puzzle: despite this overall cultural more appropriate solution is to posit a small similarity, Neandertals never truly acculturated. cognitive difference that had profound long-term Despite direct or indirect contact for thousands consequences. of years (Mellars, 1996), Neandertals never fully (4) Much modern thinking is still based on acquired the trappings of modern human culture abilities that evolved long ago. It is very unlikely (or vice versa). Such a pattern of coexistence for that the advent of modern humans was marked by millennia without acculturation does not fit easily a total reorganization of the brain; it is probable into anthropology’s understanding of culture pro- that much of modern thinking still consists of cess. It suggests that there must have been a more processes that evolved in earlier times. Many fundamental difference linked to Neandertal and modern human activities place minimal demands modern human capacities for culture, in other on problem solving ability (the overworked words, a cognitive difference. There have been driving-to-work example). More likely, the neural many attempts to characterize this cognitive differ- change leading to modernity was modest and ence, mostly based on global models of the mind. added to the abilities already possessed by pre- More recent examples include Mithen’s (Mithen, modern populations [e.g., Homo helmei in Africa T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 469

(McBrearty and Brooks, 2000) and Neandertals in The final piece that made minds modern Europe and western Asia]. If we can identify and peel away this final acquisition, we should be able In our recent work (Coolidge and Wynn, 2001; to describe the Neandertal mind itself. Wynn and Coolidge, 2003; Coolidge and Wynn, in press), we have proffered the following scenario as the final neuronal rearrangement that led to Methods modern thinking. This scenario is based on Baddeley and Hitch’s (1974) original concept of Because we do not have experimental access to working memory. As conceived of by Baddeley Neandertals we must draw on several indirect and Hitch, and recently modified by Baddeley and methods of enquiry. Logie (1999) and Baddeley (2001), working memory is a tripartite cognitive system consisting 1. Cognitive neuropsychology, in particular, of a central executive, primarily involved in main- studies of working memory and skilled cog- taining relevant attention and decision-making nition. This approach is based primarily on (the latter two processes are part of the executive classic controlled experimental scenarios in functions of the frontal lobes), and two slave which the targeted activities are narrowly systems, phonological storage or articulatory loop defined, subjects tested in controlled settings, for the maintenance of speech-based information and rigorous quantitative measures applied. and the visuospatial sketchpad, an interface for The subjects in these experiments either have visual and spatial information. We offered evi- documented brain dysfunction or damage, or dence from behavioral genetics for the highly may be normal and used to establish a clear heritable basis of the executive functions of work- reference population. Precise physiological ing memory and its slave systems and hypothesized assessment with neuroimaging techniques, that a relatively simple mutation in this system such as positron emission tomography (PET) may have produced fully modern thinking. We and functional magnetic resonance imaging further postulated that this mutation was either (fMRI) has recently aided greatly in the specific to phonological storage, and resulted in a neuronal localization of many neuropsycho- lengthened capacity to maintain speech sounds, or logical functions and other behaviors. was more generic and resulted in an enhancement 2. Cognitive anthropology, in particular, studies of the general capacity of the central executive. of the cognitive basis of technological activity. The latter might have included a greater ability to Cognitive anthropology differs from cognitive maintain attention despite competing but non- psychology in its emphasis on “real world” relevant stimuli. Because working memory has activities, and its use of participant observation been empirically shown to be strongly related to and ethnographic description. Despite meth- both general intelligence (Kyllonen, 1996) and odological differences, cognitive psychology native, fluid intelligence (Kane and Engle, 2002), and cognitive anthropology are not incompat- this mutation might have subsequently had a pro- ible, and in fact together provide a powerful found positive effect on the general reasoning approach to understanding the human mind. abilities of modern humans. We have labeled this 3. Cognitive archaeology, in particular the analy- effect “enhanced working memory” (EWM). We sis of stone manufacture using insights also reviewed archaeological evidence that sup- derived from (1) and (2). Cognitive archae- ports a relatively recent date for such a mutation. ology, as it is most successfully practiced, is a Even if it yielded only a slight selective advantage, form of processual archaeology (Nowell, 2001; such a mutation could have spread rapidly in Wynn, 2002) that relies on cognitive theories African populations, enabling the dramatic to interpret action sequences reconstructed spread of anatomically and behaviorally modern from the archaeological record itself and from humans after 50 Ka. There are at least two experimental replication. possible scenarios (Wynn and Coolidge, 2003). In 470 T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487

Table 1 Definitions of working memory terminology

Working memory refers to Baddeley’s model of cognition containing three major components: (1) a decision-making central executive, and two slaves systems; (2) the phonological loop; and (3) the visuospatial sketchpad.

Central executive is the decision-making component of working memory, the chief functions of which are attention to task, selective inhibition, and goal-direction.

Phonological loop consists of two components: (1) a short-term store for verbal and acoustic stimuli (hence the name “phonological store”) and (2) an articulatory (vocal or subvocal) rehearsal mechanism, which allows for the transfer to long-term memory by way of the hippocampus.

Visuospatial sketchpad is a temporary place of storage for the interface between visual and spatial information and allows for its manipulation and long-term storage. It is important for problems of spatial location and orientation.

Long-term working memory is a long-term storage that does not fade rapidly and generally takes more trials to establish than for verbal or declarative memories. It consists of skills (which we have labeled savoir faire) or the ability to replay motor behaviors, techniques, or procedures (hence the name “procedural memory”) such as . It also includes the declarative knowledge of those skills (which we labeled connaissance).

Enhanced working memory: we have postulated that the working memory of modern Homo sapiens was enhanced by a mutation approximately 50 to 100 Ka. Thus, possessed working memory but it did not have the same capacity of modern humans.

Working memory capacity is a general ability or domain-free capability to control attention and maintain relevant stimuli in the face of interference. It can be enhanced by any increases in capacity by its domain-specific components.

