Master Author Index to Volumes 1–12 Issues 1–24 Prepared by Chris Matthew Sciabarra

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Master Author Index to Volumes 1–12 Issues 1–24 Prepared by Chris Matthew Sciabarra The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 12, No. 2 (Issue 24) 289 Master Author Index to Volumes 1–12 Issues 1–24 Prepared by Chris Matthew Sciabarra. This index is organized alphabetically by author in the following format: Volume . Number . Issue Number . (Date) : Page Numbers. For example, an article published in Volume 1, Number 1, Issue 1, Fall 1999, pp. 1–26 is rendered as: 1.1.1 (Fall 1999): 1–26. No references to abstracts or biographical entries are included. Multiple author references are organized chronologically. Symposia contributions are noted by symposium title in brackets. Books reviewed are noted in brackets after article titles, where appropriate. ALTICK, JOHN. Reply to Graham and Nobis: Putting Humans First? YES! 8.2.16 (Spring 2007): 317–30. ARMSTRONG, ARI. A Direct Realist’s Challenge to Skepticism [Skepticism and the Veil of Perception by Michael Huemer]. 5.2.10 (Spring 2004): 421–40. Rejoinder to Huemer: Direct Realism and Causation. 7.1.13 (Fall 2005): 239–45. AUNE, JAMES ARNT. Reply to Yeager: Rhetorical Incorrectness? 4.1.7 (Fall 2002): 231–34. BARR, EMILY J. Sex and the Egoist: Measuring Ayn Rand’s Fiction Against Her Philosophy. 12.2.24 (December 2012): 193–206. BASS, ROBERT H. Egoism versus Rights [Symposium: A Dialogue on Ayn Rand’s Ethics]. 7.2.14 (Spring 2006): 329–49. 290 The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 12, No. 2 (Issue 24) Rejoinder to Cathcart and Campbell: Defending the Argument [Symposium: A Dialogue on Ayn Rand’s Ethics]. 7.2.14 (Spring 2006): 371–81. BEADLE, RON. Rand and MacIntyre on Moral Agency. 9.2.18 (Spring 2008): 221–43. On Human Capability [co-author: Dyer-Smith, Martyn]. 3.1.5 (Fall 2001): 1–27. BEITO, DAVID T. Isabel Paterson and the Idea of America [The Woman and the Dynamo: Isabel Paterson and The Idea of America by Stephen Cox]. 8.2.16 (Spring 2007): 261–69. BELL-VILLADA, GENE H. Nordau’s Degeneration and Tolstoy’s What Is Art? Still Live [The Aesthetics Symposium]. 2.2.4 (Spring 2001): 291–97. Reply to Johnson: Nabokov and Rand: Kindred Ideological Spirits, Divergent Literary Aims. 3.1.5 (Fall 2001): 181–93. BERNSTEIN, ANDREW. Reply to Minsaas: On the Ayn Rand CliffsNotes. 3.2.6 (Spring 2002): 349. BISSELL, ROGER E. Music and Perceptual Cognition. 1.1.1 (Fall 1999): 59–86. Rejoinder to Vacker: Rockin’ with Rand: Sailing the Turbulent Seas of the Objectivist Aesthetics. 2.1.3 (Fall 2000): 221–27. Critical Misinterpretations and Missed Opportunities: Errors and Omissions by Kamhi and Torres [The Aesthetics Symposium]. 2.2.4 (Spring 2001): 299–310. Reply to Long: Mistaken Identity: Long’s Conflation of Dialectics and Organicism. 3.2.6 (Spring 2002): 351–57. The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 12, No. 2 (Issue 24) 291 A Neglected Source for Rand’s Aesthetics. 4.1.7 (Fall 2002): 187–204. Art as Microcosm: The Real Meaning of the Objectivist Concept of Art. 5.2.10 (Spring 2004): 305–63. Langer and Camus: Unexpected Post-Kantian Affinities with Rand’s Aesthetics. 7.1.13 (Fall 2005): 57–77. Ayn Rand and “The Objective”: A Closer Look at the Intrinsic- Objective-Subjective Trichotomy. 9.1.17 (Fall 2007): 53–92. Mind, Introspection and “The Objective”. 10.1.19 (Fall 2008): 3–84. Will the Real Apollo Please Stand Up?: Rand, Nietzsche, and the Reason-Emotion Dichotomy [A Symposium on Friedrich Nietzsche and Ayn Rand]. 