Brain-And-Cosmos-V1i

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Brain-And-Cosmos-V1i Brain and Cosmos – Volume 1 Issue 1 June 2011 Table of Contents Article Title Page number 1. From the Publisher 2 ­David Alan Kaiser 2. Cosmologist’s search for self 2 ­Moninder Singh Modgil 3. Boltzmann brains ‐ I’d rather be one than see one 3 ­Richard Gott­III 4. Stairway to heaven 22 – why physicists want a Theory of Everything? ­Moninder Singh Modgil 5. Introduction to di Biase ‐ 31 ­R. Adam Crane 6. A Holoinformational Model of Consciousness 37 ­Francisco di Biase 1 From the Publisher Are we surrounded by infinite imaginary selves, a continuum of perspectives and commentaries on all that ever is? Mathematics does well with only two dimensions to represent most relationships of quantity, a real and an imaginary axis, but physics and biology require time and space, and psychology posits further dimensions hidden from senses but reliably measured. Diversity of understanding is the core of Brain and Cosmos, a forum to discuss concepts across disciplines such as dimensionality and the imaginary, mind and its relationship to matter. The first issue addresses a question of cosmology and intelligence: Is the brain more complex than the universe is infinite? From the Editor Can consciousness constrain cosmology? The anthropic principle, that our cosmos is structured to enable consciousness, has been reformulated into an intriguing thesis between consciousness and cosmology, one of necessity and inevitability, called the Boltzmann Brain Hypothesis1. Named after the pioneer of statistical physics and thermodynamics2, a Boltzmann brain is a conscious system produced by random fluctuations of elementary particles, freak observers as they are called. But I ask, can statistical fluctuation create anything? Why do we not observe spontaneous manifestations of Mercedes Benz in space then? 3,4 If fluctuation can create something of complexity, with enough time can a person be created? And am I this person? Another way to ask this question is “What am I?” The answer to this question is the goal of philosophy, and the Boltzmann brain contributes to this debate. Physicists believe consciousness is a matter­ generated phenomenon, one that may arise by random fluctuations of matter‐energy ‐‐but it not considered a closed issue. Physicist Richard Gott’s paper starts the task of addressing the properties associated with consciousness such as using a Turing test on a Boltzmann brain5. Astronomers have detected “amino acids,” the building blocks of life in deep space.6 Might a Boltzmann brain be far behind? And how will we recognize it when we see it? Could our galaxy be intelligent? Might it be a thinking and acting on its thoughts? Could any scale of complexity contain intelligence? These are the kinds of questions begun by reading this issue. 1 en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Anthropic_principle 2 en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Boltzmann_brain 3 motls.blogspot.com/2007/01/boltzmanns‐brain‐and‐low‐entropy.html 4 arxiv.org/find/all/1/all:+AND+boltzmann+brain/0/1/0/all/0/1 5 en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Turing_test 6 arxiv.org/find/astro‐ph/1/abs:+AND+amino+acid/0/1/0/all/0/1 Accepted 30th January 2010 2 Publisher introduction of the first paper: When we consider the cosmos, matter differs clearly from mind in its perceptibility. Mind changes its relation to us covertly whereas matter tends to stay put in the world made by the senses. Mind requires tools to perceive its form and action, and with tools comes uncertainty. As a professor of physics at Princeton, Richard Gott claims not to be a Boltzmann brain but how does anyone know they are not a fluctuation of the cosmos, an auto‐relational swirl of willfulness willed into being by all that has passed before or after us in these halls? When it comes to the many combinations of mind to manifest on the matter we call Earth, Jesus comes to mind as a popular combination, the founder of the largest group to date on Earth, with an estimated two billion adherents alive, another two billion having passed, and cousins in nearly every way of life. So there are three questions that I ask about Jesus or Jesus consciousness after reading Gott’s paper: 1. Was Jesus a Boltzmann brain, or any similar prophet or spiritual leader, the entropic culmination of Creation, pre‐ordained in a physical as well as interpersonal sense? 2. If religious leaders are or are not Boltzmann Brains, was Abba, the one Jesus prayed to, his Dad a BB, or Yahweh, the Old Testament God? 3. Are any of us Boltzmann brains, sweet spots in the universe? BOLTZMANN BRAINS—I’D RATHER SEE ONE THAN BE ONE J. Richard Gott, III Princeton University ABSTRACT The standard cosmological, or ‘big bang’ model, is said to be dominated by dark energy. A commonly perceived problem with this theory is that in the future, space time becomes asymptotic1 to an exponentially2 expanding de Sitter space3, filled with Gibbons and Hawking thermal radiation4. Furthermore, from this thermal state, given 1 tendency of a system to behave as one approaches infinity 2 Expanding at a rate which ‐ say doubles per unit time. 3 The closed expanding universe with positive curvature. 