Empiricism and Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Empiricism and Philosophy Empiricism and Philosophy Nathan Sinclair Degree: Doctor of Philosophy The University of Sydney 2008 This thesis is submitted in partial fulfillment for the degree of doctor of philosophy and is entirely my own work except where indicated in the references. 4 To Kate, with and without whom I could not have written this Contents I Evidence 27 1 Strong Empiricism 31 1.0.1 Translation . 32 1.0.2 Postulation . 32 1.0.3 Sense-data . 34 1.1 The refutation of strong empiricism . 37 1.1.1 Craig's theorem . 39 1.1.2 Hidden objects and computational complexity . 44 1.1.3 Another view of hidden objects . 47 2 Weak empiricism 51 2.1 From experience to stimulation: the rejection of phenomenology . 51 2.1.1 Evidence naturalised . 61 2.2 Stimuli . 62 2.2.1 Looking under the skin . 63 2.2.2 Looking at sensory surfaces: Problems with inter-subjective identification of stimuli . 73 2.2.3 Looking above the skin . 75 2.2.4 Each to their own . 92 2.3 The scope of human knowledge according to weak empiricism . 95 2.3.1 Foundations and Constructions . 106 2.3.2 The status of logic . 114 II Inference 117 3 In search of necessity 119 3.1 Conceptual Necessity . 121 4 Quine's arguments against analyticity 147 4.1 Circularity . 148 7 8 CONTENTS 4.2 The first argument from Universal Revisability . 152 4.3 The second argument from Universal Revisability . 153 4.4 The argument via Universal maintainability . 156 4.5 The good argument . 161 4.5.1 Objections and loose ends . 176 4.6 The End of a Dream . 193 III Philosophy 203 5 Distinguishing philosophy and science 207 5.0.1 Causes of Quine's oversight and its acceptance . 209 6 Resolving philosophical disputes 211 6.1 Philosophy of the don't cares . 211 6.1.1 The lack of decisive resolutions . 214 6.1.2 The need for decisive resolutions . 215 6.2 Some traditional suggestions for resolving philosophical disputes 217 6.2.1 Simplicity . 217 6.2.2 Inconsistency . 224 6.3 Looking for a defect other than inconsistency . 227 6.3.1 Theories . 227 6.3.2 Defective Theories: First Impressions . 229 6.3.3 Ambiguities without senses . 232 6.3.4 The fly in the ointment: Craig's theorem revisited . 243 6.4 Conclusion . 248 Introduction We ought not then be lead astray by the contentious argument you quoted. It would make us lazy, and is music in the ears of weaklings. The other doctrine produces energetic seekers after knowledge; and being convinced of its truth, I am ready, with your help, to inquire into the nature of virtue. (Socrates in the Meno) In nineteen ninety-eight I experienced a physical, an emotional and an in- tellectual crisis. I was beaten and stabbed1 four times on Petersham station, I separated from the mother of my first two (and then only) children, and I lost faith in the analytic-synthetic distinction. Though it dominated for a short pe- riod of time, the physical pain soon subsided; and as it gradually became clear that my children were going to largely recover from the harm inflicted upon them in my separation with their mother, so did the emotional. The longest en- during crisis, and the one which over time caused me the greatest unhappiness, was my loss of faith in the analytic-synthetic distinction. The ankle-tap which lead to my rejection of the analytic-synthetic distinction was provided by Michael McDermott in a course titled \Ayer and Quine". That course introduced me to Quine's polemic against the existence of a distinction between analytic and synthetic truths. Till that time I had held a constellation of beliefs that may be best tersely described as a form of Australian realism; and, influenced by David Armstrong, I took Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico- Philosophicus to be one of the central texts of that school. (At the time I was unaware of the work's latent phenomenalism2) Even at the time the Tractatus was not taken as holy writ; Armstrong held that the atoms into which possible states of affairs could be divided were to be discovered by empirical investiga- tion rather than by analysis of the meanings which were these atom's semantic counterparts. For my own part I held a less rigid view of atoms, believing that 1with a key protruding through the knuckles 2I now have the impression that the only thing stopping Wittgenstein from an open ad- mission that the atomic facts were sensory was, to borrow his term, an inability to make sense of the \grammar" of the phrase `is an atomic fact'. 