10.2.20 (Spring 2009): 343–69. The Logic of Liberty: Aristotle, Ayn Rand, and the Logical Structure of the Political Spectrum. 12.1.23 (August 2012): 5–75. BLOCK, WALTER E. The Libertarian Minimal State? A Critique of the Views of Nozick, Levin, and Rand. 4.1.7 (Fall 2002): 141–60. Ayn Rand and Austrian Economics: Two Peas in a Pod [Cente- nary Symposium, Part II: Ayn Rand Among the Austrians]. 6.2.12 (Spring 2005): 259–69. Ayn Rand, Religion, and Libertarianism. 11.1.21 (July 2011): 63–79. BOETTKE, PETER J. Teaching Economics Through Ayn Rand: How the Economy is Like a Novel and How the Novel Can Teach Us About Econom- ics [Centenary Symposium, Part II: Ayn Rand Among the Austrians]. 6.2.12 (Spring 2005): 445–65. 292 The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 12, No. 2 (Issue 24) BOSTAPH, SAMUEL. Ayn Rand’s Economic Thought. 11.1.21 (July 2011): 19–44. BOWMAN, DURRELL. Reply to Sciabarra: To Rand or Not To Rand: Neil Peart’s Varied Influences [Symposium on “Rand, Rush, and Rock”]. 5.1.9 (Fall 2003): 153–60. BOYDSTUN, STEPHEN. Universals and Measurement. 5.2.10 (Spring 2004): 271–304. BROOKS, DEAN. Rebuttal Witnesses [Facets of Ayn Rand by Mary Ann Sures and Charles Sures]. 5.1.9 (Fall 2003): 97–103. BROWN, DAVID M. Questions About Answers [Ayn Rand Answers: The Best of Her Q&A, edited by Robert Mayhew]. 7.2.14 (Spring 2006): 473–82. BROWN, SUSAN LOVE. Essays on Ayn Rand’s Fiction [Essays on Ayn Rand’s Anthem; Essays on Ayn Rand’s We the Living, edited by Robert Mayhew]. 8.1.15 (Fall 2006): 63–84. Society: Toward an Objective View. 9.1.17 (Fall 2007): 113–38. BROWNE, GREGORY M. Reply to Long: The ‘Grotesque’ Dichotomies Still Unbeautified. 8.1.15 (Fall 2006): 123–42. BUBB, FRANK. Reply to Mack: Did Ayn Rand Do the Shuffle? [Symposium: A Dialogue on Ayn Rand’s Ethics]. 7.2.14 (Spring 2006): 257–86. The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 12, No. 2 (Issue 24) 293 CAMPBELL, ROBERT L. Ayn Rand and the Cognitive Revolution in Psychology. 1.1.1 (Fall 1999): 107–34. A Veteran Reconnoiters Ayn Rand’s Philosophy [Ayn Rand by Tibor R. Machan]. 1.2.2 (Spring 2000): 293–312. Rejoinder to Shedenhelm, Thomas, and Vacker: Implied Epistemology, Epistemology of the Implicit. 2.1.3 (Fall 2000): 211–19. Can Academics Learn from a Mere Clinical Psychologist? [The Art of Living Consciously: The Power of Awareness to Transform Everyday Life by Nathaniel Branden]. 3.1.5 (Fall 2001): 125–43. Goals, Values, and the Implicit: Explorations in Psychological Ontology. 3.2.6 (Spring 2002): 289–327. Reply to Bass: Altruism in Auguste Comte and Ayn Rand [Symposium: A Dialogue on Ayn Rand’s Ethics]. 7.2.14 (Spring 2006): 357–69. The Peikovian Doctrine of the Arbitrary Assertion. 10.1.19 (Fall 2008): 85–170. The Re-Writing of Ayn Rand’s Spoken Answers. 11.1.21 (July 2011): 81–151. CAMPOS, ANDRE SANTOS. Ayn Rand Shrugged: The Gap Between Ethical Egoism and Global Capitalism. 12.1.23 (August 2012): 77–116. CATHCART, CHRIS. Reply to Bass: Egoism and Rights [Symposium: A Dialogue on Ayn Rand’s Ethics]. 7.2.14 (Spring 2006): 351–56. CHAMPAGNE, MARC. Some Convergences and Divergences in the Realism of Charles Peirce and Ayn Rand. 8.1.15 (Fall 2006): 19–39. 294 The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 12, No. 2 (Issue 24) What About Suicide Bombers? A Terse Response to a Terse Objection. 11.2.22 (December 2011): 233–36. COX, STEPHEN. Outsides and Insides: Reimagining American Capitalism. 1.1.1 (Fall 1999): 27–57. The Art of Fiction [The Art of Fiction: A Guide for Writers and Readers by Ayn Rand, edited by Tore Boekmann]. 