the first, this mutation accompanied the evolution the most famous neuropsychological case studies of anatomically modern humans sometime prior to involved a patient known as H.M. After a bilateral 150 Ka in Africa, where it then enabled the hippocampectomy (which essentially severed his gradual development of modern behavior [a ability to store any verbal long-term memories, scenario favored by, for example, McBrearty and leaving his procedural memory system intact), Brooks (2000)]. In the second, the mutation H.M. could “recall” old procedural skills and occurred after 100 Ka and produced behavioral transfer new ones to long-term procedural modernity in groups that were already anatomi- memory, but he could not verbally recall doing so cally modern. This scenario is favored by Klein (Milner et al., 1968). Experts are able to access and and others (e.g., Mithen, 1996; Klein and Edgar, also encode information very rapidly, but only in 2002; Klein, 2003). In either case, modern humans the narrow domain of their expertise. To explain with enhanced working memory entered Europe this ability, Ericsson and colleagues developed the sometime after 50 Ka, leading to the eventual concept of long-term working memory (henceforth demise of Neandertals (see Table 1 for definitions L-TWM) (Ericsson and Kintsch, 1995). One of the of terms associated with working memory). characteristics of classic working memory is rapid fade: unless actively maintained by repetition (rehearsal), information held in working memory The expert Neandertal mind fades very rapidly, and is lost in a matter of Long-term working memory seconds. If an experimental subject is distracted while performing a WM task, she cannot pick up Paradoxically, perhaps, one of the abilities that where she left off because the information is remain relatively intact when EWM capacity is gone. But Ericsson (Ericsson and Kintsch, 1995; removed is skilled, expert knowledge. One of Ericsson and Delaney, 1999; Ericsson et al., 2000) T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 471 found this not to be true for experts processing element here is the retrieval structure, but expert information in the areas of their expertise. Chess retrieval structures are not easily acquired. One masters, for example, are able to assess a chess acquires them through extensive practice and position very rapidly and, when the position is analysis. Ericsson, following the literature on removed from view, can return it to mind with skilled knowledge, suggests that ten years is a good virtually no loss of information, even when dis- estimate of the time necessary to achieve mastery- tracted. Musicians often demonstrate similar abili- level expertise in fields like chess or music (Mozart ties, as in the famous example of Mozart learning was fourteen at the time he copied the motet and a complete motet on one hearing (Gutman, 1999). had been composing since he was four). The This ability is domain-specific; it is not a general resulting retrieval structure can assess a huge range memory ability, but a very specialized ability of situations very rapidly because of the breadth its linked to the information of one area of expertise. retrieval cues. The result is, somewhat counter- Because it does not fade, the information must intuitively, a powerful and flexible kind of think- somehow be entered rapidly into long-term ing. But it is limited to a narrow domain. The memory, a process that usually takes many rep- retrieval structure of a chess master is useless in etitions, or a longer time in attention (about 10 playing Go, or even checkers, and indeed is only seconds) than short-term memory. Most long-term slightly better than average at remembering chess memory is also less reliable than short-term boards on which pieces have been placed ran- memory, yet the reliability of expert memory rivals domly. L-TWM is not inherently innovative; it can that of short-term memory. Here, then, is a form rapidly assess and respond to a huge range of of memory that is fast, reliable, and does not fade, familiar situations and problems, but is not adept but is very narrowly focused. It is clearly an at creating truly novel responses because the important cognitive process for everyday activity retrieval structure and cues are stable, linked and, indeed, appears to underpin our most elements of long-term memory itself. impressive feats of cognitive power. Neuroimaging studies appear to corroborate Ericsson and colleagues have proposed a model Ericsson’s model. In fMRI studies of chess playing for L-TWM that can account for an expert’s and Go playing, Atherton et al. (2003a,b) found ability to encode information into, and retrieve that the areas of cortex normally activated in information from, LTM very rapidly. The model is working memory, the dorsolateral prefrontal cor- based on retrieval cues and retrieval structures. A tex in particular, are minimally activated (though, cue is an item of knowledge (a “chunk” in memory interestingly, more for Go than for chess). Instead, terms) that is linked by association to a longer a more diffuse activation pattern is present, as one encoding [Ericsson suggests that the cue “rein- would expect from activation of long-term states the conditions of encoding” (Ericsson and memory. Kintsch, 1995)]. A retrieval structure is a set of While Ericsson emphasizes the performance of retrieval cues that the expert creates over time and experts, this kind of thinking is not confined to a which is relatively stable. Using chess as an few accomplished individuals. It is a style of think- example, when a chess master sees a chess position, ing employed by everyone in their own areas of his or her chess retrieval structure rapidly encodes experience and expertise; it is simply most easily the positions into LTM using retrieval cues recognized and studied in exceptional individuals. (for example, the cue “Sicilian defense” allows Ericsson’s model of L-TWM is, in fact, very simi- immediate encoding of the relative position of lar to accounts of technical thinking provided by thirty two pieces); he or she does not need to cognitive anthropologists. Even though Ericsson encode the specific board location of each piece. emphasizes the role of semantic cues in L-TWM, Later, if the board is removed, or if it is a blind there is no reason that cues cannot also be images, chess demonstration, the master accesses the or even “muscle memories,” which are relatively encoded information using the same cues (for precise patterns of muscle action learned by example, “Game #2 is Sicilian defense”). The key multiple repetition that can be deployed without 472 T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 conscious direction (e.g., a fencing parry). This is and Keller, 1996: 90). This umbrella plan may especially clear from a characterization of black- contain semantic knowledge-names of materials, smithing provided by Keller and Keller (1996). estimates of time, costs, etc., but it is also made up of visual, tactile, and aural images. The plan is Technical cognition executed using constellations, which are “. con- figurations of ideas implements, and materials .” The most important similarity between (Keller and Keller, 1996: p. 91), that enable the Ericsson’s model of L-TWM and technical cog- completion of one step in the process. A constel- nition lies at the behavioral level. The technical lation is not simply a mental image; it includes, expert learns his or her craft in the same way that and indeed is constituted through, the actual tools all experts learn—by observation, analysis, and and materials. The visual, kinesthetic, and aural practice. The ten-year term cited by Ericsson as a features of the tools and materials structure the norm for acquiring expert knowledge is essentially nature of each particular step in a procedure as the same as is necessary to develop from appren- much as any semantically declarative knowledge. tice to master in any craft. Superficially, at least, all There is active feedback between the actions of the expertise appears to share this learning curve. But smith and his or her constellation until the step is do craft experts rely on retrieval cues and retrieval completed or, if it fails, is begun anew with a structures? This is a harder question to answer revised constellation. In common procedures, and requires comparison of two rather different these constellations may become recipes that are approaches to cognition—the experimentally deployed with little active reflection, though the based studies of cognitive psychology and the mutually constituting roles of tools, materials, and ethnographic and participant-based studies of cog- procedures still operate. nitive anthropology. The experimental approach is Even with this superficial presentation of the good at isolating and investigating specific cog- Kellers’ account, it is possible to identify simi- nitive components and producing replicable larities with Ericsson’s account of expert perform- results. The ethnographic approach is good at ance. First, the stock of knowledge is clearly describing the richness and complexity of real- content held in LTM. Much of this knowledge world tasks. The methods are different but, as we consists of procedural memories as as hope to show, the results are comparable. declarative knowledge. It is much richer in content The Kellers’ (Keller and Keller, 1996) study of than the narrow domains usually tapped in exper- blacksmithing emphasizes a phenomenological/ imental studies of LTM, especially in the import- action theory approach to understanding cog- ance of non-semantic information in the guise of nition, and the clarity of its presentation allows visual and kinesthetic images, but there is no reinterpretation in light of some of the narrower reason to suppose that it is stored differently. concepts of cognitive psychology. In characterizing Umbrella plans would appear to be constructed the cognitive life-world of the smith, the Kellers using retrieval structures. The task at hand calls up introduce three useful concepts—stock of knowl- the appropriate retrieval structure, held in LTM, edge, umbrella plan, and constellation. The stock which contains retrieval cues that tap into associ- of knowledge consists of the pool of information ated knowledge. What is different about an acquired by the smith during years of practice. umbrella plan is that the retrieval structure Although it includes semantic information, it con- includes many non-semantic cues. Constellations sists primarily of visual, tactile, and aural images are retrieval structures linked dynamically to tools of results, materials, and procedures. When a and materials. Here the two-way role of retrieval smith begins a task he or she first conceives an structures is apparent. Not only do the cues access umbrella plan, which is “. the smith’s mental appropriate images and procedures, they enable representation of an ultimate goal for production rapid encoding of new information in LTM, add- and his associated general overview of the step-by- ing to the smith’s stock knowledge. Short-term step procedures required to attain an end” (Keller working memory is also engaged in constellations. T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 473