4 Due to expansion of universe, light from points beyond a particular distance, is not able to reach an observer. These are the points which are moving at speed of light and they form the cosmological event horizon for that observer. Gibbons and Hawking thermal radiation is the energy radiating from the cosmological event horizon, analogous to that from the horizon of black holes. 3 infinite time there will be produced an infinite number of Boltzmann Brains (BBs)5 per finite co‐moving volume6 today. If BBs outnumber ordinary observers by an infinite factor, why am I not one? This Gibbons & Hawking thermal radiation is observer dependent, which is due to observer‐dependent event horizons7. Different observers moving relative to each other will see different photons, and different Boltzmann Brains. I will argue that the only particles that are real are the particles dredged out of the quantum vacuum state8 by particular real material detectors. (In much the same way, accelerated detectors dredge thermal Unruh radiation9 out of the Minkowski vacuum10 due to their observer‐dependent event horizons.). Thus, I may see a thermal Gibbons & Hawking Boltzmann Brain, but cannot be one. Observer‐independent Boltzmann Brains can be created by quantum tunneling11 events, but the rate at which ordinary observers are being added to the universe by tunneling events to inflating regions12 exceeds the rate for producing BBs by tunneling by an infinite factor. I also argue that Boltzmann Brains do not really pass the Turing test13 for intelligent observers. Thus, the standard flat‐lambda model14 is safe. INTRODUCTION The invasion of the Boltzmann Brains has become a perceived problem for the standard cosmological model, which is dominated by Dark Energy. Astronomers have discovered that the expansion of the universe is accelerating (Riess, et al. 1998, Perlmutter, et al 1999). This can be produced by a cosmological constant15 term as proposed originally by Albert Einstein. Today we would say that Einstein’s cosmological constant term represents a quantum vacuum state of constant energy density and constant negative pressure (a sort of 5 are complex human brain like objects, formed not biologically but through random statistical fluctuation in organization of matter particles. 6 Actual volume of a region in an expanding universe increases with time. A co‐moving volume, refers to relative volume of a region (as compared with say other regions). 7 A surface which light cannot cross due to either gravitation or expansion. 8 The state of space modified by presence of a quantum field – even when no particle of the field is present. 9 An accelerated particle detector, senses the presence of quantum fields, in form of particles, even though real particles may not be present. 10 Minkowski space time is the flat space time in which Einstein formulated his theory of special relativity. Minkowski vacuum is the quantum field theoretic state of its vacuum. 11 Jumping of a system across potential barriers, due to quantum mechanical effects. 12 Rapidly expanding region of space time. 13 This is a test to see if an artificially intelligent system can mimic the abilities of a human brain. 14 Currently accepted most viable cosmological model, in which the expanding universe is flat, and the cosmological constant provides the dark energy required for accelerated expansion. 15 This was a term he inserted to balance his equations, so that the universe was static and eternal, rather than expanding and with a finite past. After discovery of expansion of universe by Hubble, Einstein called it his worst professional mistake. But Cosmological constant provides a way for quantum fields to effect evolution of universe. 4 universal suction). Normally, we would think that a vacuum (empty space containing no particles and no photons) represents a state of zero energy density. But we have learned that empty space can have a non‐zero energy density. We now call this Dark Energy (or sometimes the Λ term following Einstein’s notation). If empty space has a non‐zero energy density, and it is to have no preferred standard of rest16, as Einstein wanted, it must have a negative pressure as well, equal in magnitude to its energy density. This implies that as the universe expands, the energy density of empty space will stay constant, as would its pressure, which is negative and equal to the energy density. As the universe expands, the PdV work17 done by the expansion on each volume element keeps the energy density constant as the volume expands. Since the negative pressure is uniform, it exerts no hydrodynamic forces.
