Confucian Insights for Gianni Vattimo's Secularized Religiousness a Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Division of the U

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Confucian Insights for Gianni Vattimo's Secularized Religiousness a Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Division of the U CONFUCIAN INSIGHTS FOR GIANNI VATTIMO’S SECULARIZED RELIGIOUSNESS A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAIʻI AT MĀNOA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY DECEMBER 2012 By Richard D. Power Dissertation Committee: Chung-ying Cheng, Chairperson Tamara Albertini Roger T. Ames Ron Bontekoe Poul Andersen ii DEDICATION This modest achievement is lovingly dedicated to my wife, Vicki. From Oklahoma to Honolulu to Beijing to Kansas, she has journeyed with me and never doubted we would reach the goal. The journey and the destination are sweeter because they have been shared with her. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I am deeply grateful to the members of my dissertation committee for their encouragement on this project and their constructive comments on the early drafts of the paper. To my chairperson, Cheng Chung-ying, I owe a special debt of gratitude for his patience, guidance and advocacy. It was from Cheng Chung-ying and Roger Ames that I took my first undergraduate courses in Chinese philosophy some thirty years ago. They helped to spark my interest in world philosophy, especially the Chinese milieu. It is my extreme good fortune to have returned to Hawaii to study with them in this doctoral program. To Ron Bontekoe, Graduate Chair, for his timely communication and counsel regarding departmental and graduate division policies. To Renee Kojima-Itagaki, for serving as a helpful liaison with the committee and for demonstrating personal concern and interest in the students of the philosophy department. iv ABSTRACT As an exercise in comparative philosophy, this study seeks to bring early Confucian philosophy into constructive dialogue with the postmodern religious thought of Italian philosopher, Gianni Vattimo. I interpret classical Confucianism as an immanental worldview that does not appeal to categories of strict transcendence for its meaning, values and religiousness. Confucianism affirms the spirituality of becoming more fully human within the world. Vattimo is a hermeneutical philosopher in the lineage of Martin Heidegger and Hans-Georg Gadamer. He offers a historicist revision of Christianity that utilizes the metaphor of kenosis to signify the emptying of God’s transcendence onto the plain of human relationships. Vattimo believes secularization is the inevitable outworking of the Christian message in society. Vattimo’s “weak thought” offers a post-metaphysical, nihilistic account of hermeneutics, religious experience and ethical conduct. He seeks a Gadamerian culture of dialogue in which truth is consensus among language users. Religious experience, for Vattimo, is a feeling of dependence upon the chain of messages received within the biblical tradition. In ethics, Christian charity, as the principle that best serves the reduction of violence, is the limit of secularization. Confucianism offers constructive insights for Vattimo’s secularized religiousness. I develop a Confucian “sagely hermeneutics” that focuses on the key role of wise listeners and interpreters in the community. Religiousness is considered under two rubrics: first, the sense of unity with and participation in cosmic order and, second, human interrelatedness and ethical responsibility. I suggest that an ecological sensibility v based on a Confucian/Daoist vision of human-cosmic unity enables one to see the world as enchanted or sacred. For human relationships, I recommend Confucian role ethics that begins in the family with xiao (孝), “family reverence.” In place of charity, I propose shu (恕) “putting oneself in another’s place.” vi CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS . iii ABSTRACT . iv INTRODUCTION . 1 Catalysts for the Study . 3 Voices in the Conversation . 15 Chapter 1: Hermeneutics . 25 Hermeneutical Character of the Study . 25 Confucian Sagely Hermeneutics . .43 Chapter 2: Transcendence . 56 The Debate Regarding Transcendence in Confucian Texts . 56 Thinking Transcendence in a Post-metaphysical World . .74 Chapter 3: Religiousness—The Experience of the Sacred . 90 Vattimoʻs Secularized Religiousness . 90 Confucian Religiousness: A Sense of Unity With and Participation In Cosmic Order . 105 Chapter 4: Religiousness—Human Interrelatedness and Ethical Responsibility . 137 Vattimoʻs Ethics of Continuity and Charity . 138 Confucian Religiousness: Human Relationships . 157 CONCLUSION . 175 BIBLIOGRAPHY . 