A constellation deployed by L-TWM does not Boeda’s (Boeda, 1994) reconceptualization of exhaust the attention capacity of working memory, Levallois being landmark contributions. This especially during routine tasks that have become reorientation is based largely on two methods. The recipes. The free attention capacity can be used to first documents sequences through careful analysis innovate, plan ahead, or, more dangerously, day- of artifacts, cores, , and experimental dream. The retrieval cues themselves often consist replication (Boeda, 1994, 1995; Chazan, 1997). of image associations: “A glance at a tool may The second documents sequences through refitting trigger an idea for production” (Keller and Keller, cores (Van Peer, 1992, 1995; Schlanger, 1996; 1996: 94). Such non-semantic retrieval cues are Chazan, 1997). The two approaches have suc- essential elements of all technical activity, but are ceeded in providing a detailed description of no different than the semantic cues emphasized by sequences of action required in the production of Ericsson (indeed, we suspect that many of the cues MP artifacts. These descriptions are sufficiently used by chess masters may also be visual images). detailed and comprehensive to stand in place of Ericsson and colleagues have stressed the study prehistoric actors in a cognitive analysis. To put it of experts because extraordinary performance another way, it is very unlikely that prehistoric both calls out for understanding and, because of knappers used sequences of action that have not the saliency of expert activity, permits ease of been identified. study. But clearly L-TWM is not a cognition Levallois is the most informative of the MP possessed only by an accomplished few. As the reduction techniques. We do not, of course, intend work of the Kellers exemplifies, it is a style of to equate Levallois with Neandertals. Its first thinking that is deployed in many human activi- appearance in the archaeological record, for ties; indeed, we contend that it is the style of example, antedates the appearance of Neandertals. thinking that is most commonly used in everyday Moreover, comparable reduction techniques were tasks. That some have achieved mastery levels of used by anatomically modern humans in Africa skill reflects the years of concentrated practice and the Near East. However, Neandertals did use necessary to acquire a stock of knowledge, includ- Levallois and its variants for thousands of years, ing an array of relevant retrieval structures for and it remains the best described example of successful completion of a huge array of potential sequentially organized action in the Neandertal tasks. record. We believe that Neandertals regularly employed Levallois is a technical process or reduction L-TWM that was as effective as any documented procedure, not a tool type (Van Peer, 1992; Boeda, for modern humans. The evidence lies in the 1995; Chazan, 1997). It is a general procedure in archaeological record, primarily in the reconstruc- which a core is prepared for the ultimate removal tion of skilled performance in reduction of one or several flake blanks, which then may or procedures. may not be further modified. The procedure pro- duces a variety of preparatory, intermediate, Levallois reduction and final products that document a complex sequence of actions. “The repetitive pattern of Over the last twenty years palaeolithic archae- Levallois surface preparation evidences a desire for ologists have moved away from an emphasis on standardized morphological control of a limited stone tool typologies, which focuses on tools as number of blanks” (Van Peer, 1995: 4). These products, to an emphasis on the entire use-life blanks are “determined” in the sense that a of stone artifacts—from initial raw material sequence of actions, the chaine operatoire, con- acquisition and distribution to discard. Middle strains the final product. It is not, however, necess- Palaeolithic (MP) assemblages have played per- ary that the knapper have an image, a “mental haps the key role in this reorientation, with template,” of the final blank (Schlanger, 1996; Dibble’s critique of typology and demonstrations Chazan, 1997). In general, there are three basic of MP reduction sequences (Dibble, 1987), and steps in the procedure. The first prepares a core 474 T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 with two distinct but related surfaces, one, a more ultimately, produce a finished product. At this convex platform surface that will include the strik- purely descriptive, qualitative level of comparison, ing platform, and a second flatter production there is no obvious distinction between the two surface from which the blank or blanks will be activities, especially if we compare Levallois reduc- removed. The second step prepares the striking tion to the “recipe” procedures of blacksmithing platform itself in relation to the axis of the (procedures used in often-performed tasks). But intended blank. The third step is the removal, by are the cognitive underpinnings the same, that is, hard hammer, of the blank or blanks. The first two did Neandertal stone knappers have stocks of steps each encompasses its own sequence of action, knowledge, make umbrella plans, and use constel- as does the final step if multiple blanks are lations? We can only answer these questions by removed. Levallois is not a single, invariant using modern knappers as surrogates. Given procedure. There are two basic varieties— the descriptive similarity between Levallois and “preferential” for the removal of a single final modern technical activity this strikes us justifiable, blank and “recurrent” for the removal of two if not ideal. We have already seen that a technical or more final blanks (Boeda, 1995). Recurrent analysis of Levallois, based on experimental knap- Levallois itself has many variants—unidirectional, ping and refitting, identifies two components to bi-directional, and even centripetal (Chazan, cognition, connaissance and savoir faire. Both are 1997), and each requires a different approach to clearly components of the knapper’s stock of core and platform preparation. “The crucial point, knowledge, with former being the declarative- which has been demonstrated repeatedly through component and the latter being the skilled pro- experimentation, is that the configuration of the cedural and motor component. Equally clearly, two faces must suit the specific recurrent method both are acquired through extended periods of employed” (Chazan, 1997: 726). Cores can be, and practice. It is apparent that much of this knowl- were, reused by preparing the platform and pro- edge must be held in the form of visual, tactile, and duction faces anew, and striking off a second even aural images concerning raw material, knap- blank, or second set of blanks. This invariably ping qualities, edge angles, angles and force of requires an adjustment of technique because the delivery, and so on. Most palaeolithic archae- mass of the core has been much reduced. ologists, for example, understand at least some of The complexity of the task, and the compre- the declarative knowledge necessary to produce hensiveness of the accounts, invites a cognitive a Levallois flake, but very few are capable of interpretation. In a sense, some archaeologists actually doing it because they lack the necessary have already taken this approach in describing two non-declarative knowledge and skill. The con- major components of the knapper’s mind: naissance and savoir faire of Levallois knappers connaissance, which is the knowledge held by the clearly constitutes a stock of knowledge that one knapper, and savoir faire, which is the motor skill acquires with years of practice. This stock of required for performance (Boeda, 1995; Chazan, knowledge includes a large range of alternative 1997). It is also possible to articulate the accounts procedures—recurrent bi-directional, preferential, of Levallois with cognitive anthropology and cog- etc. nitive psychology. The Kellers’ concepts of stock Experimental archaeologists and refitters have of knowledge, umbrella plan, and constellation not explicitly identified cognitive components can be directly applied. directly comparable to umbrella plans and constel- The sequence of actions that can be recon- lations, but their accounts suggest that these inter- structed for Levallois reduction resembles the pretive concepts are appropriate. Boeda (1995: 46), sequence of action documented by the Kellers for for example, refers to the “volumetric conception blacksmithing: a sequential task with definable of the core” in the guise of “two assymetrical steps during which the artisan makes choices [sic] convex secant surfaces.” Baumler (1995) among a variety of specific techniques and pro- distinguishes between strategy and sequence. cedures in order to complete each step and, “Reduction strategy refers to the goal(s) of the T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 475 knapper, while sequence or sequences more form preparation, re-preparation, and so on). narrowly represent the method of achieving goals” Second, the dynamic nature of Levallois reduction (p. 17), and “. From beginning to end, the suggests not just constellations, but the retrieval reduction of a core is characterized by adjustments structures on which they are based. Modern knap- to changing parameters—some predictable, others pers change their strategy based on changing con- less so, and some not at all” (p. 17). The awkward- ditions, and it is clear that prehistoric knappers did ness of the wording attests to the non-semantic as well. “The data presented here, based on the nature of this conception. This visual image would complete sample of cores and the entire series of appear to orient each step of the process; it is, in both Levallois and non-Levallois flakes, clearly essence, the key feature to an umbrella plan devel- indicate that flaking patterns did indeed change oped by the knapper prior to beginning each step. as a function of the degree of core reduction” The analog to constellations lies in the actual (Dibble, 1995: 102). More specifically, we suggest execution, which incorporates raw material, avail- that the “volumetric conception of the core,” as able hammers, muscle tensions, visual and aural described by Boeda and Chazan, is itself a retrieval images, and the feedback from the process itself. In structure. It consists of an interrelated set of cues sum, Levallois reduction, at least as performed by that call up much larger encodings of the Levallois modern knappers, fits easily into the Kellers’ procedure that are held in long term memory. The model of technical cognition. More importantly, cues include the various convexities of the plat- there is no valid reason to believe that Neandertals form and production surfaces, edge angle at the performed Levallois reduction differently; in other , orientation of ridges that direct words, their technical cognition appears to have the force, and so on. The larger encodings held in been the same as that of modern humans. long term memory include a huge array of infor- Levallois reduction also fits the criteria for mation learned in previous knapping episodes (and expert performance and results from the deploy- encoded through the retrieval structure), some of ment of Ericsson’s L-TWM. The connaissance and which is declarative knowledge, but most of which savoir faire of knappers are clearly information consist of images (visual, tactile, and aural), motor stored in long term memory. That much of this procedures and the muscle tensions tied to skilled information is non-semantic simply corroborates activity. the importance of visual, tactile, and aural imagery The validity of applying L-TWM retrieval in technical expertise. That modern archaeological structures to prehistoric examples of Levallois is studies do not identify a specific cognitive structure corroborated by Schlanger’s (1996) masterful or style that can be equated with retrieval cues and analysis of a refitted core from Maastricht– retrieval structures is not a surprise. Ericsson’s Belvedere (a MP site in the Netherlands dating to research and that of Boeda and van Peer do not OIS 7). In reducing the core, the knapper produced overlap in terms of specific theory, concepts, or nine Levallois flakes in seven distinct phases. citation universe. There are, nevertheless, good Toward the beginning of each phase the knapper reasons for concluding that Levallois reduction identified a particular configuration of the pro- employed retrieval cues and retrieval structures. duction surface to act as the distal convexity First, one learns knapping in the same manner as (opposite the future striking platform), and then one learns every task—by experience and analysis. trimmed the lateral convexities and the platform Levallois is one of the more difficult techniques to itself. In three of the phases he or she employed learn, and mastery emerges only after years of a “preferential” strategy, and in three other, a practice. From Ericsson’s perspective, a knapper “recurrent” strategy. For each phase he or she had must acquire a large suite of retrieval cues organ- to modify the plan to adjust to the ever shrinking ized into retrieval structures appropriate to a huge size of the core. This account fits nicely into the variety of specific circumstances (raw material, Kellers’ concepts of umbrella plan, in this case nodule shape and size, imperfections, results of the overall approach to the core, and constella- preforming, results of face preparation and plat- tions, in the execution of each phase. Flexibility is 476 T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 apparent in the ease of shifting from preferential to L-TWM stocks of knowledge in varying circum- recurrent and back again. But most telling of all, stances would yield varying products. Moreover, the knapper clearly used the “distal convexity” expert retrieval structures take time to as a cue to call up an appropriate retrieval struc- learn—years, in fact—providing ample oppor- ture that was then used to guide subsequent prep- tunity for minor intergenerational drift in tech- arations of the core. As we saw with blacksmith- niques. Major changes would be rare, and occur ing, this reliance on the retrieval structures of long only through serendipitous discovery (e.g., a major term working memory is characteristic of expert blunder with a fortuitously good result) or the performance. From this perspective Neandertal arrival of new that could be copied expert technical cognition is indistinguishable from (see below). L-TWM is also consonant with that of modern humans. Gamble’s (1999) more audacious argument This account of Neandertal expert cognition that Neandertals acted in “landscapes of habit.” bears on, but certainly does not resolve, several According to Gamble (1999), a Neandertal lived long standing problems in MP research. It adds out his or her life on a geographic scale with a most usefully to our understanding of variability radius of perhaps only 20–30 km, with occasional and innovation. It has long been recognized that ventures of longer distance. “Within the regional European MP assemblages varied in terms of scale represented here by the landscape of habit relative percentages of individual types, and measured by raw-material transfers, the effec- relative predominance of knapping techniques, tive networks of individuals structure the degree to and in the presence and absence of certain which social life was extended [i.e., no large scale diagnostic types (e.g., handaxes or backed pieces). social groups]. I therefore conclude that life was The degree of variability within the European still very local and usually immediate” (p. 242). MP appears to have been greater than that Such a scale could easily be organized and recognized for earlier periods, but not as great exploited through retrieval structures built on very as that recognized for the late Upper Palaeolithic specific cues in the local environment. Neandertals [the apparently intrusive early Upper Palaeolithic would truly have been experts of their local Aurignacian was, initially at least, less variable domain, so much so that new arrivals would be than the local Middle Palaeolithic (Kozlowski hard pressed to compete. But Neandertals would 2000)]. Archaeologists have interpreted this varia- have had a more difficult time coping with large, bility in a variety of ways: Bordes (1968) argued interregional spaces, and would be seriously handi- for ethnic differences, Binford (1973) for func- capped for any task requiring long range planning tional differences, Mellars (1969, 1973) for chrono- (spatially and temporally). logical differences, and Dibble (1987) for A technology based solely on L-TWM would differences in reduction sequences, resharpening, not be innovative, if by innovative we mean exper- and the use-life of tools. Our current account of imentation with new forms and techniques. The expert cognition fits best into recent interpret- question of creativity is a contentious one in ations by Mellars (1996) and Gamble (1999). discussions of human evolution, but here we Mellars argues that most of MP variability can side with Mithen (1996, 1998). Even though be understood as resulting from relative social Neandertals’ technology did vary and change, it isolation and technological drift. This is precisely did so on a scale and at a rate that would appear to what one would expect of a technology based rule out conscious experimentation and creativity. entirely on expertise. Because knapping retrieval These are, we contend, the stuff of enhanced structures are stable but flexible strategies of pro- working memory. The reason Keller’s blacksmith- duction, they can adjust to changing circumstances ing is not identical to Neandertal knapping is such as availability of raw material (size, quality, that EWM provides freed-up attention capacity. ease of access) or the demands of specific tasks Especially when L-TWM has converted umbrella (butchering freshly killed bison as opposed to plans to recipes, the smith has processing capacity scraping reindeer hides). Simple deployment of the available to make unique comparisons, think T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 477 further ahead, or daydream. One result of this is intelligence and working memory capacity because innovation. We have no reason to conclude that these tasks do not generally employ distraction. Neandertals ever did this. L-TWM worked well for They postulate that maintenance of attention in them and provided sufficient flexibility to solve all the presence of interference is the critical control of their immediate problems. But their day-to-day function of working memory capacity. Kane and life consisted of recipes and an endless “drive to Engle used various working memory tasks on work.” normally functioning participants and divided Our discussion has focused on Neandertals them into two extreme groups, those with the because they are known to have used the Levallois highest working memory spans and those with the technique, and are otherwise the best known pre- lowest working memory spans. They found that modern hominid. They were certainly not alone in that the lowest span participants were more sus- demonstrating reliance on expert performance. ceptible to long-term memory interference, includ- Other late hominids used Levallois and ing retroactive and proactive interference. If other prepared core techniques of equal com- Neandertals did have restricted working memory plexity. Our characterization of Neandertal cog- capacities, then they would have had greater diffi- nition applies to these hominids as well. One culty in solving a new task because of prior habits group of these, perhaps McBrearty and Brooks’ of thought. Kane and Engle have also demon- (McBrearty and Brooks, 2000) Homo helmei, strated that lower capacity participants also have a eventually gave rise to anatomically and behav- much greater vulnerability to outside interference, iorally modern humans with enhanced working particularly when there is competition between the memory. new task goal and old habitual responses. For Neandertals, this might have meant they had more Neuropsychology difficulty changing their ways of manufacturing tools after 200,000 years of sameness, given their There is some interesting evidence from neuro- skilled-cognitions, especially motor skills, which psychological studies of normally functioning often require many more trials to master than do adults who have naturally restricted work- verbal skills. With EWM, modern humans may ing memory that corroborates this picture of have had a distinct advantage defending against Neandertal cognition. Kane and Engle (2002) have the interference from habitual responses, both investigated the role of the prefrontal cortex in verbal and motor. Kane et al. (2001) have also working memory, its executive functions, and their demonstrated this same vulnerability to interfer- relationship to intelligence from an individual- ence of low capacity participants to attention- differences perspective. They first established, capturing visual tasks. Conway et al. (2001) have through numerous empirical studies of evidence, found similar results in verbal acoustic-attention the important role that the prefrontal cortex plays tasks. Those participants with lower fluid intelli- in both working memory and executive functions, gence had similar failed goal maintenance in the especially their overlapping roles in attention to presence of interference as those participants with relevant tasks. They view this focused attention lower working memory capacity (e.g., Duncan as a central feature of the prefrontal cortex and et al., 1996), further supporting the link between note that a critical aspect is the maintenance of working memory capacity and fluid intelligence. attention in spite of competing but irrelevant In summary, there is some neuropsychological stimuli. Interestingly, as previously noted, working basis for thinking that Neandertals may have had memory capacity has been shown to be strongly trouble adjusting to novel conditions, particularly correlated to both general intelligence and fluid those that might have required new ways of behav- intelligence (e.g., Kyllonen, 1996; Kane and Engle, ing outside the range of their individual expert 2002). Kane and Engle also argue that typical abilities. short-term memory tasks (verbal memory of In sum, psychological, anthropological, archae- lists of words) are not correlated as well with ological, and neuropsychological evidence come 478 T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 together in a way that allows us to draw a picture structures when applied to familiar problems, of Neandertal cognition. Neandertals regularly that Neandertals could learn prismatic core tech- employed an expert cognition fully as effective as niques by applying retrieval cues and structures that used by modern humans. Such expert cog- developed over a lifetime of stone knapping. But nition was very effective and flexible, and able to for Chatelperronian blades, the Neandertals used deal with all of the problems of Neandertal life, large, thick flakes or small blocks for cores, and much as it deals with most of the problems in our removed the blade along a prepared crest (d’Errico everyday life. What was missing from Neandertal et al., 1998: S 13). This is unlike true prismatic core cognition was the enhancement of working technique, and a bit like Levallois in its emphasis memory that enabled regular innovation and on prepared surfaces, which is precisely what one experimentation. would expect if Neandertals invented their own technique, i.e., emulated the goal of blade produc- tion. Given the sophistication of Levallois retrieval The Chatelperronian structures, examination of a blade from a pris- matic core would have been sufficient to generate a This model of Neandertal cognition also helps problem solution. Such cues as ridge orientation, us understand the nature of information trans- convexities, striking platform, and so on, would fer evident in Chatelperronian assemblages.1 have called up possible solutions from long-term Traditionally the modern elements found in the memory. Minimal trial and error would have soon Chatelperronian have inspired interpretations of produced the solution we see in the archaeological imitation or independent invention (d’Errico et al., record. Similar goal emulation could have pro- 1998). Imitation advocates appear only to mean duced all of the modern elements we see in “learned from” rather than any of the more Chatelperronian culture without the necessity of detailed definitions available from the comparative invoking instruction or direct observation of the literature, where imitation requires copying at least procedure. In other words, it is not necessary that part of a specific motor sequence (Tomasello et al., Neandertals ever directly observed modern human 1987; Whiten and Ham, 1992; Tomasello, 1994). knapping; they could have reconstructed a pro- The nature of Chatelperronian stone tools, and the cedure by observing the debitage alone. Indeed, apparent expertise of Neandertal stone knappers, the nature of Chatelperronian knapping suggests actually suggests that Neandertals acquired that Neandertals rarely, if ever, directly observed a modern features through “emulation.” This is modern human knapping. Given the sophistication a form of observational learning in which the of their own knapping abilities and retrieval struc- subject understands the goal but invents his or tures, they almost certainly would have been able her own procedure for achieving it. For the to reproduce prismatic core techniques as precisely Chatelperronian this is most apparent from the as if they had actually observed the procedure. We technique of blade production. There can be little present these arguments in more detail elsewhere doubt, given the flexibility inherent in retrieval (Coolidge and Wynn, in press).