9 10 CONTENTS like many mathematical spaces, if the space of possible worlds had at least one basis or spanning set of atomic elements then it had at least countably many such sets. Like Armstrong however, I thought that such spanning sets, and hence the range of space that was to be spanned, were to be discovered in the first instance by scientific empirical investigation. My loss of faith in the analytic-synthetic distinction was all the more painful because I had not realised that it had been based upon faith at all. Eventually, after much struggle to find a defence of the distinction, and despite finding many flaws in all the oft-recited arguments against its existence, I came at last to realise that my own belief in the analytic-synthetic distinction had been based upon the cardinal Wittgensteinian sin of presuming that my intuitions came with labels attached. This loss did not occur overnight, nor without much searching about for alternative justifications, and my master's thesis, written in the dying days of my faith, was a disconnected hodge-podge of various attempts to revive the distinction. My final rejection of the distinction came at a high price. Prior to rejecting it I had taken the production of (interesting) valid arguments to be an essential part of philosophical practice, and thought validity to be analyticity of the conditional. I was thus left without any account of why anyone should listen to anything I had to say, nor why I should listen to the pronouncements of others (particularly other philosophers). Scientific theories could still be recognised as having some merit, for they gave issue to predictions that turned out to be palpably correct, (though how this merit might be recognised ahead of time remained a mystery) but it seemed that philosophers had nothing of value to add to scientist's brute practices of modifying their theories in the light of accumulating evidence. Getting the right answer, making predictions that came true was the only standard by which theories were to be judged, and all the rest was suspected of being hot air. Though such a state is not conducive to wide reading, I scanned the liter- ature avidly for any hope of an alternative. Just because I did not have any account of the distinction between good and bad arguments, nor my ability to discern the difference, that did not imply that there was no such distinction to be made. (Concern that my only reason for believing this was an unfounded intuition that the contrary conditional was invalid was put aside for practical purposes.) At one time we were unable to account for the ability of chicken- sexers to discriminate between male and female chicks but chicken-sexers had the ability nonetheless and their exercise of it was a useful and productive en- terprise, though at least in their case there was an account of why it was useful. My investigation into the literature in hopes of an alternative account of the epistemic basis by which the valid arguments of a novel foreign tongue might CONTENTS 11 be identified revealed, to my surprise, that though the rejection of the analytic- synthetic distinction was almost universal and widely heralded, I was almost alone in being troubled by it. In hindsight I believe that this almost universal and curiously undogmatic slumber has two main historical causes: The first is the wide-spread rejection of the very idea of a sharp distinction between sci- ence and philosophy (which in turn is largely due to Quine's arguments that \One effect of abandoning them [i.e. the analytic-synthetic distinction and re- ductionism] is, as we shall see, a blurring of the supposed boundary between speculative metaphysics and natural science"), and the second was Lewis' ac- count of philosophical methodology as the systematisation and simplification of our pre-existing intuitions and the consequent extraordinary popularity of beginning philosophical papers with appeals to intuition. One of the oddities of the historical role of the belief that there is no sharp distinction between science and metaphysics is the extraordinary discrepancy between the arguments which have been taken to justify it, and the conclusions that philosophers have drawn from it. Though the most influential arguments for this belief are Quine's, and are entirely epistemic and based upon empiricist principles, philosophers have used this belief to justify the rankest unempiri- cal metaphysical speculation. Quine's point was that metaphysical speculations were to be judged by the same standard as scientific speculations | i.e. whether they contributed to the development of the simplest and strongest overall em- pirical theory fitting with our experiences. Good metaphysics, like good science, simplifies and clarifies, and bad metaphysics, like bad science, either breaks the fit with experience or pointlessly muddies the waters. The conclusion that many philosophers citing Quine as their authority for this belief appear to have drawn from it however, is that the most unempirical speculation deserves the same respect and credibility as science.
