Evaluating Cognitive Models and Architectures

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Evaluating Cognitive Models and Architectures Evaluating Cognitive Models and Architectures Marc Halbrugge¨ Human Factors Institute, Universitat¨ der Bundeswehr Munchen¨ [email protected] Abstract problem. While this is a recommendable request, it is hard to verify that the modeler has complied with it. Cognitive modeling is a promising research area combining the fields of psychology and artificial intelligence. Cognitive • Underlying theories. A special case of the irrelevant spec- models have been successfully applied to different topics like ification problem can occur when the architecture incor- theory generation in psychology, usability testing in human- porates knowledge from previous research, for example computer interface research, and cognitive tutoring in algebra Fitts’ law (Fitts 1954) about the time needed to perform a teaching. rapid movement of the forearm. These underlying empir- This paper is focused on two major problems concerning the ical laws may provide a big part of the fit of the cognitive evaluation of cognitive models and architectures. First, it is model in question. shown that current approaches to quantify model complex- ity are not sufficient and second, the claim is reinforced that • Interpretability. Most of the time, one needs to look at the flexibility of cognitive architectures leads to the problem the code of a model in order to understand what it really that they cannot be falsified and are therefore too weak to be does. As many psychologists do not hold a degree in com- considered as theories. puter science, this hinders them from participating in the cognitive modeling research field. Cognitive architectures The usage of a cognitive architecture – as opposed to From a psychologist’s point of view, the main goal of cog- modeling everything from scratch – does not solve these nitive modeling is to simulate human cognition. A cognitive problems completely, but weakens them noticeably. Cogni- model is seen as an instantiation of a theory in a computa- tive architectures are subject to social control by the research tional form. This can then be used to test a certain theory community. This way, theory compliance, interpretability, empirically. and rejection of irrelevant parts are enforced at least on the Cognitive architectures like SOAR (Laird, Newell, & level of the architecture. Rosenbloom 1987), EPIC (Kieras & Meyer 1997), and ACT- An informative evaluation of cognitive models has been R (Anderson et al. 2004) are useful frameworks for the cre- done by Gluck & Pew (2005). They applied several cogni- ation of cognitive models. In addition, they are often re- tive architectures to the same task and compared the result- garded as useful steps towards a unified theory of cognition ing models not only with regard to goodness-of-fit but also (Newell 1990). to modeling methodology, features and implied assumptions When a computational model is used to evaluate a theory, of the particular architecture, and the role of parameter tun- the main goal is (generalizable) concordance with human ing during the modeling process. data. But this is not a sufficient proof of the theory. The This approach of Gluck & Pew is well suited for address- following problems are often stated in the literature: ing the problems of model evaluation besides goodness-of- fit and therefore I’ll recommend it as standard practice. • Compliance with the theory. The underlying theory and its implementation (in a cognitive architecture) may di- verge. Evaluation methodology for cognitive models • Irrelevant specification (Reitman 1965). Most of the I stated above that from a psychologist’s point of view models need to make additional assumptions. It is very concordance with human data is the main goal of cog- hard to tell which parts of the model are responsible for nitive modeling. This concordance is typically assessed its overall performance and which parts may be obsolete. by computing goodness-of-fit indices. This approach has Newell (1990) demanded to “listen to the architecture” been critized sharply during the last years (Roberts & Pash- when creating new models in order to get around this ler 2000), initiating a discussion that concluded with the joint statement that a good fit is necessary, but not suffi- Copyright c 2007, Association for the Advancement of Artificial cient for the validity of a model (Rodgers & Rowe 2002; Intelligence (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. Roberts & Pashler 2002). 