1.2.2 (Spring 2000): 313–31. Having Your Say [The Art of Nonfiction: A Guide for Writers and Readers by Ayn Rand, edited by Robert Mayhew]. 3.2.6 (Spring 2002): 339–47. Completing Rand’s Literary Theory [Centenary Symposium, Part I: Ayn Rand: Literary and Cultural Impact]. 6.1.11 (Fall 2004): 67–89. Merely Metaphorical: Ayn Rand, Isabel Paterson, and the Language of Theory. 8.2.16 (Spring 2007): 237–60. DAVIS, WAYNE A. Reason, Emotion, and the Importance of Philosophy. 4.1.7 (Fall 2002): 1–23. DEGUTIS, ALGIRDAS. Deconstructing Postmodern Xenophilia. 8.1.15 (Fall 2006): 49–62. DEN UYL, DOUGLAS J. Individualist Ethics and the Welfare State [A Life of One’s Own: Individual Rights and the Welfare State by David Kelley]. 3.1.5 (Fall 2001): 109–15. Reply to Vedder: Defending Norms of Liberty [co-author: Rasmussen, Douglas B.]. 10.1.19 (Fall 2008): 235–38. DENT, ERIC B. Objectivism and Christianity. 11.2.22 (December 2011): 189–213. The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 12, No. 2 (Issue 24) 295 DIPERT, RANDALL P. The Puzzle of Music and Emotion in Rand’s Aesthetics [The Aesthetics Symposium]. 2.2.4 (Spring 2001): 387–94. DOLLING, LISA M. Ayn Rand: A Feminist Despite Herself? [Feminist Interpretations of Ayn Rand, co-edited by Mimi Reisel Gladstein and Chris Matthew Sciabarra]. 1.2.2 (Spring 2000): 263–81. DOUGHNEY, LACHLAN. Ayn Rand and Deducing ‘Ought’ from ‘Is’. 12.1.23 (August 2012): 151–68. DWYER, WILLIAM. Do Knowledge, Ethics, and Liberty Require Free Will? [Initiative: Human Agency and Society by Tibor Machan]. 3.1.5 (Fall 2001): 83–108. Rejoinder to Lyons and Machan: Free Will and Determinism. 4.1.7 (Fall 2002): 221–30. DYER-SMITH, MARTYN. On Human Capability [co-author: Beadle, Ron]. 3.1.5 (Fall 2001): 1–27. DYKES, NICHOLAS. Ayn Rand in the Scholarly Literature IV: Ayn Rand in England. 5.2.10 (Spring 2004): 365–400. The Facts of Reality: Logic and History in Objectivist Debates about Government. 7.1.13 (Fall 2005): 79–140. EDITORS, THE. Introduction: The Aesthetics Symposium. 2.2.4 (Spring 2001): 251–52. 296 The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 12, No. 2 (Issue 24) ENRIGHT, JOHN. Art: What a Concept [The Aesthetics Symposium].
Recommended publications
  • Originalism, Vintage Or Nouveau: “He Said, She Said” Law
    Fordham Law Review Volume 82 Issue 2 Article 10 2013 Originalism, Vintage or Nouveau: “He Said, She Said” Law Tara Smith University of Texas at Austin Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Tara Smith, Originalism, Vintage or Nouveau: “He Said, She Said” Law, 82 Fordham L. Rev. 619 (2013). Available at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol82/iss2/10 This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. It has been accepted for inclusion in Fordham Law Review by an authorized editor of FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ORIGINALISM, VINTAGE OR NOUVEAU: “HE SAID, SHE SAID” LAW Tara Smith* INTRODUCTION: AN OVERVIEW OF ORIGINALISM’S BASIC FAILURE I begin with a brief overview of originalism’s central failings. I then consider three lines of defense that help to explain its resilient appeal and proceed to critique those three lines of reasoning. Through its various incarnations, I contend, originalism is guilty of a fatal contradiction. Law represents coercion. A legal system governs by force; that is the tool that gives teeth to its rules. I say this not as an indictment of law or of government; it is simply a fact—a fact that is significant to the proper conduct of judicial review. A legal system also works by words, which state the authority that it does and does not possess and how its coercive power will be used.