Recommended publications
  • At Least in Biophysical Novelties Amihud Gilead
    The Twilight of Determinism: At Least in Biophysical Novelties Amihud Gilead Department of Philosophy, Eshkol Tower, University of Haifa, Haifa 3498838 Email: [email protected] Abstract. In the 1990s, Richard Lewontin referred to what appeared to be the twilight of determinism in biology. He pointed out that DNA determines only a little part of life phenomena, which are very complex. In fact, organisms determine the environment and vice versa in a nonlinear way. Very recently, biophysicists, Shimon Marom and Erez Braun, have demonstrated that controlled biophysical systems have shown a relative autonomy and flexibility in response which could not be predicted. Within the boundaries of some restraints, most of them genetic, this freedom from determinism is well maintained. Marom and Braun have challenged not only biophysical determinism but also reverse-engineering, naive reductionism, mechanism, and systems biology. Metaphysically possibly, anything actual is contingent.1 Of course, such a possibility is entirely excluded in Spinoza’s philosophy as well as in many philosophical views at present. Kant believed that anything phenomenal, namely, anything that is experimental or empirical, is inescapably subject to space, time, and categories (such as causality) which entail the undeniable validity of determinism. Both Kant and Laplace assumed that modern science, such as Newton’s physics, must rely upon such a deterministic view. According to Kant, free will is possible not in the phenomenal world, the empirical world in which we 1 This is an assumption of a full-blown metaphysics—panenmentalism—whose author is Amihud Gilead. See Gilead 1999, 2003, 2009 and 2011, including literary, psychological, and natural applications and examples —especially in chemistry —in Gilead 2009, 2010, 2013, 2014a–c, and 2015a–d.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Armand Maurer. the Philosophy of William of Ockham in the Light of Its
    Armand Maurer. The Philosophy of William of Ockham in the Light of Its Principles. Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1999. Someone must be looking out for William Ockham. Excommunicated and exiled in his own lifetime, Ockham's philosophical works were revitalized in the twentieth century like those of no other medieval author. The two best medieval monographs of the century, from a philosophical point of view, were studies of Ockham.i And while the still unfinished Opera Omnia of Aquinas and Scotus plodded along, a brilliant group of scholars assembled in Olean, New York, to publish Ockham's Opera Philosophica et Theologica over a mere twenty-three years.ii And in a century that saw sophisticated bodies of philosophical scholarship grow up around the ancient and early modern periods, only Ockham among the medievals can lay claim to anything remotely analogous.iii Now Armand Maurer, at a mere 84 years of age, has managed to slip one more contribution into a century that, for Ockham Studies, was already venerable enough. It should be said from the start that Maurer's volume cannot compare, in philosophical detail and sophistication, with Marilyn Adams's even longer book on the subject. But this is nevertheless an important and valuable work. Maurer seeks to provide an introduction to Ockham's philosophy (10) and he succeeds entirely, in a manner worthy of comparison to Copleston and perhaps even Gilson. 1 It is surprisingly difficult to determine just what Maurer means by `the philosophy of Ockham.' He does not have in mind the medieval sense of `philosophy.' Though the volume begins with logic and metaphysics, and devotes a long chapter to physics, it is Ockham's Opera Theologica that receive most of Maurer's attention.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory and Reality
    an introduction to the philosophy of science ........................................................... SCIENCE AND ITS CONCEPTUAL FOUNDATIONS A SERIES EDITED BY DAVID L. HULL THEORY AND REALITY ........................................................... Peter Godfrey-Smith is associate professor of philosophy and of his­ tory and philosophy of science at Stanford University. He is the author PETER GODFREY-SMITH of Complexity and the Function ofMind in Nature. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 60637 The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London © 2003 by The University of Chicago All rights reserved. Published 2003 Printed in the United States of America 12 II 100908 45 ISBN: 0-226-30062-5 (cloth) ISBN: 0-226-30063-3 (paper) Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Godfrey-Smith, Peter. Theory and reality: an introduction to the philosophy of science I Peter Godfrey-Smith. p. cm. - (Science and its conceptual foundations) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-226-30062-5 (alk. paper) - ISBN 0-226-30063-3 (pbk. : alk. The University of Chicago Press / Chicago and London paper) I. Science-Philosophy. I. Title. II. Series. QI75 .G596 2003 501-dc2I 2002155305 @ The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the American National Standard for Information Sciences-Perma­ nence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39.48-1992. 56 Chapter Three Later (especially in chapter 14) I will return to these problems. But in the next chapter we will look at a philosophy that gets a good part of its motivation from the frustrations discussed in this chapter. Further Reading 4...................................................................................... Once again, Hempel's Aspects ofScientific Explanation (1965) is a key source, con­ Popper: Conjecture and Refutation taining a long (and exhausting) chapter on confirmation.