186 INTRODUCTION The postmodern ethos engenders conversation among interlocutors separated by vast temporal and cultural distances. It is an atmosphere in which formerly disrespected (non-Western) and/or discredited (pre-modern) perspectives are valued as important contributions to the global exchange of ideas. This study seeks to allow voices from ancient China to speak into twenty-first century discussions about what it means to be religious. Specifically, I employ insights from the early Confucian canon to critique the thought of Italian philosopher, Gianni Vattimo. Can Confucians and postmodern European thinkers communicate across the historical and cultural chasms that separate their intellectual milieus? And, if so, what does each have to say to the other? My conviction is that these philosophers share remarkably similar questions and interpretations regarding what it means to be authentically human, regarding the relation of human beings to the cosmos and to what, if anything, lies beyond the natural world. As an exercise in inter-cultural conversation, this study will apply Mencius’ admonition to “look for friends in history.” Mencius said, The best Gentleman in the village is in a position to make friends with the best Gentlemen in other villages; the best Gentleman in a state, with the best Gentlemen in other states; and the best Gentleman in the Empire, with the best Gentlemen in the Empire. And not content with making friends of the best Gentlemen in the Empire, he goes back in time and communes with the ancients. When one reads the poems and writings of the ancients, can it be right not to know something about them as men? Hence one tries to understand the age in which they lived. This can be described as “looking for friends in history.” (Mencius VB.8)1 1 D. C. Lau, trans. Mencius, (London: Penguin Books, 1970), 158. 孟子謂萬章曰 :一鄉之善士,斯友一鄉之善士;一國之善士,斯友一國之善士;天下之善士,斯友天下 2 Postmodern philosophers like Vattimo, to the extent they are willing to listen to ancient voices, may discover in the early Confucian texts a worldview companionable to their own understandings of life in the world. As a post-metaphysical expression of religiousness, Vattimo’s thought finds significant points of contact with early Confucian spirituality. However, compared to Vattimo’s philosophical context, Confucianism, unencumbered by the weight of the metaphysical categories enshrined in Western modernity, offers an environment more congenial to the ideas of religion and ethics without radical transcendence. Early Confucians and Daoists share an immanental cosmology according to which human religious and ethical experience are explained by reference to a cosmic totality of which human beings are a contributory part. There is no transcendent being or realm that exists independently of the natural world. Yet, there is a sense of transcendence when one reflects upon his or her role as a co-creator among the myriad beings of the universe. The Confucian texts, both in their attentiveness to human self-creativity and their emphasis upon social roles and relationships, portray human existence as deeply spiritual or religious. In its “this-worldly,” human-centered spirituality, Confucianism offers significant insights for Vattimo’s secularized religiousness. Respectful dialogue between Anglo-European postmodern thought and early Confucian philosophy in China contributes to intercultural understanding in a globalized world. As the West struggles to overcome (Überwindung), or, in Vattimo’s words, to 之善士。以友天下之善士為未足,又尚論古之人。頌其詩,讀其書,不知其人,可乎?是 以論其世也。是尚友也。 3 twist, distort or ironically accept (Verwindung),2 its metaphysical inheritance, it stands to benefit from openness to, and dialogue with, non-metaphysical worldviews represented in philosophies of a non-Western provenance. This study is offered as a modest contribution to that conversation. Catalysts for the Study Three philosophical and cultural developments serve as catalysts for this study: first, the so-called “return to religion” in Continental philosophy; second, progress in understanding among Western scholars regarding the nature of Confucian religiousness; and, third, continuing advances in the field of comparative philosophy, East and West. The “Religious Turn” in Continental Philosophy It is difficult to identify precisely the occasion of the theological turn in Continental philosophy. As early as 1980, there began to be serious inquiry into the religious implications of Heidegger’s thought, particularly his later phase.3 Following 2 See Gianni Vattimo, “Philosophy and the Decline of the West,” in Nihilism and Emancipation: Ethics, Politics, and Law, ed. Santiago Zabala, trans. William McCuaig (New York: Columbia University Press, 2004), 27-28. In contrast to Hegel’s dialectical overcoming (Überwindung), Verwindung is the term employed by Heidegger in his treatment of the West’s relation to its metaphysical lineage. Vattimo takes up and elaborates these terms in many texts and articles. 3 See, for example, Richard Kearney & Joseph O’Leary, eds., Heidegger et la Question De Dieu (Paris: Grasset, 1980). This volume features papers presented at a conference
Recommended publications
  • Dialectics, Difference, Weak Thought
    1 Dialectics, Difference, Weak Thought GIANNI VATTIMO In this essay I will try to sketch the main tenets of weak thought, il pensiero debole, and how it is related to dialectics and difference. This connection is not to be understood mainly or solely as an “overcoming” but, rather, it is to be defined primarily in terms of the Heideggerian notion ofVerwindung , a term whose sense also must be understood within the horizon of a “weak” notion of what it means to think. We cannot in any case read the relationship between these three terms as if we were talking of a passage from one to the other. Weak thought has not entirely left dialectics and difference behind; rather, they constitute for it a past in the Heideggerian sense of Gewesenes, which has to do with the idea of sending [invio] and destiny. With these premises, however, I am not saying that to take dialectics and difference as a point of departure requires I take a theoretical stance which would need to be