    [Show full text]
  • Reply to Fred Seddon: What Does Ayn Rand Have to Do with Who Says That’S Art? Author(S): Michelle Marder Kamhi Source: the Journal of Ayn Rand Studies , Vol
    Reply to Fred Seddon: What Does Ayn Rand Have to Do with Who Says That’s Art? Author(s): Michelle Marder Kamhi Source: The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies , Vol. 15, No. 2 (December 2015), pp. 280-286 Published by: Penn State University Press Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.5325/jaynrandstud.15.2.0280 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Penn State University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies This content downloaded from 86.59.13.237 on Mon, 07 Jun 2021 09:32:48 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Discussion Reply to Fred Seddon What Does Ayn Rand Have to Do with Who Says That’s Art? Michelle Marder Kamhi ABSTRACT: This commentary is in response to Fred Seddon’s review of Who Says That’s Art? A Commonsense View of the Visual Arts in The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies (December 2014). In addition to answering objections raised in the review about such matters as whether “abstract art” and photography should qualify as “fine art,” it aims to show in what respects the book was influenced by Rand’s thought.
    [Show full text]
  • What “Rand's Aesthetics” Is, and Why It Matters1 Michelle Marder Kamhi
    Discussion Reply to The Aesthetics Symposium (Spring 2001) What “Rand’s Aesthetics” Is, and Why It Matters1 Michelle Marder Kamhi This is the first of a two-part reply to our Spring 2001 symposium on Ayn Rand’s philosophy of art. In our Fall 2003 issue, we will publish part two, written by Louis Torres. — The Editors The Aesthetics Symposium is described in the journal’s table of contents as “[a] discussion of Ayn Rand’s philosophy of art inspired by Louis Torres and Michelle Marder Kamhi’s What Art Is: The Esthetic Theory of Ayn Rand.” The ten contributors vary widely in the extent to which they deal with either Rand’s theory of art or our book, however. While Lester Hunt and Jeff Riggenbach offer on the whole thoughtful, though not necessarily approving, responses to our analysis and application of Rand’s theory, two of the longest essays —those by John Hospers2 and Barry Vacker—scarcely touch on Rand’s philoso- phy of art, much less on our book. David Kelley focuses on two points we raised in “Critical Neglect of Ayn Rand’s Theory of Art” (Kamhi & Torres 2000)—a chapter omitted from the book and subsequently published in this journal.3 Like Kelley, Roger Bissell deals only with points related to that article, not with the main thesis of our book.4 Michael Newberry deals exclusively with the application of Rand’s concept of metaphysical value-judgments to the interpretation of paintings. Gene Bell-Villada appears to deal with the substance of our book—in particular, with our application of Rand’s theory in Part II—but he so often ignores or misconstrues our point that it is The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 4, no.