Recommended publications
  • September Issue
    THE GLOBAL PRESS, ISSUE 1 OCT 4, 2013 JOHN MUIR K-12 MAGNET SCHOOL | BUILDING GLOBAL CITIZENS | FALL 2013 Sam Rempola - Editor-In-Chief Harry Pearce - Science & Technology Rahja Williams - Global Connections Pedro Quiroz & Tanya Reyes - Art Nicole Matthews - Food & Entertainment Mayra Jaramillo & Charday Drayton-White - Student Life Areli Ventura - Graphic Design Staff Writers: Genesis Felix, Rahel Garcia, Jose Juarez- Bardales, Riley Petka, Munah Togba Muir excited to announce class ambassadors by Mayra Jaramillo Annual peace march a success Being a class ambassador means by Jose Juarez students get the opportunity to On September 20th, John Muir held its annual peace walk, an event that brings together represent their classes and bring ideas students from all grades. As is the tradition, we were led by our own peace dove as we walked to the attention of ASB. Candidates were around the school holding signs and flags promoting peace. selected by their teachers based on maturity, academic standing, and leadership skills and then chosen by Muir welcomes new principal by Areli Ventura & Jael Villagomez their class. The ASB is looking forward appreciates the opportunity to have a direct to getting input from the more Muir students are happy to introduce our impact on students’ lives. Mrs. Bellofatto feels representatives of the student body, so new principal, Mrs. Laura Bellofatto. Mrs. being a principal is an amazing experience. the school supports all students. Bellofatto previously worked as a principal at Eleventh grade ambassador, Rahja When Mrs. Bellofatto is not at school, she Morse High and the Construction Tech likes to be outdoors.
    [Show full text]
  • Avoiding Boltzmann Brain Domination in Holographic Dark Energy Models
    Physics Letters B 750 (2015) 181–183 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Physics Letters B www.elsevier.com/locate/physletb Avoiding Boltzmann Brain domination in holographic dark energy models R. Horvat Rudjer Boškovi´c Institute, P.O.B. 180, 10002 Zagreb, Croatia a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t Article history: In a spatially infinite and eternal universe approaching ultimately a de Sitter (or quasi-de Sitter) Received 2 March 2015 regime, structure can form by thermal fluctuations as such a space is thermal. The models of Dark Received in revised form 10 August 2015 Energy invoking holographic principle fit naturally into such a category, and spontaneous formation of Accepted 2 September 2015 isolated brains in otherwise empty space seems the most perplexing, creating the paradox of Boltzmann Available online 7 September 2015 Brains (BB). It is thus appropriate to ask if such models can be made free from domination by Boltzmann Editor: M. Cveticˇ Brains. Here we consider only the simplest model, but adopt both the local and the global viewpoint in the description of the Universe. In the former case, we find that if a dimensionless model parameter c, which modulates the Dark Energy density, lies outside the exponentially narrow strip around the most natural c = 1line, the theory is rendered BB-safe. In the latter case, the bound on c is exponentially stronger, and seemingly at odds with those bounds on c obtained from various observational tests. © 2015 The Author. Published by Elsevier B.V.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Is There Something, Rather Than Nothing?