radically justified, assuming that it could. In the present context, these two terms are “givens” of destiny understood as trans- mission: they are points of reference we encounter each and every time we engage in thinking, here and now. It is probably only “strong” thought, that of deductive cogency, which fears letting the initial move escape, the move after which everything falls into place. And yet the question of beginnings cannot be avoided even from the standpoint of a weak notion of thinking. Weak thought presupposes that, contrary to the heavily metaphysical frame- work beneath the problem of beginnings (starting from the first principles of Being), and contrary moreover to a historicist metaphysics (in Hegel’s sense, in which Being has no first principles but is rather a providential process: to think means to be up on the times), a third way may be possible.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Post-Secular Debate
    The Post-Secular Debate: Introductory Remarks Camil Ungureanu and Lasse Thomassen* Some scholars have recently expressed their doubts about the popular use of the term “post-secularism” and suggested that it is merely a short-lived fashion in social theory and philosophy, all too often used to gain access to research grants.1 Veit Bader may be perfectly right about the term itself, for in time it may indeed fall into disregard and disappear from use. Skepticism about its inflationary use is, we think, warranted. However, we also submit that, if severed from the temptation of proposing a new grand narrative, “post-secularism” can be useful for designating a socio-cultural phenomenon that will not wither away any time soon. Let us first consider the inflationary reading according to which the “return” of religion is interpreted as the shift to a new age or to a new type of society coming after the secular one. According to this influential reading, advanced by philosophers as different as Jürgen Habermas, John D. Caputo, and Gianni Vattimo, in this new age a transformed religion may play a fundamental role in the socio-political sphere and enable individuals to overcome unhelpful divisions between faith and reason. Habermas, for one, speaks of a new “post-secular society” in which religious and non- * Department of Social and Political Science, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona, Spain. Email: camil.ungureanu@ upf.edu. School of Politics and International Relations, Queen Mary, University of London. Email: [email protected] 1 religious citizens engage, predominantly in the social-public sphere, in a process of mutual learning and reconciliation through dialogue and the exchange of reasons.2 For Habermas, religious and non-religious citizens can attain agreements and enrich public discourse by means of a rational dialogue, understood, in large part, as leading to the translation of sacred language into secular language.
    [Show full text]
  • This Won't Hurt
    24 PHILOSOPHY tongue was bound with a leather gag – all of the What lies ahead philosophers whom Bradatan considers to have “performed” exemplary deaths exercise complete control and mastery in their last moments: they die walking, talking, laughing he story is as old as philosophy itself. WILL REES Giordano Bruno and Jan Patocka: “martyr- and mocking the authorities that execute them. Socrates, found guilty of impiety and philosophers” who did not simply have ideas They remain themselves right to the end, dying Tof corrupting the youth, is sentenced to Costica Bradatan about death, but who died for ideas. “Once the deaths that are uniquely theirs. Doesn’t the death by an Athenian court. Given the chance body has come into play . everything appeal of this belie a certain anxiety, a fear of DYING FOR IDEAS to save himself, he refuses. In his Phaedo, The dangerous lives of the philosophers changes. Now death can no longer be a ‘topic’, the loss of control and self that more com- Plato explains how, just a few hours before 272pp. Bloomsbury. £19.99 (US $34.95). there cannot be anything abstract about it.” monly awaits us at the end of life? drinking the hemlock that kills him, Socrates 978 1 4725 2551 2 Regardless of their philosophical colours, After all, most of us do not face deaths such proffers a novel redefinition of the philoso- these thinkers are the ultimate empiricists, as these; indeed, for most of us death will not pher: those who practise philosophy do so using their bodies as laboratories in which to be a “performance” at all.
    [Show full text]
  • The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2012 The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Joseph Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Joseph, "The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno" (2012). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 125. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/125 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno A Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy October, 2011 By Joseph Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Sciences DePaul University Chicago, Illinois 2 ABSTRACT Joseph Weiss Title: The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Critical Theory demands that its forms of critique express resistance to the socially necessary illusions of a given historical period. Yet theorists have seldom discussed just how much it is the case that, for Walter Benjamin and Theodor W.