    [Show full text]
  • Tara Smith's Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics
    Review Essay: Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist Carrie-Ann Biondi Marymount Manhattan College There has been in academic philosophy a resurgence of naturalistic virtue ethics that renders it a viable competitor with deontology and utilitarianism, making the timing opportune for the appearance of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist.1 Indeed, Smith in part situates her book within this trend, but also contrasts her explication of how Rand’s rational ethical egoism intersects with virtue theories that have at best “danced around the edges of egoism” (p. 1). Thus far, Smith’s book has been generally well received in the few reviews it has gotten,2 especially by scholars and advocates of Rand’s Objectivism. However, some attention from mainstream philosophers, even by those who are sympathetic readers,3 reveals that contemporary moral philosophers struggle to understand the nuanced value theory underlying Objectivism and are slow to embrace full-fledged egoism. This is hardly surprising, given that many (if not most) ethics 1 Tara Smith, Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006). 2 See Stephen Hicks, “Review of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Philosophy in Review 27, no. 5 (October 2007), pp. 377-79; Helen Cullyer, “Review of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (November 12, 2006), accessed online at: http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=8123; Robert Mayhew, “Review of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Philosophical Books 49, no.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Foundations of Capitalism
    Capitalism and Morality _________________________ Philosophical Foundations of Capitalism Edward W. Younkins Professor of Accountancy Wheeling Jesuit University The power of ideas is great. If we are to educate, persuade, and convert others to free-market thinking, we need to articulate, in structured form, the conceptual and moral foundations of free enterprise. We are obliged to expound a coherent and consistent body of principles that are in accord with reality and that properly reflect and explain capitalism. In other words, we must approach the idea of free enterprise from a philosophical point of view. The survival of free enterprise may be in jeopardy unless people understand its conceptual and moral foundations. Capitalism is a rational doctrine based on a clear understanding of man and society in which economics, politics, and morality (all parts of one inseparable truth) are found to be in harmony with one another. Capitalism as defined in this essay involves that set of economic arrangements that would exist in a society in which the state’s only function would be to prevent one person from using force or fraud against another person. The enclosed exhibit provides an example model or diagram of the conceptual foundations of capitalism that are consistent with the nature of man and the world. The development of a conceptual framework is a natural endeavor that is undertaken in most areas that have claims to be called scientific or based on real world conditions. Frameworks for thinking about reality have long been the basis for organized knowledge. Constructing a set of ideas about real world objects, events, and occurrences would serve as a framework for a realistic political and economic system.
    [Show full text]
  • The Future of Education in the Visual Arts
    The Future of Education in the Visual Arts Comments for the January 20, 2010, ESEA Reauthorization Meeting submitted by Michelle Marder Kamhi, Co-Editor Aristos (An Online Review of the Arts) Member, National Art Education Association Member, University Council for Art Education Contact: [email protected] [Note: To save space, some of the links cited below have been condensed to “Tiny URLs.” See http://tiny.com.] The traditional visual arts of painting, drawing, and sculpture have played a significant role in human culture since prehistory. Yet they are receiving ever-shorter shrift in our nation’s schools. Critics of the Elementary and Secondary Education Act, or “No Child Left Behind” (NCLB), attribute the neglect of arts education largely to the pressures imposed on schools by mandatory testing in math and reading. They seek to remedy the situation with new proposals for the section of the Act dealing with the arts in education. As I have indicated in numerous articles published in Arts Education Policy Review and elsewhere, however, the real problem with visual art education goes much deeper than the impact of NCLB. Moreover, the changes to NCLB proposed by the National Education Taskforce (NET) will, I argue, only make matters worse. The NET proposal recommends defining the arts as “creative activities and products of the theater, the visual arts, dance, music, and multimedia combinations of the above” and requiring that “all children [be] taught the arts by arts specialists.” With respect to the visual arts in particular, however, standards have so declined that virtually anything can qualify as contemporary visual art—from purely verbal expressions such as Jenny Holzer’s Truisms < http://mfx.dasburo.com/art/truisms.html > to “sound installations” < http://tiny.cc/FnIuN >.
    [Show full text]
  • Tara Smith's Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics: a Positive Contribution?