1 We are fully aware of the controversy concerning the chronology, stratigraphy, taphonomy, and typology of Neandertal personality Chatelperronian and early Aurignacian assemblages in western Europe (Mellars, 1996, 1999; d’Errico et al., 1998; d’Errico, 2003; Zilhao and d’Errico, 1999; Conard and Bolus, 2003). Our There is no widely accepted definition of the interpretation presumes some temporal overlap between Nean- term “personality” in psychology; indeed some dertal and modern human populations, and in this sense comes personality textbooks eschew a single definition down on the side of acculturation rather than independent entirely. It has often been defined globally as the development. Indeed, given what we have been able to recon- struct about Neandertal cognition, independent development of sum total of a person’s behavior, and it has also the Chatelperronian over such a brief period strikes us as been defined eclectically vis-a`-vis a specific psycho- unlikely. logical theory, e.g., Freudian psychoanalytic T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 479 theory (Larsen and Buss, 2002). Nonetheless, some cose behavior a less attractive causal hypothesis of its accepted attributes are a set of traits, pro- and dangerous hunting strategies a more likely cesses, or mechanisms that are relatively enduring one. They concluded that Neandertals probably and influence social and environmental inter- killed their quarry from close range. The actions. Tattersall (2002) has recently pronounced were almost certainly thrust, not thrown. Success “We have no idea what the Neandertals were like in such an endeavor relies, ultimately, on personal temperamentally: whether they were aggressive or expertise—knowledge of animal behavior, timing retiring; cooperative or individualistic; forthright of the rush, placement of thrusts, pursuit of or sneaky; trusting or suspicious; crude or lovable; wounded animals, deception of other members of or like our own species, all of the above. For all a herd, etc. This kind of hunting is truly dangerous that we know about Neandertals from the impress- and, even for modern hunters, requires skills ive record they left behind, we are still unable to learned over years. But unlike modern hunters, form a psychological profile of these hominids that Neandertals appear to have been largely opportun- might help us to divine how they might have istic. Neandertals hunted what was available and interacted with this new element [Cro-Magnons] almost certainly could be selective when appropri- on the landscape.” (pp. 129–130). But is our ate (Gaudzinski and Roebroeks, 2000; but see also knowledge of Neandertal personality this bleak? Munson and Marean, 2003). They were very effec- Does it actually require divine intervention, or tive hunters, indeed good enough to flourish in a does the archaeological record and neuropsycho- relatively hostile European glacial environment, logical theory offer us a basis for speculation? We but they do not appear to have “tweaked” the think the latter, and shall briefly review the system by developing closely scheduled seasonal pros and cons of the archaeological evidence of systems, altering the landscape, or developing stor- Neandertal subsistence strategies, archaeological age and remote capture systems (Wynn and evidence for symbolism, anthropological evi- Coolidge, 2003). In addition to the pattern of dence for language, and ground our hypotheses traumatic bone injury, Trinkaus (1995) found high accordingly. levels of general wear-and-tear, and degenerative Neandertal hunting has long been a topic of bone disease, but he found not a single case of a debate and disagreement. Binford’s extreme argu- healed lower limb injury that would have pre- ment (Binford, 1989) that Neandertals were obli- vented mobility. This led him to suspect that the gate scavengers has given way to a more eclectic maintenance of locomotion was an absolute picture in which Neandertals employed a variety of necessity in daily life and those who hunting techniques. d’Errico (2003) reviews evi- were not mobile were left behind. All of this dence that Neandertals were clearly expert hunters is entirely consistent with the model Neandertal of a wide range of large mammals, including cognition presented above; long-term working dangerous species, and concludes that once the memory could provide a flexible and effective set zooarchaeological evidence has been carefully of hunting techniques that would work in a wide examined “. little remains to distinguish the variety of specific circumstances. Psychological subsistence strategies of Neandertals and anatomi- traits that may be inferred from these, particularly cally modern humans” (p. 5). However, evidence the hunting of more dangerous species, might from bone trauma suggests that Neandertals include bravery, low levels of harm avoidance, and may not have been quite as modern as d’Errico perhaps greater difficulties in making cost-benefit envisions. analyses. Thus, a kind of stoicism may have been Berger and Trinkaus (1995) found similar post- the norm among Neandertals. From a contem- cranial trauma patterns between Neandertals and porary social perspective, one might be tempted to rodeo athletes, with high levels of head and neck add cruelty, although current psychological think- injuries, as well as high frequencies of shoulder and ing might require amusement as a motivation for arm injuries. Neandertals’ low population densities the cruelty, or cruelty for the sake of dominance appear to make interpersonal violence and belli- establishment. 480 T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487