    Why Is There Something, Rather Than Nothing?∗ Sean M. Carroll Walter Burke Institute for Theoretical Physics California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA 91125, U.S.A. [email protected] February 8, 2018 It seems natural to ask why the universe exists at all. Modern physics suggests that the universe can exist all by itself as a self-contained system, without any- thing external to create or sustain it. But there might not be an absolute answer to why it exists. I argue that any attempt to account for the existence of some- thing rather than nothing must ultimately bottom out in a set of brute facts; the universe simply is, without ultimate cause or explanation. Science and philosophy are concerned with asking how things are, and why they are the way they are. It therefore seems natural to take the next step and ask why things are at all – why the universe exists, or why there is something rather than nothing [1, 2]. Ancient philosophers didn’t focus too much on what Heidegger [3] called the “funda- mental question of metaphysics” and Gr¨unbaum [4] has dubbed the “Primordial Existential Question.” It was Leibniz, in the eighteenth century, who first explicitly asked “Why is there something rather than nothing?” in the context of discussing his Principle of Sufficient Rea- son (“nothing is without a ground or reason why it is”) [5]. By way of an answer, Leibniz arXiv:1802.02231v1 [physics.hist-ph] 6 Feb 2018 appealed to what has become a popular strategy: God is the reason the universe exists, but God’s existence is its own reason, since God exists necessarily.
    [Show full text]
  • What Follows from the Possibility of Boltzmann Brains?
    What Follows from the Possibility of Boltzmann Brains? Matthew Kotzen University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Department of Philosophy Draft of August 27, 2017 1 The Boltzmann Brain Problems A Boltzmann Brain is a hypothesized observer that comes into existence by way of an extremely low-probability quantum or thermodynamic1 “fluctuation” and that is capable of conscious experience (including sensory experience and apparent memories) and at least some degree of reflection about itself and its environment. Boltzmann Brains do not have histories that are anything like the ones that we seriously consider as candidates for own history; they did not come into existence on a large, stable planet, and their existence is not the re- sult of any sort of evolutionary process or intelligent design. Rather, they are staggeringly improbable cosmic “accidents” that are (at least typically) mas- sively deluded about their own predicament and history. It is uncontroversial that Boltzmann Brains are both metaphysically and physically possible, and yet that they are staggeringly unlikely to fluctuate into existence at any particular moment.2 Throughout the following, I will use the term “ordinary observer” to refer to an observer who is not a Boltzmann Brain. We naturally take ourselves to be ordinary observers, and I will not be arguing that we are in any way wrong to do so. There are several deep and fascinating philosophical and cosmological ques- tions that are raised by the possibility of Boltzmann Brains. Here are just a few of them: Do I have compelling reasons to believe that I am not a Boltzmann Brain? Is it possible, under any circumstances, for me to coherently believe 1Some cosmologists have argued that Boltzmann Brains that arise as quantum fluctuations in the vacuum pose more serious problems than those that arise as thermal fluctuations — see, e.g., Davenport and Olum.