    [Show full text]
  • The Road to Freedom? | by Tim Parks | the New York Review of Books
    3/6/2017 The Road to Freedom? | by Tim Parks | The New York Review of Books The Road to Freedom? Tim Parks JANUARY 14, 2016 ISSUE Memory Theater by Simon Critchley Other Press, 101 pp., $15.95 Suicide by Simon Critchley Thought Catalog, 88 pp., $2.99 (e­book) In Samuel Beckett’s novel Malone Dies the eponymous hero becomes obsessed with the idea of reciting a complete inventory of his worldly goods in the few moments preceding his death: a unique occasion, he feels, for producing “something suspiciously like a true statement at last.” Needless to say, despite Malone’s enjoying very few possessions, the reader understands at once that this last desperate bid for control will be beyond him. The world will not stay still, his memory is failing, and the moment of death, or rather the last moments of lucidity in which an inventory might be recited, are impossible to predict. In Memory Theater, Simon Critchley’s hero, who would Simon Critchley, Tilburg, the Netherlands, 2012 appear to be a fictional Simon Critchley, in that he shares the same curriculum vitae and publications as Critchley, has a more extravagant but related ambition: in the hours immediately preceding his demise he will embark on a virtuoso recall not only of his own life but of all the philosophy and history he has ever known. At the instant of my death, I would have recalled the totality of my knowledge. At the moment of termination, I would become God­like, transfigured, radiant, perfectly self­sufficient, alpha and omega. Critchley’s delirious alter ego has more energy than Malone and with the aid of a “memory theater,” an elaborate prompting mechanism, appears to have achieved his end, at least so far as the recall is concerned, only to discover that he is not going to die when expected.
    [Show full text]
  • Nihilism & Emancipation: Ethics, Politics, & Law Gianni Vattimo
    Nihilism & Emancipation: Ethics, Politics, & Law Gianni Vattimo Foreword by Richard Rorty [ix] Gianni Vattimo is a prominent social democratic politician, a widely read newspaper columnist, and a distinguished philosopher. He was elected in 1999 to the European Parliament, where he has been very active in promoting progressive social legislation and in furthering European unification. For decades, his comments on the political scene in Italy and Europe have appeared in La stampa and other leading Italian newspapers and magazines; he is currently using those media to unleash fierce criticisms of the Berlusconi regime. His philosophical writings, of which this volume provides a rich sample, are among the most imaginative contributions to the tradition of philosophical thought that flows from Nietzsche and Heidegger. These writings are perfectly suited to the needs of those hitherto unfamiliar with this tradition who would like to gain an understanding of the intellectual outlook he calls "nihilism." This way of seeing things might also be called "commonsense Heideggerianism," for it is widespread, and often taken for granted, among European intellectuals. Many philosophers who, like Vattimo and Derrida, were students in the 1950s, were deeply impressed by Heidegger essays such as "Letter on Humanism," "The Question Concerning Technology," "The Origin of the [x] Work of Art" and "Nietzsche's Word: God is Dead." Many of them presuppose, in their own writings, their readers' familiarity with Heidegger's story about the history of Western thought—his account of how the Platonic dream of escaping from Becoming to Being has been dreamt out, and how Nietzsche brought metaphysics to its destined end by inverting Plato, giving Becoming primacy over Being.
    [Show full text]
  • Habermas for Historians Four Approaches to His Works
    FORSCHUNGSBERICHTE FORSCHUNGSBERICHTE Hanco Jürgens Habermas for Historians 5 Four Approaches to his Works Undoubtedly Jürgen Habermas is Germany’s most important living philos- opher. His writings on the public sphere, technology and science, communi- cative action, law and democracy, and the post-secular and the post-national society have influenced generations of scholars in various disciplines. For historians, Habermas’ life, his works, and his polemics are a challenge.1 His broad scope, the topicality of his work, and slight, but noteworthy transi- tions of his ideas – over a period of more than half a century – make it diffi- cult to position the sociologist philosopher in the cultural and intellectual debates of our times. As a philosopher, Habermas changed from a Neo- Marxist critic modern society into a defender of modernity. As a polemist, Habermas has been involved in many public debates, amongst others about nuclear proliferation, the Rote Armee Fraktion, the place of the Holocaust in German history, the German unification, constitutional patriotism, and gene technology. Allthough Habermas has never felt himself a historian, his influence on historiography is considerable. On the one hand, histori- ans very often refer to his early work on the structural transformation of the public sphere, on the other to his leading role in the Historikerstreit. Could this all be brought together into one picture? This article is meant to outline Habermas’ contribution to historiogra- phy by contextualizing his ideas first. To do so, I think we should distinguish four different approaches to his work: within the context of the History of Philosophy, of Critical Theory, of the German intellectual debate after World War II, and finally of a certain discipline, be it sociology, law, eco- nomics, political science, linguistics, or history.