    Reason Papers Vol. 35, no. 1 Response to Eyal Mozes, “Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: A Positive Contribution?” Carrie-Ann Biondi Marymount Manhattan College Irfan Khawaja Felician College 1. Introduction In this discussion note, we respond to Eyal Mozes’s critique of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics via his criticism of Carrie-Ann Biondi’s review of that book in Reason Papers.1 We take issue with Mozes’s discussion of Ayn Rand’s non-conflicts-of-interest principle (NCIP) along with his discussion of the nature of moral virtue. We end by taking issue with his inappropriately moralized conception of philosophical discourse. Since we agree with many (though not all) of Mozes’s claims about emergencies and the scope of morality, we leave those topics undiscussed. 2. Conflicts of Interest Mozes offers two objections to Smith’s discussion of the NCIP: For any book that purports to be a presentation of Rand’s normative ethics, a crucial part of its task is to give an elaborate explanation and defense of Rand’s no-conflicts-of-interest-principle, filling in the details of Rand’s own cursory discussion. In evaluating such a book, I don’t think there’s any question more important than how well it succeeds in explaining and defending this principle. Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics disgracefully fails in this task.2 We reject every element of this criticism. 1 Tara Smith, Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006), hereafter ARNE; Carrie-Ann Biondi, “Review Essay: Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Reason Papers 30 (Fall 2008), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae Tara Smith September 2016 6008 Aurora Drive Department of Philosophy Austin TX 78757 University Of
    Curriculum Vitae Tara Smith September 2016 6008 Aurora Drive Department of Philosophy Austin TX 78757 University of Texas at Austin Cell: (512)-507-3392 2210 Speedway, Stop C3500 [email protected] Austin, TX 78712-1737 (512) 471-6777 Department Fax: (512) 471-4806 Areas of Specialization Ethics, Political Philosophy, Philosophy of Law Education Ph.D. and MA, Philosophy, The Johns Hopkins University, 1989, 1985 Dissertation: "The Inflation of Rights" (Advisors: Susan Wolf, Richard Flathman) B.A., Philosophy and Government, University of Virginia, 1983 magna cum laude, Phi Beta Kappa London School of Economics and Political Science, Spring 1982 Professional Appointments Fall 2005-present, Professor, University of Texas at Austin Fall 1996-2005, Associate Professor, University of Texas at Austin Fall 1989-1996, Assistant Professor, University of Texas at Austin Spring 1989, St. Mary's College of Maryland, Visiting Instructor Summer 1987-Spring 1988, Towson State University, Lecturer 1985-1988, The Johns Hopkins University, Teaching Assistant Publications Books: Judicial Review in an Objective Legal System, Cambridge University Press, 2015, 301 pages. Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics – The Virtuous Egoist, Cambridge University Press, 2006, 318 pages. Chinese edition, 2010; second Chinese translation, July 2015. Viable Values: A Study of Life as the Root and Reward of Morality, Rowman & Littlefield, 2000, 205 pages. Moral Rights and Political Freedom, Rowman & Littlefield, 1995, 224 pages. Japanese edition, 1997. Articles: Forthcoming: "What Good is Religious Freedom? Locke, Rand, and the Non-Religious Case for Respecting It," Arkansas Law Review vol. 69: 4, February 2017. “Religious Liberty or Religious License? Legal Schizophrenia and the Case Against Exemptions,” Virginia Journal of Law and Politics, vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Just Sayin'—How the False Equivalence of Speech With
    JUST SAYIN’—HOW THE FALSE EQUIVALENCE OF SPEECH WITH ACTION UNDERMINES THE FREEDOM OF SPEECH Tara Smith* ABSTRACT This Article argues that a firm distinction between speech and ac- tion is critical to the preservation of freedom of speech. The line be- tween the two has blurred in recent years in disputes over such things as cake bakers’ artistic freedom to refuse certain clients, disruptions of speakers on college campuses, whether campaign finance restrictions limit spending or speaking, and social media companies’ status as platforms or publishers. For the legal system to resolve such conflicts correctly and to uphold the proper boundaries of individuals’ freedom, a firm grasp of the respective referents of “speech” and “action” is imperative. The Article is in two main parts. First, it presents the basic rationale for a legal system’s treating speech and action differently. It explains that the distinctive concern of the First Amendment is the protection of intellectual activity and demonstrates how the relationship of intellectual activities to the rights of others justifies their special legal status. Second, the Article considers the case for viewing speech and action as more readily intermingled, addressing arguments that, in turn, invoke harm, power, and symbolic speech. On analysis, none of these arguments, I show, vindicates the equation of speech with action. Finally and more briefly, the Article also considers some of the underlying sources of the conflation of speech with action, sketches the proper resolutions of a few of the recent controversies generated by * Professor of Philosophy, BB&T Chair for the Study of Objectivism, and Anthem Foundation Fellow for the Study of Objectivism at the University of Texas at Austin.