Symbolic capacity and language three Herto skulls from Ethiopia, which date to between 160 to 154 Ka, White and his colleagues Reconstruction of many aspects of Neandertal found evidence of post-mortem defleshing and mental life hinges on an understanding of symbol polishing. These are skulls of anatomically modern use and language. Below we treat them separately. humans. It is impossible, of course, to identify Symbol use in general has long been linked to specific symbolic meanings to such actions, but frontal lobe function (e.g., Luria, 1966). While nothing like it has so far been identified for symbolic reference, per se, probably does not Neandertals. depend on working memory, the use of symbols Evidence for Neandertal art is meager. They did certainly would. Symbols are tokens that can be use ochre and other mineral (d’Errico held in attention, and manipulated by working et al., 2003), and did produce enigmatic non- memory, so any enhancement of working memory figurative engravings on bones (Bednarik, 2003). would provide greater capacity for the deployment There is nothing, however, that approaches the of symbols. If Neandertals and modern humans artistic performances of European Upper Palaeo- did differ in their working memory capacity, we lithic artists. Lewis-Williams (2002) sees the would expect there to have been some difference in demands of two-dimensional art as requiring their use of symbols. Despite serious methodologi- much greater cognitive ability than Neandertals cal problems, linked largely to taphonomic pro- were likely to have possessed. For Lewis-Williams, cesses, the archaeological record for mortuary the representational pictures of cave art, along treatment and art appears to support this scenario. with highly ritualized burials and carvings, implied By 30,000 years ago, modern human burial that modern humans had a hierarchical, or at least included features unknown for Neandertals. One differentiated, society that was not simply based on of the best examples is from Sungir in Russia, age, sex, or physical strength. The bulk of this which dates to about 32,000 to 30,000 (White, evidence also leads Lewis-Williams to speculate 1993). This site contained the remains of a young that Neandertals had a different form of con- boy covered with strands of beads, 4903 in total. sciousness from modern humans and that their He wore a cap of beads with fox teeth attached. mental imagery may have been more closely tied to His belt contained over 250 polar fox canine teeth, their skilled motor cognition. which required a minimum of 63 hunted or The archaeological record for symbolic behav- trapped fox to produce it. In his grave, there was ior is controversial, to say the least [see the recent also a carved mammoth ivory pendant and a review by d’Errico et al. (2003)]. We are not carved ivory disc. Beside him was also a mammoth suggesting that Neandertals lacked symbolic ivory lance, much too large and heavy to have ability, only that the archaeological evidence for been a practical hunting weapon. An adjacent symbol use among Neandertals is far less extensive grave contained the body of a young girl with 5247 than it is for modern humans. This is in keeping beads and other objects (but curiously, no fox with our hypothesis that the difference lay in the teeth). White (1993) has estimated the time to capacity of working memory. fashion the beads might have required over 3500 Because our model of Neandertal mental life hours. At Qafzeh in Israel a burial of a modern relies on a relatively lower capacity for working human dating to between 90 and 110 Ka memory, we must consider the potential effects of (Schwarcz et al., 1988) includes personal orna- this on language. The relatively minor genetic ments [perforated and color-stained shells mutation we have proposed may have increased (d’Errico et al., 2003)]. Such burials stand in stark the length of phonological storage of modern contrast to Neandertal burials, where there are human working memory, and this enhancement in few, if any, convincing examples of . phonological store may have had a significant White et al. (2003) have recently documented a impact on language. Modern neuropsychological much earlier example of probable mortuary (or at assessment methods typically measure phonologi- least post-mortem) treatment of corpses. On the cal storage by the Digit Span subtest of the T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 481