    [Show full text]
  • Impossible Objects: Interviews by Simon Critchley, Carl Cederström and Todd Kesselman Cambridge: Polity, 2012 (ISBN: 978-0745653211)
    Impossible Objects: Interviews by Simon Critchley, Carl Cederström and Todd Kesselman Cambridge: Polity, 2012 (ISBN: 978-0745653211). 180pp. Richard Mailey (University of Glasgow) English philosopher Simon Critchley made his name as an expert on the so-called deconstructive tradition; his new book – the aptly-titled, Impossible Objects – shows how deep these roots run. The book is a collection of interviews spanning Critchley’s career, and it is therefore fitting that Carl Cederström and Todd Kesselman should use their editorial introduction to reflect on the powerlessness of the philosopher as interviewee – a powerlessness which lays all of his best plans to waste before the brute immediacy of live communication. By a very Freudian turn, Cederström and Kesselman take this as a major plus point; the interview is not a theoretical supplement they claim, but an unparalleled chance to catch the philosopher in his natural environment, to see him squirm and stress and stutter under the weight of his contemplative obligation. I could hardly agree more: if the text of Impossible Objects teaches us anything at all, it is surely that the good, thoughtful philosopher will and should always feel the pressure of the interview format. This is how Derrida, who Critchley admiringly and crucially refers to as ‘the philosopher’ (p.59), would perhaps have seen it: there is never enough time or knowledge to justify the philosopher’s speech; and yet, he is always being asked, by the very definition of his position, to stand up and speak. Impossible Objects can surely be well-read as a demonstration of this paradox.
    [Show full text]
  • AUC Interpretationes 1 2015 4473.Indd
    2015/1 ACTA UNIVERSITATIS CAROLINAE PAG. 13–36 Interpretationes Studia Philosophica Europeanea YES, WE CAN1 WALTER MIGNOLO Abstract At the end of 2012 at Al Jazeera, Santiago Zabala published a text about Zizek and the role of the philosopher nowadays. This publication motivated a critical response from the Iranian philosopher Hamid Dabashi, followed by Walter Mignolo ’ s intervention. Both responses emphasized the pending task of decolonizing knowledge. Returning to the axes of that exchange, H. Dabashi wrote the recently published book Can non-Europeans think? The article presented below is the foreword of the book, written by Walter Mignolo: “Yes, we can”. La Europa que consideró que su destino, el destino de sus hombres, era hacer de su humanismo el arquetipo a alcanzar por todo ente que se le pudiese asemejar; esta Europa, lo mismo la cristiana que la moderna, al trascender los linderos de su geografía y tropezar con otros entes que parecían ser hombres, exigió a éstos que justificasen su supuesta humanidad. Leopoldo Zea, La filosofía americana como filosofía sin más (1969) 1 Tiré de Dabashi Hamid, Can Non-Europeans Think?, London, Zed Books, 2015. 13 Ali Shari ’ ati, “Mission of a Free Thinker” (1970–71) I take this opportunity to continue the conversation started in Al Jazeera a while ago, prompted by Santiago Zabala ’ s essays on Slavoj Žižek, followed by Hamid Dabashi ’ s essay titled “Can Non-Europeans Think?”, reprinted in this vol- ume. Dabashi picked up in the first paragraph of Zabala ’ s essays on Žižek an un- conscious dismissal that has run through the history of the coloniality of power in its epistemic and ontological spheres: the self-assumed Eurocentrism (the world seen, described and mapped from European perspectives and interests).