27 In order to assess the fit of a model or to compare fits Model 2 consists of four states represented by chunks a, between models, it is important to be aware of the complex- b, c and d. The productions allow state transitions from ity of the models. Models with many degrees of freedom every state to its single successor (a→b, b→c, c→d, d→a). usually achieve better fits, but bear the risk of overfitting, Notice that although the second model looks determinis- the siamese twin of the irrelevant specification problem de- tic, the retrieval failure that breaks the cycle of firings may scribed in the previous section. In addition, the principle appear at any moment. All of the four activation weights are of parsimony demands to prefer a less complex model to a equally important for the outcome of the model. more complex one, given comparable fit. Therefore mea- Production utility learning is not used in the models. The surements of complexity are needed. only influential weights are the activations of the chunks. Pitt, Myung, & Zhang (2002) have developed statistics for Now the question of model complexity shall be addressed: model selection that take into account both goodness-of-fit According to the weight counting approach (Baker, Corbett, and complexity. These statistics aim at closed form mathe- & Koedinger 2003), the second model is more complex than matical models, where fitting means to choose the member the first one. It uses more memory objects with each single of a class of functions that represents some empirical data one being associated with a numerical activation. But be- best. Examples for this type of model range from simple cause of the arrangement of states and productions (see fig- linear regression to complex neural networks. ure 1), this model can only create outputs of the form abcd- In order to expand the notion of complexity to cognitive abcda and so on. The first model in contrast can output models, Baker, Corbett, & Koedinger (2003) used the num- any sequence of a’s and b’s. Therefore model 1 should be ber of free weights of the subsymbolic part of an ACT-R considered the more complex one. model as measure of the degress of freedom of the model. Even if model run time is used as dependent variable, you As will be show in the following, this is not sufficient. can spot the difference in complexity. Imagine that two of While some parts of cognitive models can be described by the four possible transitions in the models take a lot of time mathematical formulas (i.e. retrieval latencies, spreading ac- compared to the other two (i.e. 1000 ms vs. 100 ms). While tivation), they also include an algorithmic part. Additional the overall distribution of the run time will stay comparable degrees of freedom can emerge from the algorithmic struc- for the two models, the second model will only be able to ture of a model. Therefore the complexity of a model can produce a limited set of values (i.e. 100, 1100, 1200, 2200, not be adequately quantified by the number of numerical 2300). weights in its implementation. In order to test this, I created the two models,1 ran each one 10000 times and recorded the simulated run time. The Example: Memory retrieval in ACT-R results are displayed in figure 2. The greater restriction of This claim shall be illustrated by an example. Imagine two model 2 is apparent. simple cognitive models using ACT-R, both of them retriev- A close inspection of the models reveals that model 2 pos- ing a series of chunks from declarative memory. Which sesses just one degree of freedom – the total run time: De- chunk is to be retrieved next depends on the production that pending on the noisy chunk activation, the model may run currently fires. The models stop when the memory retrieval shorter or longer. But when the number of states visited dur- fails which depends mostly on the amount of noise added to ing a run is known, the sequence of states is known as well. chunk activation. On the other hand, model 1 has more degrees of freedom Both models consist of four productions (resembling four because it can take multiple paths of production firings to state transitions), but differ in their number of chunks in the reach a specific state at a given position in the sequence of declarative memory. The structures of the models are dis- states. played in figure 1. Taken together, the example provides two important find- ings: • Even for two simple models as the ones described above (about 100 lines of code each), it is very hard to assess the model complexity when only the number of chunks and productions is known. In order to be able to judge a model, one has to look into the code. Model 1 Model 2 • Knowledge of numerical parameters is not sufficient for the estimation of model complexity as more degrees of Figure 1: Structure of the two models. Circles represent the freedom can emerge from the algorithmic structure. internal states, arrows productions. Initial and final states The strategy of “eliminating parameter estimation” (An- and corresponding productions are not shown. derson et al. 2004, p. 1057) in order to deal with the criti- cism of model fitting (Roberts & Pashler 2000) falls short Model 1 consists of two states a and b, represented by in this case.