Wechsler Adult Intelligence Scale (e.g., Lezak, working memory would not necessarily benefit 1995). The Digit Span subtest requires participants from memories of the past, stored in long-term to repeat increasingly long strings of numbers memory. So how would phonological storage forwards and then backwards. Interestingly, this aid the prediction of the future? Baddeley (2001) subtest usually produces the lowest correlation proposed that working memory would allow for with IQ among all other subtests (although it does the reflection of multiple past experiences. This correlate strongly), and it is thought to be a better might allow the individual to actively choose a measure of attention than of IQ. If modern future action or create an alternative action, rather humans benefited from a mutation-based increase than simply choosing the path of most probable in phonological storage, then the neural cognitive success. Although an individual would still be architectural differences need not have been better off (compared to one without benefit of past much different from that of Neandertals. In experience) choosing alternatives simply based on fact, they could have been nearly identical. Phono- the past, Baddeley proposed that working memory logical storage, as Baddeley and Logie (1999) would allow for the formulation of mental models have recently proposed, may be the bottleneck of future behavior. Shepard (1997) described a of language comprehension and production. similar working-memory and long-term memory Increased phonological storage may have allowed dichotomy. He postulated that natural selection modern humans greater articulatory rehearsal, favored a perceptual and representational system allowing for better long-term storage, greater self- able to provide implicit knowledge of the pervasive reflection, and the beginnings of introspection and and enduring properties of the environment self-reflection. Greater phonological storage would (long-term memory) and that natural selection also have allowed increases in syntactical complexity. favored a heightened degree of voluntary access to Sentences could be longer and contain more infor- this representational system (working memory). mation, and they could also be imbued with more This access, he proposed, facilitated the accurate meaning through syntactical embedding. A greater mental simulation of varying actions, allowing the phonological store might also permit greater evaluation of the success or failure of these actions morphemological richness. While the native ability without taking a physical risk. Shepard thought to produce different morphemes might not have that the mere accumulation of facts (as in been directly affected, the ability to hold and Baddeley’s semantic memory or Mithen’s natural maintain new and various morphemes might have history intelligence or technical intelligence) would been enhanced by an increase in phonological not result in advances in scientific human knowl- storage. edge but its advancement would require “thought The increase in phonological storage might also experiments.” He also postulated that every have increased the pragmatics of speech, including real experiment might have been preceded by an enhancement of modes of speech. For example, thought experiments (which we think is directed simple declarative sentences could now con- by working memory) that increased the prob- tain more information. Commands (imperative ability of the success of the real experiment. mode) could become more complex. Questions Dawkins (1989) also proposed that natural selec- (interrogative mode) could contain more specific tion would have favored the reproductive success information as well, and the results might have of those organisms capable of simulation. He been greater efficiency, clarity, and more effective described systems highly similar to those of communication. executive functions and replete with the executive The creation and enhancement of the subjunc- functions metaphor. For example, he viewed con- tive mode of speech [Klein and Edgar’s (2002) sciousness as the culmination of an evolutionary “what if” statements] or the greater development trend in which consciousness served as executive of the future tense in language due to an increase decision-makers with the acquired “ability to pre- in phonological storage requires particular atten- dict the future and act accordingly” (Dawkins, tion. In part, because of its highly transient nature, 1989: 59). 482 T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487

Sugiyama (2001) has recently argued that Back to personality narratives, folklore, or story-telling (all of which may be clearly categorized as episodic memories) So what does a lack of EWM, and an abbrevi- may have been selected because they are an ated phonological store, mean for Neandertals’ efficient and safe means of transferring infor- personality? First and probably foremost, we mation. Verbal representations are substitutes for think that there might have been dramatic time-consuming and sometimes dangerous first- language differences between modern humans and hand experience. She posits that fitness in varying Neandertals. We contend that EWM enabled a habitats may have particularly aided foraging cognitively different form of culture, as epitomized knowledge by transmitting information about by the highly ritualized burials such as Sungir and geography, plants, fauna, weather, and other ornate parietal art, with its implications for the aspects. We surmise that increased phonological presence of sophisticated and extensive symbol- storage would serve to create and store more based systems of thought. If we are correct, then elaborate stories (which thus contain greater infor- the language of Neandertals may have been prag- mation), and serve as a better and larger “stage” matically restricted to declarative, imperative, and for their recall from long-term memory. Arsuaga exclamatory modes of speech. Interrogative speech (2001) has further postulated that Neandertals was probably more limited, and we hypothesize may not have had the myth-making and story- subjunctive speech may have been non-existent telling abilities possessed by modern humans, and or severely limited, as was the use of the future that the latter’s enhanced abilities kept them in tense. In this regard, modern humans would better contact with their natural world, their peers have seemed loquacious, while Neandertals might (local and distant), and their ancestors. have appeared more laconic. Story-telling and An increase in phonological storage could have narratives used by modern humans might have also aided in cross-modal thinking. Hermer and been as ornate as present-day story-telling, while colleagues (Hermer and Spelke, 1996; Hermer- Neandertal stories might have been simpler and Vasquez et al., 1999) found that, in both children less inventive (e.g., Arsuaga, 2001). and adults, success in a cross-modal task requires If we could look back in time, would we have the conjoint use of spatial vocabulary with non- seen Neandertals laugh less? Mithen (1996) is geometric information in a single thought or alone in addressing the issue of Neandertal humor, memory (e.g., “it’s to the right of the blue one”), and he proposes a less humorous Neandertal. He and it is not dependent on IQ, age, or vocabulary bases his speculation on the presumed lack of size. As a whole, the findings support Carruthers’s integration between the natural history intelligence (2002) contention that language serves as the and social intelligence of Neandertals. This lack of vehicle of inter-modular thinking, and we contend cognitive fluidity, he postulates, would have put that increased phonological storage allowed Neandertal at a disadvantage when attempting to language to “load up” additional information in a appreciate appropriate incongruities, one import- single spoken or subvocalized thought that gave ant aspect of some types of humor. There are, of modern humans their ultimate selective advantage course, other types of humor, and there is no over Neandertals. We believe the scenario would reason to suspect that Neandertals would not find be the same if this minor genetic mutation was some aspects of physical humor funny (e.g., much not specific to phonological storage but actually of the sort we call slapstick), particularly if enhanced general working memory capacity, the situation was appropriate. We speculate that which is our speculation as to the nature of the Neandertal humor, given the hypothesized lack of genetic mutation. We believe the greater sophisti- EWM and a restriction in linguistic comprehen- cation in behavior resulting from increased phono- sion and production, might lack an appreciation logical storage would have been the same had the for language-based humor, including plays-on- mutation involved an increase in working memory words and puns. Given that the archaeological capacity. record gives us a picture of the hardness and T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 483 difficulties of daily living in Neandertal culture, and Cummings, 1999; Goldberg, 2001; Stuss et al., might Neandertal humor have had an element of 2001). cruelty or might it have been devoid of humor Again, there is danger is extrapolating from completely? neuropsychological studies of frontal lobe brain- The only neuropsychological basis for the latter damaged patients to normally functioning ones. speculation is a dangerous one: case studies of However, these studies do give some basis for patients with frontal lobe dysfunction and inter- reasoned speculation; we need not conclude that ruptions of executive functions and working there is no basis whatsoever for postulating differ- memory. The danger in the use of such studies lies ences between Neandertals and other humans. in assuming the behavioral sequelae of brain dam- Many of the personality traits listed previously age are the same as the sequelae of restricted may result from impairment of working memory, working memory. With this caveat in mind, frontal which is, after all, a well-established frontal lobe lobe-impaired patients (e.g., Levin et al., 1991) are function. Many are in fact consistent with the generally reported as humorless or laugh inappro- model of Neandertal cognition presented earlier in priately. Other symptoms include apathy, dis- this paper, i.e., heavy reliance on long-term inhibition, and emotional dysregulation. They working-memory, with little or no excess capacity usually lack initiative, creativity, and spontaneity. for creativity and innovation. In the current state They most often speak only when spoken to. Their of understanding in neuropsychology, we cannot speech is sparse and frequently confined to simple be more specific. However, the evidence is suf- declarative and imperative modes rather than the ficient to conclude that Neandertal personality, subjunctive. They often neglect personal hygiene while obviously perfectly normal for Neandertals, and become unwashed and unkempt. They have would have been very different from that of a narrow interests and do not engage in former typical modern human. hobbies, nor do they take up new hobbies or interests. They have a high tolerance for boredom. They are often seen as inflexible, preferring to stick Conclusions to old habits and ways. Their families perceive them as easily angered or irritated. They are not The preceding analysis has combined concepts typically guilt-ridden or overly anxious. They show and methods of three disciplines to draw a sketch little or no grief. More often than not, frontal lobe of Neandertal cognition. We do not pretend that patients frequently lose interest in sex, although this is a comprehensive picture; such a feat is there are rare instances of hypersexuality. They are probably impossible. However, we believe that we often immodest and crude. They are not overly have made a strong case for Neandertals’ reliance wily and crafty. Their methods for getting what on a long-term working memory capability that they want are more likely to be blunt and overt. was essentially modern in scope. This ability is They show little joy and have little empathy (show- most apparent in the technical domain of stone ing reduced or absent ability to understand the knapping, but is also consistent with other perspectives of others). In the more strict defini- archaeologically documented activities includ- tions of executive functions, frontal lobe patients ing effective hunting. We also believe that are usually indecisive, show poor planning abili- Neandertals’ low levels of innovation and ties, and are disorganized when it comes to goal creativity attest to a lower capacity of working attainment. They have great difficulty with memory. We do not suggest that Neandertals had abstractions and metaphors. Innovation and no working memory, only that its capacity was creativity are completely absent. Finally, they lower, either in terms of a smaller phonological often fail to complete tasks despite the ability to do store, or a reduced attention capacity. This cog- so (e.g., Luria, 1966; Lezak, 1982; Levin et al., nitive profile has also allowed us to speculate 1991; Mega and Cummings, 1994; Lezak 1995; about associated personality characteristics, Coolidge et al., 1996; Coolidge et al., 1998; Miller including stoicism, tolerance for boredom, low 484 T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 levels of harm avoidance, and difficulties in cost a second green-up of grass (Lewis, 1982); or evi- benefit judgments. Reliance on long-term working dence for rapid, directional change in technology memory clearly provided a very successful adap- that results from conscious invention and exper- tation; L-TWM is a very flexible form of cognition imentation; or evidence of long range social net- that can respond appropriately to a huge range of works. Any of these would be outside the scope of new, but familiar situations. It is important to expertise based on L-TWM, and would constitute re-emphasize that most of what modern humans strong evidence against our hypothesis. do is based on L-TWM. The enhanced working Finally, this model of Neandertal cognition memory that appears to have accompanied the provides a basis for speculating about what went evolution of modern humans enabled much higher before. Given the diffuse neurological storage of levels of innovation, thought experiment, and long-term memories, one simple prediction is that narrative complexity. In the long run, these yielded earlier hominids with a smaller neocortex and a way of life that ultimately led to the demise of smaller association cortices would have had a Neandertals. reduced LTM capacity. One result would be a From this model of Neandertal cognition it is long-term working memory capable of storing possible to generate certain predictions or expec- fewer and less sophisticated retrieval structures. tations about the paleoanthropological record. This alone would result in less flexibility in expert Even though the model is far from comprehensive, performance; technology, for example, would be it does allow identification of patterns that would less finely tuned to local circumstances. It is also be consistent with Neandertal cognition, and pat- likely that smaller cortices would be associated terns that would be inconsistent. It also permits with smaller working memory capacities than that speculation about the evolutionary antecedents of of Neandertals, with attendant consequences for Neandertal cognition. complexity of plans of action. The Neandertal paleoanthropological record should regularly demonstrate certain characteris- tics. The first is technical mastery and sophisti- References cation. Neandertals would have been fully capable of learning and mastering any basic stone-age Arsuaga, J.L., 2001. The Neandertal’s Necklace. Four Walls technology, including prismatic core technique Eight Windows, New York. (indeed, it is quite possible that their level of Atherton, M., Zhuang, J., Bart, W.M., Hu, X., He, S., 2003a. A functional MRI study of highlevel cognition. I. The game of technical expertise could learn any modern techno- chess. Cognitive Brain Research 16, 26–31. logical activity). Second, Neandertals should dem- Atherton, M., Zhuang, J., Bart, W.M., Hu, X., He, S., 2003b. A onstrate effective long term adaptations to local functional MRI study of highlevel cognition. II. The game environments that included flexibility in the face of GO. Cognitive Brain Research 16, 32–37. of shifting conditions. Third, variability in Baddeley, A.D., 2001. Is working memory still working? American Psychologist 11, 851–864. Neandertal material culture should map onto Baddeley, A.D., Hitch, G.J., 1974. Working memory. In: variations in local conditions. Fourth, there should Bower, G.A. (Ed.), Recent Advances in Learning and be only a limited amount of technical variability Motivation. Academic Press, New York, pp. 47–90. attributable to drift, i.e., small non-directional Baddeley, A.D., Logie, R.H., 1999. Working memory: the changes in technique resulting from small errors in multiple-component model. In: Miyake, A., Shah, P. (Eds.), Models of Working Memory: Mechanisms of Active intergenerational transmission of technical know Maintenance and Executive Control. Cambridge University how. Press, New York, pp. 28–61. On the other hand, the Neandertal paleoanthro- Baumler, M.F., 1995. Principles and properties of lithic core pological record should not yield evidence of reduction: implications for Levallois technology. In: Dibble, certain other activities. For example, there should H.L., Bar Yosef, O. (Eds.), The Definition and Interpretation of Levallois Technology. Press, be no evidence for long range contingency plan- Madison, pp. 3–19. ning, such as that practiced by native Australians Bednarik, R.G., 2003. The earliest evidence for palaeoart. Rock in scheduled burning of specific areas to encourage Art Research 20, 3–28. T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 485