    [Show full text]
  • Block.What.Psch.States.Not.1972.Pdf
    Philosophical Review What Psychological States are Not Author(s): N. J. Block and J. A. Fodor Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 81, No. 2 (Apr., 1972), pp. 159-181 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2183991 Accessed: 08/09/2009 16:04 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review.
    [Show full text]
  • There Is No Pure Empirical Reasoning
    There Is No Pure Empirical Reasoning 1. Empiricism and the Question of Empirical Reasons Empiricism may be defined as the view there is no a priori justification for any synthetic claim. Critics object that empiricism cannot account for all the kinds of knowledge we seem to possess, such as moral knowledge, metaphysical knowledge, mathematical knowledge, and modal knowledge.1 In some cases, empiricists try to account for these types of knowledge; in other cases, they shrug off the objections, happily concluding, for example, that there is no moral knowledge, or that there is no metaphysical knowledge.2 But empiricism cannot shrug off just any type of knowledge; to be minimally plausible, empiricism must, for example, at least be able to account for paradigm instances of empirical knowledge, including especially scientific knowledge. Empirical knowledge can be divided into three categories: (a) knowledge by direct observation; (b) knowledge that is deductively inferred from observations; and (c) knowledge that is non-deductively inferred from observations, including knowledge arrived at by induction and inference to the best explanation. Category (c) includes all scientific knowledge. This category is of particular import to empiricists, many of whom take scientific knowledge as a sort of paradigm for knowledge in general; indeed, this forms a central source of motivation for empiricism.3 Thus, if there is any kind of knowledge that empiricists need to be able to account for, it is knowledge of type (c). I use the term “empirical reasoning” to refer to the reasoning involved in acquiring this type of knowledge – that is, to any instance of reasoning in which (i) the premises are justified directly by observation, (ii) the reasoning is non- deductive, and (iii) the reasoning provides adequate justification for the conclusion.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN Curriculum Vitae Last updated 3/6/2019 I. Personal and Academic History .................................................................................................................... 1 List of Degrees Earned ........................................................................................................................................................ 1 Title of Ph.D. Thesis ........................................................................................................................................................... 1 Positions held ..................................................................................................................................................................... 1 Invited lectures and lecture series ........................................................................................................................................ 1 List of Honors, Prizes ......................................................................................................................................................... 4 Research Grants .................................................................................................................................................................. 4 Non-Academic Publications ................................................................................................................................................ 5 II. Professional Activities .................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Mind Body Problem and Brandom's Analytic Pragmatism
    The Mind-Body Problem and Brandom’s Analytic Pragmatism François-Igor Pris [email protected] Erfurt University (Nordhäuserstraße 63, 99089 Erfurt, Germany) Abstract. I propose to solve the hard problem in the philosophy of mind by means of Brandom‟s notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. The explanatory gap between a phenomenal concept and the corresponding theoretical concept is a gap in the pragmatically mediated semantic relation between them. It is closed if we do not neglect the pragmatics. 