    [Show full text]
  • Santiago Zabala
    Biographies Biographies Daniela Angelucci is associate professor of Aesthetics and co-director of the Postgraduate course in Environmental Humanities at University Roma Tre. Her research interests include philosophy of film and literature, contemporary philosophy, and psychoanalysis. She is the author of the book, Deleuze and the Concepts of Cinema (2014). She has recently published, among many others, the essays: ‘Cinema and Resistance’ in Deleuze in Italy (2019); ‘Tremor, Uncertainty, Invention. Europe and the Sea’ in Notes on Europe. The Dogmatic Sleep (2020). E-mail: [email protected] Jaume Casals is Full Professor of Philosophy and former President of Pompeu Fabra University in Barcelona. He is the author of books, articles, chapters in edited collections and annotations of works by eminent classic, modern and contemporary philosophers. He has translated and edited works by Montaigne, Montesquieu, Berkeley and Bergson, among others. His most recent book is ¿Qué sé yo?: La filosofía de Michel de Montaigne (2018) E-mail: [email protected] Daniel Innerarity is Professor of Political Philosophy at the University of the Basque Country and the Ikerbasque Foundation for Science, Spain. He is also director of the Instituto de Gobernanza Democrática and part time Professor at the European University Institute. Author of several books and articles translated in many languages. Among his most recent publications are Una teoría de la democracia compleja (2021) and Pandemocracia. Una filosofía de la crisis del coronavirus (2021). E-mail: [email protected] Silvia Mazzini teaches the History of Late-Modern Continental Philosophy at the University of Groningen and Aesthetics at the IDSVA. She is the author of Für eine mannigfaltige mögliche Welt.
    [Show full text]
  • After Deconstruction
    Differentia: Review of Italian Thought Number 1 Autumn Article 34 1986 After Deconstruction Rodger Friedman Follow this and additional works at: https://commons.library.stonybrook.edu/differentia Recommended Citation Friedman, Rodger (1986) "After Deconstruction," Differentia: Review of Italian Thought: Vol. 1 , Article 34. Available at: https://commons.library.stonybrook.edu/differentia/vol1/iss1/34 This document is brought to you for free and open access by Academic Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Differentia: Review of Italian Thought by an authorized editor of Academic Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. After Deconstruction by Rodger Friedman Review-essay on Gianni Vattimo and Aldo Rovatti, eds. JI pensierodebole. Milano: Giangiacomo Feltrinelli Editore, 1983. 262pp. Post-structuralist philosophical writing in Italy, as elsewhere, is faced with taking seriously the thesis of "the end of philosophy" sketched earlier this century by Heidegger and continued in the work of Adorno, Benjamin, and on into the French 1970s. The thesis of the end of the parabola of Western philosophy (actually, the end of expository philosophical discourse) was conceived par­ tially in a polemical stance toward Western rational m~taphysics and toward the totalizing, systemic philosophies epitomized in Descartes, in Kant, and (more or less judiciously) in Plato, depend­ ing on the polemic involved. Philosophical writers in Italy find themselves in a position where the polemic has largely served its purpose. The restrictions inherent in the metaphysical undertak­ ing have been disclosed to the extent that further disclosure of the problem would not seem to obtain.
    [Show full text]
  • Hermeneutic Responsibility: Vattimo, Gadamer, and the Impetus of Interpretive Engagement
    Duquesne Studies in Phenomenology Volume 1 Issue 1 Hermeneutics Today Article 4 April 2020 Hermeneutic Responsibility: Vattimo, Gadamer, and the Impetus of Interpretive Engagement Theodore George Texas A&M University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/dsp Recommended Citation George, T. (2020). Hermeneutic Responsibility: Vattimo, Gadamer, and the Impetus of Interpretive Engagement. Duquesne Studies in Phenomenology, 1 (1). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/dsp/vol1/ iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Duquesne Studies in Phenomenology by an authorized editor of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. H ERMENEUTIC R ESPONSIBILITY VATTIMO, GADAMER, AND THE IMPETUS OF INTERPRETIVE ENGAGEMENT THEODORE GEORGE Texas A&M University Few fields of study have drawn more attention to questions of responsibility—moral, social, and political—than contemporary Continental philosophy. In recent writings, Gianni Vattimo has returned to focus on his radical, even revolutionary hermeneutical considerations of responsibility.1 Within this context, his Gifford Lectures and related essays (published as Of Reality: The Purposes of Philosophy) address questions of hermeneutic responsibility elicited by the renewed philosophical interest in realism in our times. For Vattimo, as we shall see, it is our hermeneutical responsibility to resist, even to engage in interpretive conflict against, what he will describe as the “temptation of realism.” Both within the discipline of philosophy and in larger spheres of society and politics, realism is often lauded not only as, say, a metaphysical position but, moreover, as an ideal or even as an attitude.2 ‘Realism’ often stands for belief in the progress of knowledge through research in the sciences, suspicion of intellectual sophistication that obscures the facts, and, accordingly, trust in sound common sense.
    [Show full text]