Berger, T.D., Trinkaus, E., 1995. Patterns of trauma among the cal review of the evidence and its interpretation. Curr. Neandertals. J. Archaeol. Sci. 22, 841–852. Anthrop. 39(Special issue), s1–s44. Binford, L.R., 1973. Interassemblage variability—the d’Errico, F., Henshilwood, C., Lawson, G., Vanhaeren, M., Mousterian and the “functional” argument. In: Renfrew, C. Tillier, A.-M., Soressi, M., Bresson, F., Nowell, A., (Ed.), The Explanation of Culture Change. Duckworth, Lakarra, J., Backwell, L., Julien, M., 2003. Archaeological London, pp. 227–254. evidence for the emeregence of language, symbolism, and Binford, L.R., 1981. Bones: Ancient Men and Modern Myth. music—an alternative multidisciplinary perspective. J. Academic Press, New York. World Prehist. 17, 1–70. Binford, L., 1989. Isolating the transition to cultural adap- Dibble, H.L., 1987. The interpretation of Middle tations: an organizational approach. In: Trinkaus, E. (Ed.), morphology. Am. Antiq. 52, 109–117. The Emergence of Modern Humans: Biocultural Dibble, H.L., 1995. Biache-Saint-Vaast, Level II: a comparison Adaptations in the Later Pleistocene. Cambridge University of approaches. In: Dibble, H.L., Bar-Yosef, O. (Eds.), The Press, Cambridge, pp. 18–41. Definition and Interpretation of Levallois Technology. Boeda, E., 1994. Le Concept Levallois: Variabilite des Prehistory Press, Madison, pp. 93–116. Methodes. CNRS Editions, Paris. Donald, M., 1991. Origins of the Modern Mind: Three Stages Boeda, E., 1995. Levallois: a volumetric construction, methods, in the Evolution of Culture and Cognition. Harvard a technique. In: Dibble, H.L., Bar-Yosef, O. (Eds.), The University Press, Cambridge. Definition and Interpretation of Levallois Technology. Duncan, J., Emslie, H., Williams, P., Johnson, R., Freer, C., Prehistory Press, Madison. 1996. Intelligence and the frontal lobe: the organization of Bordes, F., 1968. The Old . Weidenfeld and goal-directed behavior. Cognitive Psychology 30, 257–303. Nicholson, London. Ericsson, K., Delaney, P., 1999. Long-term working memory as Carruthers, P., 2002. The cognitive functions of language. an alternative to capacity models of working memory in Behav. Brain Sci. 25, 657–726. everyday skilled performance. In: Miyake, A., Shah, P. Chazan, M., 1997. Redefining Levallois. J. Hum. Evol. 33, (Eds.), Models of Working Memory: Mechanisms of Active 719–735. Maintenance and Executive Control. Cambridge University Conard, N.J., Bolus, M., 2003. Radiocarbon dating the appear- Press, Cambridge, pp. 257–297. ance of the modern humans and timing of cultural innova- Ericsson, K.A., Kintsch, W., 1995. Long-term working tions in Europe: new results and new challenges. J. Hum. memory. Psychological Review 102, 211–245. Evol. 44, 331–371. Ericsson, K.A., Patel, V., Kintsch, W., 2000. How experts’ Conway, A.R.A., Cowan, N., Bunting, M.F., 2001. The cock- adaptations to representative task demands account for the tail party phenomenon revisited: the importance of working expertise effect in memory recall: comment on Vicente and memory capacity. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 8, Wang (1998). Psychological Review 107, 578–592. 331–335. Gamble, C., 1999. The Palaeolithic Societies of Europe. Coolidge, F.L., Merwin, M.M., Nathan, J.H., Schmidt, M.M., Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. 1996. Assessment of neurobehavioural symptoms after Gaudzinski, S., Roebroeks, W., 2000. Adults only. Reindeer traumatic brain injury. Indian Journal of Psychological hunting at the Middle Palaeolithic site Salzgitter Issues 4, 1–9. Lebenstedt, northern Germany. J. Hum. Evol. 38, 497–521. Coolidge, F.L., Mull, C.E., Becker, L.A., Stewart, S.E., Segal, Goldberg, E., 2001. The Executive Brain: Frontal Lobes and D.L., 1998. Hyperawareness of neuropsychological deficits the Civilized Mind. Oxford University Press, New York. in patients with mild closed head injuries: a preliminary Grayson, D.K., Delpech, F., 2002. Specialized early Upper investigation. International Journal of Rehabilitation and Palaeolithic hunters in southwestern France. J. Archaeol. Health 4, 193–198. Sci. 29, 1439–1449. Coolidge, F.L., Wynn, T., 2001. Executive functions of the Gutman, R.W., 1999. Mozart: A Cultural Biography. Brace frontal lobes and the evolutionary ascendancy of Homo and Harcourt Co, New York. sapiens. Cambridge Archaeol. J. 11, 255–260. Hayden, B., 1993. The cultural capacities of Neandertals: a Coolidge, F.L., Wynn, T., in press. A cognitive and neuropsy- review and re-evaluation. J. Hum. Evol. 24, 113–146. chological perspective on the Chatelperronian puzzle. J. Hermer, L., Spelke, E., 1996. Modularity and development: the Anthrop. Res. case of spatial reorientation. Cognition 61, 195–232. Dawkins, R., 1989. The Selfish Gene. Oxford University Press, Hermer-Vasquez, L., Spelke, E., Katsnelson, A., 1999. Sources New York. of flexibility in human cognition: dual-task studies of space Dennett, D., 1991. Consciousness Explained. Little, Brown and and language. Cognitive Psychology 39, 3–36. Company, New York. Kane, M.J., Bleckley, M.K., Conway, A.R.A., Engle, R.W., d’Errico, F., 2003. The invisible frontier: a multiple species 2001. A controlled-attention view of working-memory model for the origin of . Evol. capacity. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 130, Anthrop. 12, 188–202. 169–183. d’Errico, F., Zilhao, J., Julien, M., Baffier, D., Pelegrin, J., Kane, M.J., Engle, R.W., 2002. The role of prefrontal cortex in 1998. Neandertal acculturation in Western Europe? A criti- working-memory capacity, executive attention, and general 486 T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487