    [Show full text]
  • Forging a Culture of (Quantum) Information Science
    Forging a Culture of (Quantum) Information Science Charles H. Bennett (IBM Research Yorktown) AQIS Singapore 5 Sept 2017 Physicists, mathematicians and engineers, guided by what has worked well in their respective disciplines, acquire different scientific tastes, different notions of what constitutes an interesting, well-posed problem or an adequate solution. While this has led to some frustrating misunder- standings, it has invigorated the theory of communication and computation, enabling it to outgrow its brilliant but brash beginnings with Turing, Shannon and von Neumann, and develop its own mature scientific taste, adopting and domesticating ideas from thermodynamics and especially quantum mechanics that physicists had mistakenly thought belonged solely to their field. Theoretical computer scientists, like their counterparts in physics, suffer and benefit from a high level of intellectual machismo. They believe they have some of the biggest brains around, which they need to tackle some of the hardest problems. Like mathematicians, they prove theorems and doubt the seriousness of those who don’t (e.g. physicists like me). But beginning in the 1960’s a few (e.g.Landauer, Wiesner, Feynman, and Deutsch) tried to bring physical ideas into informatics but were not well understood. Brassard was among the first computer scientists to take these ideas seriously. Since then the productive friction between the cultures of physics, mathematics and engineering has produced more complete theory of information and communication, extending the old theory as subtly and beautifully as complex numbers extend the reals. Like other parts of mathematics, information science originated as an abstraction from practical experience. Today’s information revolution is based on the brilliant abstractions of Turing and Shannon (among others): •Turing—a universal, hardware-independent notion of computation • Shannon—a universal, meaning-independent theory of communication But now these notions are known to be too narrow.
    [Show full text]
  • An Equation Simultaneously Encodes the Duality of the Mind and the Body
    Preprints (www.preprints.org) | NOT PEER-REVIEWED | Posted: 10 February 2021 doi:10.20944/preprints202102.0233.v1 An equation simultaneously encodes the duality of the mind and the body Zilin Nie1 and Yanming Nie2 1 Department of Infectious Diseases, Mayo Clinic, 200 First St. SW, Rochester, MN 55905, USA 2 College of Information Engineering, Northwest A & F University, Yangling, Shaanxi, China 712100 Corresponding authors: [email protected]; [email protected] Keywords: Mind-body problem; Mind-body coupling phenomenon; Entropic system; Entropic system equation; Law of entropic system; Self-organized criticality (SOC); Self- organized critical triggering factor (SOCTF); Conscious strength; Macrostates of consciousness; Self-organization of minds. The mind-body problem is the central issue in both of philosophy and life science for several centuries. To date, there is still no conclusive theory to interpret the relation between the mind and the body, even just the mind alone. Here, we promote a novel model, a derived mathematic equation called the entropic system equation, to describe the innate characters of the mind and the mechanism of the mind-body coupling phenomenon. As the semi-open thermodynamic systems far from equilibrium, the living organisms could be logically considered as an entropic system. In the living organisms or the entropic systems, there also are three essential existing elements including mass, energy and information, in which the mind and the body are hypothetically coupled by free energy and entropic force. 1. Introduction In philosophy, the answer to the mind-body problem is the key criteria to distinguish the materialism and the idealism (1).
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2005.04101V1 [Physics.Hist-Ph] 28 Apr 2020
    Relativistic Implications for Physical Copies of Conscious States Andrew Knight [email protected] (Dated: May 11, 2020) The possibility of algorithmic consciousness depends on the assumption that conscious states can be copied or repeated by sufficiently duplicating their underlying physical states, leading to a variety of paradoxes, including the problems of duplication, teleportation, simulation, self-location, the Boltzmann brain, and Wigner's Friend. In an effort to further elucidate the physical nature of consciousness, I challenge these assumptions by analyzing the implications of special relativity on evolutions of identical copies of a mental state, particularly the divergence of these evolutions due to quantum fluctuations. By assuming the supervenience of a conscious state on some sufficient underlying physical state, I show that the existence of two or more instances, whether spacelike or timelike, of the same conscious state leads to a logical contradiction, ultimately refuting the assumption that a conscious state can be physically reset to an earlier state or duplicated by any physical means. Several explanatory hypotheses and implications are addressed, particularly the relationships between consciousness, locality, physical irreversibility, and quantum no-cloning. I. INTRODUCTION scious states cannot be copied, then these and other prob- lems disappear. Whether each of the above scenarios is Either it is physically possible to copy or repeat a con- actually possible is an empirical question, and given the scious state or it is not. Both possibilities have profound rate that technology is advancing, it may be just a matter implications for physics, biology, computer science, and of time before each is tested. There are related problems philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Boltzmann Brains and How Bohmian Mechanics Helps Solve It