1 Introduction In the second section, I will formulate the hard problem. In the third section, I will describe a pragmatic approach to the problem and propose to replace the classical non-normative physicalism/naturalism with a normative physicalism/naturalism of Wittgensteinian language games. In subsection 3.1, I will give a definition of a normative naturalism. In subsection 3.2, I will make some suggestions concerning an analytic interpretation of the second philosophy of Wittgenstein. In the fourth section, I will propose a solution to the hard problem within Brandom‟s analytic pragmatism by using the notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. In the fifth section, I will make some suggestions about possible combinatorics related to pragmatically mediated semantic relations. In the sixth section, I will consider pragmatic and discursive versions of the mind-body identity M=B. In the last section, I will conclude that the explanatory gap is a gap in a pragmatically mediated semantic relation between B and M. It is closed if we do not neglect pragmatics. 2 The Hard Problem The hard problem in the philosophy of mind can be formulated as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Ingenuity in Mathematics Ross Honsberger 10.1090/Nml/023
    AMS / MAA ANNELI LAX NEW MATHEMATICAL LIBRARY VOL 23 Ingenuity in Mathematics Ross Honsberger 10.1090/nml/023 INGENUITY IN MATHEMAmCS NEW MATHEMATICAL LIBRARY PUBLISHED BY THEMATHEMATICAL ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA Editorial Committee Basil Gordon, Chairman (1975-76) Anneli Lax, Editor University of California, L.A. New York University Ivan Niven (1 975-77) University of Oregon M. M. Schiffer (1975-77) Stanford University The New Mathematical Library (NML) was begun in 1961 by the School Mathematics Study Group to make available to high school students short expository books on various topics not usually covered in the high school syllabus. In a decade the NML matured into a steadily growing series of some twenty titles of interest not only to the originally intended audience, but to college students and teachers at all levels. Previously published by Random House and L. W. Singer, the NML became a publication series of the Mathematical Association of America (MAA) in 1975. Under the auspices of the MAA the NML will continue to grow and will remain dedicated to its original and expanded purposes. INGENUITY IN MATHEMATICS by Ross Honsberger University of Waterloo, Canada 23 MATHEMATICAL ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA Illustrated by George H. Buehler Sixth Printing © Copyright 1970, by the Mathematical Association of America A11 rights reserved under International and Pan-American Copyright Conventions. Published in Washington by The Mathematical Association of America Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 77-134351 Print ISBN 978-0-88385-623-9 Electronic ISBN 978-0-88385-938-4 Manufactured in the United States of America Note to the Reader his book is one of a series written by professional mathematicians Tin order to make some important mathematical ideas interesting and understandable to a large audience of high school students and laymen.
    [Show full text]
  • The Law and the Brain: Judging Scientific Evidence of Intent
    The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process Volume 1 Issue 2 Article 4 1999 The Law and the Brain: Judging Scientific videnceE of Intent Erica Beecher-Monas Edgar Garcia-Rill Follow this and additional works at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/appellatepracticeprocess Part of the Evidence Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, and the Science and Technology Law Commons Recommended Citation Erica Beecher-Monas and Edgar Garcia-Rill, The Law and the Brain: Judging Scientific videnceE of Intent, 1 J. APP. PRAC. & PROCESS 243 (1999). Available at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/appellatepracticeprocess/vol1/iss2/4 This document is brought to you for free and open access by Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process by an authorized administrator of Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE LAW AND THE BRAIN: JUDGING SCIENTIFIC EVIDENCE OF INTENT Erica Beecher-Monas* and Edgar Garcia-Rill, Ph.D.** INTRODUCTION As evidentiary gatekeepers, judges must be ready to evaluate expert testimony about science and the brain. A wide variety of cases present issues of mental state, many doubtless with battling experts seeking to testify on these issues. This poses a dilemma for nonspecialist judges. How is a nonscientist to judge scientific evidence? How can a nonscientist decide if testimony about mental state meets the criteria of good science? This essay offers a general overview of the issue of evaluating scientific evidence and is aimed at exploring the issues involved, but not attempting easy answers. Of necessity, this requires thinking about how science works.