fluid intelligence: an individual-differences perspective. Mellars, P., 1999. The Neanderthal problem continued. Curr. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 9, 637–671. Anthrop. 40, 341–365. Keller, C., Keller, J., 1996. Cognition and Tool Use: The Miller, B.L., Cummings, J.L., 1999. The Human Frontal Blacksmith at Work. Cambridge University Press, Lobes: Functions and Disorders. The Guilford Press, New Cambridge. York. Klein, R., 2003. Whither Neandertals?. Science 299, 1525–1527. Milner, B., Corkin, S., Teuber, H., 1968. Further analysis of the Klein, R.G., Edgar, B., 2002. The Dawn of Human Culture. hippocampal amnesic syndrome: 14-year follow-up study of John Wiley and Sons, New York. H. M. Neuropsychologia 6, 215–234. Kozlowski, J., 2000. The problem of cultural continuity Mithen, S., 1996. The Prehistory of Mind. Thames and between the Middle and the in central and Hudson, London. eastern Europe. In: Bar-Yosef, O., Pilbeam, D. (Eds.), The Mithen, S., 1998. A creative explosion? Theory of mind, Geography of Neandertals and Modern Humans in Europe language, and the disembodied mind of the Upper and the Greater Mediterranean. Peabody Museum, Palaeolithic. In: Mithen, S. (Ed.), Creativity in Human Cambridge, pp. 77–105. Evolution and Prehistory. Routledge, London, pp. 165–191. Kyllonen, P.C., 1996. Is working memory capacity Spearman’s Munson, P., Marean, C., 2003. Adults only? A reconsideration g? In: Dennis, I., Tapsfield, P. (Eds.), Human Abilities: of Middle Paleolithic ‘prime dominated’ reindeer hunting at Their Nature and Measurement. Lawrence Erlbaum Salzgitter Lebenstedt. J. Hum. Evol. 44, 262–273. Associates, Mahwah, NJ, pp. 49–75. Nowell, A., 2001. In the Mind’s Eye: Multidisciplinary Larsen, R.J., Buss, D.M., 2002. Personality Psychology: Approaches to the Evolution of Human Cognition. Domains of Knowledge about Human Nature. International Monographs in Prehistory, Ann Arbor. McGraw-Hill, New York. Schlanger, N., 1996. Understanding Levallois: Levin, H.S., Eisenberg, H.M., Benton, A.L. (Eds.), 1991. and cognitive archaeology. Cambridge Archaeol. J. 6, Frontal Lobe Function and Dysfunction. Oxford University 231–254. Press, New York. Schwarcz, H., Grun, R., Vandermeersch, B., Bar-Yosef, O., Lewis, H., 1982. Fire technology and resource management in Valladas, H., Tchernov, E., 1988. ESR dates for the homi- aboriginal North America and Australia. In: Williams, N., nid burial site of Qafzeh in Israel. J. Hum. Evol. 17, Hunn, E. (Eds.), Resource Managers: North American and 733–737. Australian Hunter-gatherers. American Association for the Shea, J.J., 2003. Neandertals, competition, and the origin of Advancement of Science, Washington, pp. 45–68. modern human behavior. Evol. Anthrop. 12, 173–187. Lewis-Williams, D., 2002. The Mind in the Cave: Conscious- Shepard, R.N., 1997. The genetic basis of human scientific ness and the Origins of Art. Thames and Hudson, New knowledge. In: Bock, G.R., Cardew, G. (Eds.), Character- York. izing Human Psychological Adaptations. Wiley and Sons, Lezak, M.D., 1982. The problem of assessing executive Chichester, MA, pp. 4–13. functions. International Journal of Psychology 17, 281–297. Steele, T., 2003. Red deer hunting by Middle and Upper Lezak, M.D., 1995. Neuropsychological Assessment, third ed. Paleolithic hominids from western Europe. Paper presented Oxford University Press, New York. at annual meeting of the Paleoanthropology Society, Luria, A.R., 1966. Higher Cortical Function in Man. Basic Tempe, AZ. Books, New York. Stuss, D., Gallup, G., Alexander, M., 2001. The frontal lobes Marean, C., Assefa, Z., 1999. Zooarcheological evidence for are necessary for ‘theory of mind’. Brain 124, 279–286. the faunal exploitation behavior of Neandertals and early Sugiyama, M.S., 2001. Food, foragers, and folklore: the role of modern humans. Evol. Anthrop. 8, 22–37. narrative in human subsistence. Evolution and Human McBrearty, A., Brooks, A., 2000. The revolution that wasn’t: a Behavior 22, 221–240. new interpretation of the origin of modern human behavior. Tattersall, I., 2002. The Monkey in the : Essays on the J. Hum. Evol. 39, 453–563. Science of What Makes us Human. Harcourt, New York. Mega, M.S., Cummings, J.L., 1994. Frontal-subcortical and Tomasello, M., 1994. The question of chimpanzee culture. In: neuropsychiatric disorders. Journal of Neuropsychiatry and Wrangham, R.W., McGrew, W.C., de Waal, F.B.M., Clinical Neurosciences 6, 358–370. Heltne, P.G. (Eds.), Chimpanzee Cultures. Harvard Mellars, P.A., 1969. The chronology of Mousterian industries University Press, Cambridge, pp. 301–317. in the Perigord region of southwest France. Proc. Prehist. Tomasello, M., Davis-Dasilva, M., Camak, L., Bard, K., 1987. Soc. 35, 171–234. Observational learning of tooluse by young chimpanzees. Mellars, P.A., 1973. The character of the Middle-Upper Hum. Evol. 2, 175–183. Palaeolithic transition in south-west France. In: Renfrew, Trinkaus, E., 1995. Neandertal mortality patterns. J. Archaeol. C. (Ed.), The Explanation of Culture Change. Duckworth, Sci. 22, 121–142. London, pp. 255–276. Van Peer, P., 1992. The Levallois Reduction Strategy. Mellars, P.A., 1996. The Neandertal Legacy: An Archaeologi- Prehistory Press, Madison. cal Perspective from Western Europe. Princeton University Van Peer, P., 1995. Current issues in the Levallois problem. In: Press, Princeton. Dibble, H.L., Bar-Yosef, O. (Eds.), The Definition and T. Wynn, F. Coolidge / Journal of Human Evolution 46 (2004) 467–487 487

Interpretation of Levallois Technology. Prehistory Press, research. In: Slater, P., Rosenblatt, J., Beer, J., Milinski, M. Madison, pp. 1–9. (Eds.), Advances in the Study of Behavior. 21. Academic White, R., 1993. Technological and social dimensions of Press, New York, pp. 239–283. ‘Aurignacian-age’ body ornaments across Europe. In: Wynn, T., 2002. Archaeology and cognitive evolution. Behav. Knecht, H., Pike-Tay, A., White, R. (Eds.), Before : Brain Sci. 25, 389–437. The Complex Record of the Early Upper Paleolithic. CRC Wynn, T., Coolidge, F.L., 2003. The role of working memory Press, Boca Raton, pp. 277–299. in the evolution of managed foraging. Before Farming 2, White, T.D., Asfaw, B., DeGusta, D., Gilbert, H., Richards, 1–16. G.D., Suwa, G., Howell, F.C., 2003. Pleistocene Homo Zilhao, J., d’Errico, F., 1999. The chronology and taphonomy sapiens from Middle Awash, Ethiopia. Nature 423, of the earliest Aurignacian and its implications for the 742–747. understanding of Neandertal extinction. J. World Prehist. Whiten, A., Ham, R., 1992. On the nature and evolution of 13, 1–68. imitation in the animal kingdom: reappraisal of a century of