    The Problem of Boltzmann Brains and How Bohmian Mechanics Helps Solve It Roderich Tumulka∗ December 5, 2018 Abstract Most versions of classical physics imply that if the 4-volume of the entire space-time is infinite or at least extremely large, then random fluctuations in the matter will by coincidence create copies of us in remote places, so called \Boltzmann brains." That is a problem because it leads to the wrong prediction that we should be Boltzmann brains. The question arises, how can any theory avoid making this wrong prediction? In quantum physics, it turns out that the discussion requires a formulation of quantum theory that is more precise than the orthodox interpretation. Using Bohmian mechanics for this purpose, we point out a possible solution to the problem based on the phenomenon of \freezing" of configurations. Key words: quantum fluctuation; Bunch-Davies vacuum; late universe; scalar fields in cosmology; de Sitter space-time. 1 The problem of Boltzmann brains A \Boltzmann brain" [1, 2] is this: Let M be the present macro-state of your brain. For a classical gas in thermal equilibrium, it has probability 1 that after sufficient waiting time, arXiv:1812.01909v1 [gr-qc] 5 Dec 2018 some atoms will \by coincidence" (\by fluctuation,” \by ergodicity") come together in such a way as to form a subsystem in a micro-state belonging to M. That is, this brain comes into existence not by childhood and evolution of life forms, but by coincidence; this brain has memories (duplicates of your present memories), but they are false memories: the events described in the memories never happened to this brain! Boltzmann brains are, of course, very unlikely.
    [Show full text]
  • Hep-Th] 1 May 2014
    CALT-68-2878 De Sitter Space Without Quantum Fluctuations Kimberly K. Boddy, Sean M. Carroll, and Jason Pollack∗ Physics Department, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA 91125 We argue that, under certain plausible assumptions, de Sitter space settles into a quiescent vacuum in which there are no quantum fluctuations. Quantum fluctua- tions require time-dependent histories of out-of-equilibrium recording devices, which are absent in stationary states. For a massive scalar field in a fixed de Sitter back- ground, the cosmic no-hair theorem implies that the state of the patch approaches the vacuum, where there are no fluctuations. We argue that an analogous conclusion holds whenever a patch of de Sitter is embedded in a larger theory with an infinite- dimensional Hilbert space, including semiclassical quantum gravity with false vacua or complementarity in theories with at least one Minkowski vacuum. This reasoning provides an escape from the Boltzmann brain problem in such theories. It also implies that vacuum states do not uptunnel to higher-energy vacua and that perturbations do not decohere while slow-roll inflation occurs, suggesting that eternal inflation is much less common than often supposed. On the other hand, if a de Sitter patch is a closed system with a finite-dimensional Hilbert space, there will be Poincar´e recurrences and Boltzmann fluctuations into lower-entropy states. Our analysis does not alter the conventional understanding of the origin of density fluctuations from primordial inflation, since reheating naturally generates a high-entropy environment and leads to decoherence. arXiv:1405.0298v1 [hep-th] 1 May 2014 ∗Electronic address: [email protected], [email protected], [email protected] 2 Contents 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2105.00457V1 [Hep-Th] 2 May 2021
    Black holes and up-tunneling suppress Boltzmann brains Ken D. Olum,∗ Param Upadhyay,† and Alexander Vilenkin‡ Institute of Cosmology, Department of Physics and Astronomy, Tufts University, Medford, MA 02155, USA Abstract Eternally inflating universes lead to an infinite number of Boltzmann brains but also an infinite number of ordinary observers. If we use the scale factor measure to regularize these infinities, the ordinary observers dominate the Boltzmann brains if the vacuum decay rate of each vacuum is larger than its Boltzmann brain nucleation rate. Here we point out that nucleation of small black holes should be counted in the vacuum decay rate, and this rate is always larger than the Boltzmann brain rate, if the minimum Boltzmann brain mass is more than the Planck mass. We also discuss nucleation of small, rapidly inflating regions, which may also have a higher rate than Boltzmann brains. This process also affects the distribution of the different vacua in eternal inflation. arXiv:2105.00457v1 [hep-th] 2 May 2021 ∗ [email protected][email protected][email protected] 1 I. INTRODUCTION If the observed dark energy is in fact a cosmological constant, our universe will expand forever and will soon approach de Sitter space. There will be an infinite volume in which many types of objects may nucleate. In particular there will be an infinite number of Boltzmann brains [1], human brains (or perhaps computers that simulate brains) complete with our exact memories and thoughts, that appear randomly as quantum fluctuations. Human beings (and their artifacts) can arise in the ordinary way for only a certain period of time after the Big Bang, when there are still stars and other necessities of life, but Boltzmann brains can arise at any time in the future.