    [Show full text]
  • A VETERAN RECONNOITERS AYN RAND's PHILOSOPHY Robert L
    A VETERAN RECONNOITERS AYN RAND’S PHILOSOPHY Robert L. Campbell Ayn Rand Tibor R. Machan New York: Peter Lang, 1999 xii + 163 pp., index Tibor Machan’s new book is the latest sign of accelerated growth in the academic coverage of Ayn Rand’s philosophy. Feminist Interpretations of Ayn Rand, edited by Mimi Reisel Gladstein and Chris Matthew Sciabarra, has joined a series of volumes on Plato, Hegel, and Sartre, among others. Douglas Den Uyl’s monograph, The Fountainhead: An American Novel, in the Twayne’s Masterworks series, sits alongside critical essays on Daisy Miller and War and Peace. Now Machan’s volume takes position number 5 in a series titled “Masterworks in the Western Tradition.” It is intended as an overview and introduction to Rand’s philosophical system. Machan was eminently prepared to write this book. He has been actively promoting Randian ideas since the late 1960’s. Because he was excommunicated during the days of the Nathaniel Branden Institute for asking the wrong questions, he never got close to Rand’s inner circle and has never had to shoulder the weight of Objectivist orthodoxy. Along with Robert Poole and Manuel Klausner, he took over a new, obscure magazine called Reason in 1969 and nurtured it into a cultural force. He has published in every outlet from the academic philosophy journals to the dittoed page allotments of Libertarian Connection to the editorial columns of the daily newspapers; his output of books has grown especially prodigious over the past decade. Readers who know a little of Machan’s previous work will recognize this presentation of Rand as his most recent contribution to a continuing conversation.
    [Show full text]
  • Ayn Rand and the Possibilities of an Objectivist Aesthetics of Cinema
    Screen of Vision: Ayn Rand and the Possibilities of an Objectivist Aesthetics of Cinema Kyle Barrowman School of Journalism, Media, and Culture Cardiff University This thesis is submitted to Cardiff University in fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy April 2018 Contents Abstract iii Acknowledgments iv Preface ix Introduction – Towards an Objectivist Aesthetics of Cinema 1 1. Poststructuralism and the History of Film Studies 39 2. Objectivism and the Future of Film Studies 100 Conclusion – Approaching Atlantis 154 References 166 Abstract This thesis is my attempt to establish a foundation, based on the philosophy of Objectivism as it was developed and elaborated by the Russian-American novelist and philosopher Ayn Rand, for the construction of an Objectivist aesthetics of cinema. After con textualizing and explicating Rand’s philosophy, I make the case that, propaedeutic to the construction of a new aesthetics of cinema, it is incumbent upon film scholars to refute the irrational and immoral philosophical premises that have long been destroying the philosophy of art in general and the discipline of film studies in particular. Due to the troubling combination of its contemporaneity, extremism, and considerable influence, I focus initially on the philosophical school of poststructuralism – which I contend has, since the 1960s, served as the default philosophical foundation for film scholars – before ultimately moving on to refute what I call the Kantian aesthetic tradition, of which I demonstrate poststructuralism is a deadly symptom. Upon clearing away this philosophical debris, I set about arguing for the probative value of an Objectivist aesthetics of cinema by reigniting long-dormant debates about the validity of interpretation and the role of evaluation in film criticism.
    [Show full text]
  • What About Suicide Bombers? a Terse Response to a Terse Objection
    Ethics What About Suicide Bombers? A Terse Response to a Terse Objection Marc Champagne On September 11, 2010, after presenting selected technical aspects of a Randian ethic at a prominent academic conference,1 I was confronted with the following objection, somewhat belligerent in tone: “But what about suicide bombers?” What about them? Despite the objection’s contextual timeliness, my initial reaction was to question its topical relevance.2 So I politely requested that the criticism be further unpacked. My interlocutor duly obliged, and I eventually gleaned that murder-suicide (say, in the name of some otherworldly posit) was being adduced as a supposed counterexample to the rational egoist account of values I had just expounded. I don’t recall my exact response, only that I was dissatisfied with it afterwards. The audience member clearly thought he had unearthed a powerful criticism, and the objection, though crude, had the rhetorical merit of brevity. Such an intuitively attractive “sound bite,” I later thought, deserves to be answered in kind. Tellingly, a similar objection to Rand’s metaethics was raised in the pages of this journal. Reviewing Tara Smith’s (2000) pioneering study of Rand’s metaethical ideas, Lester Hunt claims to have discerned some “curious implications” in her views. Upon describing the conduct of a violent wanton who would uncontroversially be classified as morally despicable, Hunt contends that “[t]he position that Smith adopts would seem to mean [. .] that we can pass no moral judgments here at all,” since “[t]he individual involved happens not to desire the end (life) toward which distinctions of right and wrong are means” (2000, 109).
    [Show full text]