    [Show full text]
  • History and Theory of Philosophy
    FEDERAL STATE BUDGETARY EDUCATIONAL INSTITUTION OF HIGHER EDUCATION "BASHKIR STATE MEDICAL UNIVERSITY" OF THE MINISTRY OF HEALTHCARE OF THE RUSSIAN FEDERATION (FSBEI HE BSMU MOH Russia) HISTORY AND THEORY OF PHILOSOPHY Textbook Ufa 2020 1 UDC 1(09)(075.8) BBC 87.3я7 H90 Reviewers: Doctor of Philosophy, Professor, Head of the department «Social work» FSBEI HE «Bashkir State University» U.S. Vildanov Doctor of Philosophy, Professor at the Department of Philosophy and History FSBEIHE «Bashkir State Agricultural University» A.I. Stoletov History and theory of philosophy:textbook/ K.V. Khramova, H90 R.I. Devyatkina, Z.R. Sadikova, O.M. Ivanova, O.G. Afanasyeva, A.S. Zubairova-Valeeva, N.R. Mingazova, G.R. Davletshina — Ufa: Ufa: FSBEIHEBSMUMOHRussia, 2020. – 127 p. The manual was prepared in accordance with the requirements of the Federal State Educational Standard of Higher Education in specialty 31.05.01 «General Medicine» the current curriculum and on the basis of the work program on the discipline of philosophy. The manual is focused on the competence-based learning model. It has an original, uniform for all classes structure, including the topic, a summary of the training questions, the subject of essays, training materials, test items with response standards, recommended literature. This manual covers topics related to the periods of development of world philosophy. Designed for students in the specialty 31.05.01 «General Medicine». It is recommended to be published by the Coordinating Scientific and Methodological Council and was approved by the decision of the Editorial and Publishing Council of the BSMU of the Ministry of Healthcare of Russia.
    [Show full text]
  • The Modal Logic of Potential Infinity, with an Application to Free Choice
    The Modal Logic of Potential Infinity, With an Application to Free Choice Sequences Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Ethan Brauer, B.A. ∼6 6 Graduate Program in Philosophy The Ohio State University 2020 Dissertation Committee: Professor Stewart Shapiro, Co-adviser Professor Neil Tennant, Co-adviser Professor Chris Miller Professor Chris Pincock c Ethan Brauer, 2020 Abstract This dissertation is a study of potential infinity in mathematics and its contrast with actual infinity. Roughly, an actual infinity is a completed infinite totality. By contrast, a collection is potentially infinite when it is possible to expand it beyond any finite limit, despite not being a completed, actual infinite totality. The concept of potential infinity thus involves a notion of possibility. On this basis, recent progress has been made in giving an account of potential infinity using the resources of modal logic. Part I of this dissertation studies what the right modal logic is for reasoning about potential infinity. I begin Part I by rehearsing an argument|which is due to Linnebo and which I partially endorse|that the right modal logic is S4.2. Under this assumption, Linnebo has shown that a natural translation of non-modal first-order logic into modal first- order logic is sound and faithful. I argue that for the philosophical purposes at stake, the modal logic in question should be free and extend Linnebo's result to this setting. I then identify a limitation to the argument for S4.2 being the right modal logic for potential infinity.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Analysis on the Nature and Forms of Information—From the Perspective of Marxist Philosophy †
    Proceedings Philosophical Analysis on the Nature and Forms of Information—From the Perspective of Marxist Philosophy † Mingfang Feng 1 and Liang Feng 2,* 1 School of Economics & Law, Shaanxi University of Technology, No.1, First Eastern Ring Road, Hanzhong 723001, China; [email protected] 2 School of Marxism Studies, Xi’an Jiaotong University, No.28 Xianning West Road, Xi’an 710049, China * Correspondence: [email protected] † Presented at the IS4SI 2017 Summit DIGITALISATION FOR A SUSTAINABLE SOCIETY, Gothenburg, Sweden, 12–16 June 2017. Published: 8 June 2017 Abstract: The aim of this research essay attempt to reveal the nature of information form the perspective of Marxist Philosophy. The nature of Information is the first question that philosophy of information science and technology research must be answered, thus the problem is still debated. According to Marxist dialectical materialism method to the essence of information has made the analysis and argumentation, points out the essence of information between what is and its internal contact things, and this contact information is presented. Due to the connection between the protean and endless things, thus produce the endless, full of beautiful things in eyes, each are not identical information. To grasp the nature of information, must pay attention to and the specific form of information and information processing, the reorganization, transmission, storage, use and so on. Keywords: information; nature; connection; philosophy of information 1. Introduction The development of information science and technology has spar ked the nature of information exploration after World War II. The question that ‘What is the nature of information?’ is always unable to avoid in information science and philosophical technology research.
    [Show full text]