    [Show full text]
  • The Boltzmann Brain Problem and Quantum Information Theory
    Occam’s Razor, Boltzmann’s Brain and Wigner’s Friend Charles H. Bennett* (IBM Research) including joint work with C. Jess Riedel* (Perimeter Institute) and old joint work with Geoff Grinstein (IBM, retired) Public Lecture, Niels Bohr Institute 24 October 2019 *Supported in part by a grant from the John Templeton Foundation How does the familiar complicated world we inhabit emerge cosmologically from the austere high-level laws of quantum mechanics and general relativity, or terrestrially from lower-level laws of physics and chemistry? To attack this question in a disciplined fashion, one must first define complexity, the property that increases when a self-organizing system organizes itself. • The relation between Dynamics—the spontaneous motion or change of a system obeying physical laws— and Computation—a programmed sequence of mathematical operations • Self-organization, exemplified by cellular automata and logical depth as a measure of complexity. • True and False evidence—the Boltzmann Brain problem at equilibrium and in modern cosmology • Wigner’s Friend—what it feels like to be inside an unmeasured quantum superposition A simple cause can have a complicated effect, but not right away. A good scientific theory should give predictions relative to which the phenomena it seeks to explain are typical. A cartoon by Sidney Harris shows a group of cosmologists pondering an apparent typicality violation “Now if we run our picture of the universe backwards several billion years, we get an object resembling Donald Duck. There is obviously a fallacy here.” (This cartoon is not too far from problems that actually come up in current cosmology) Scientific vs.
    [Show full text]
  • Boltzmannian Immortality* Christian Loew†
    Boltzmannian Immortality* Christian Loew† ABSTRACT: Plausible assumptions from Cosmology and Statistical Mechanics entail that it is overwhelmingly likely that there will be exact duplicates of us in the distant future long after our deaths. Call such persons “Boltzmann duplicates,” after the great pioneer of Statistical Mechanics. In this paper, I argue that if survival of death is possible at all, then we almost surely will survive our deaths because there almost surely will be Boltzmann duplicates of us in the distant future that stand in appropriate relations to us to guarantee our survival. KEYWORDS: Personal Identity; Statistical Mechanics; Survival; Thermodynamics; Boltzmann Brains. §1 Introduction The future looks grim. We all will die: Our consciousness will fade, our memories vanish, our bodies disintegrate, and the particles that made up our bodies disperse into far-off corners of space. But what if at some point in the distant future there will be an exact duplicate of you just as you were shortly before your death with your brain and all life functions intact? This person will think about the same things you were thinking about, pursue the same goals, and perhaps even finish the article you were writing. In this paper, I will show that it follows from Statistical Mechanics and Cosmology that it is overwhelmingly likely that there will be such duplicates of us in the distant future long after our deaths. Moreover, I will argue that these duplicates are suitably related to us to plausibly guarantee our survival. In particular, I will show that if survival of death is possible at all, then all of us will almost surely survive our death.
    [Show full text]