Recommended publications
  • A Distributed Computational Cognitive Model for Object Recognition
    SCIENCE CHINA xx xxxx Vol. xx No. x: 1{15 doi: A Distributed Computational Cognitive Model for Object Recognition Yong-Jin Liu1∗, Qiu-Fang Fu2, Ye Liu2 & Xiaolan Fu2 1Tsinghua National Laboratory for Information Science and Technology, Department of Computer Science and Technology, Tsinghua University, Beijing 100084, China, 2State Key Lab of Brain and Cognitive Science, Institute of Psychology, Chinese Academy of Sciences, Beijing 100101, China Received Month Day, Year; accepted Month Day, Year Abstract Based on cognitive functionalities in human vision processing, we propose a computational cognitive model for object recognition with detailed algorithmic descriptions. The contribution of this paper is of two folds. Firstly, we present a systematic review on psychological and neurophysiological studies, which provide collective evidence for a distributed representation of 3D objects in the human brain. Secondly, we present a computational model which simulates the distributed mechanism of object vision pathway. Experimental results show that the presented computational cognitive model outperforms five representative 3D object recognition algorithms in computer science research. Keywords distributed cognition, computational model, object recognition, human vision system 1 Introduction Object recognition is one of fundamental tasks in computer vision. Many recognition algorithms have been proposed in computer science area (e.g., [1, 2, 3, 4, 5]). While the CPU processing speed can now be reached at 109 Hz, the human brain has a limited speed of 100 Hz at which the neurons process their input. However, compared to state-of-the-art computational algorithms for object recognition, human brain has a distinct advantage in object recognition, i.e., human being can accurately recognize one from unlimited variety of objects within a fraction of a second, even if the object is partially occluded or contaminated by noises.
    [Show full text]
  • The Place of Modeling in Cognitive Science
    The place of modeling in cognitive science James L. McClelland Department of Psychology and Center for Mind, Brain, and Computation Stanford University James L. McClelland Department of Psychology Stanford University Stanford, CA 94305 650-736-4278 (v) / 650-725-5699 (f) [email protected] Running Head: Modeling in cognitive science Keywords: Modeling frameworks, computer simulation, connectionist models, Bayesian approaches, dynamical systems, symbolic models of cognition, hybrid models, cognitive architectures Abstract I consider the role of cognitive modeling in cognitive science. Modeling, and the computers that enable it, are central to the field, but the role of modeling is often misunderstood. Models are not intended to capture fully the processes they attempt to elucidate. Rather, they are explorations of ideas about the nature of cognitive processes. As explorations, simplification is essential – it is only through simplification that we can fully understand the implications of the ideas. This is not to say that simplification has no downsides; it does, and these are discussed. I then consider several contemporary frameworks for cognitive modeling, stressing the idea that each framework is useful in its own particular ways. Increases in computer power (by a factor of about 4 million) since 1958 have enabled new modeling paradigms to emerge, but these also depend on new ways of thinking. Will new paradigms emerge again with the next 1,000-fold increase? 1. Introduction With the inauguration of a new journal for cognitive science, thirty years after the first meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, it seems essential to consider the role of computational modeling in our discipline.
    [Show full text]
  • A Bayesian Computational Cognitive Model ∗
    A Bayesian Computational Cognitive Model ∗ Zhiwei Shi Hong Hu Zhongzhi Shi Key Laboratory of Intelligent Information Processing Institute of Computing Technology, CAS, China Kexueyuan Nanlu #6, Beijing, China 100080 {shizw, huhong, shizz}@ics.ict.ac.cn Abstract problem solving capability and provide meaningful insights into mechanisms of human intelligence. Computational cognitive modeling has recently Besides the two categories of models, recently, there emerged as one of the hottest issues in the AI area. emerges a novel approach, hybrid neural-symbolic system, Both symbolic approaches and connectionist ap- which concerns the use of problem-specific symbolic proaches present their merits and demerits. Al- knowledge within the neurocomputing paradigm [d'Avila though Bayesian method is suggested to incorporate Garcez et al., 2002]. This new approach shows that both advantages of the two kinds of approaches above, modal logics and temporal logics can be effectively repre- there is no feasible Bayesian computational model sented in artificial neural networks [d'Avila Garcez and concerning the entire cognitive process by now. In Lamb, 2004]. this paper, we propose a variation of traditional Different from the hybrid approach above, we adopt Bayesian network, namely Globally Connected and Bayesian network [Pearl, 1988] to integrate the merits of Locally Autonomic Bayesian Network (GCLABN), rule-based systems and neural networks, due to its virtues as to formally describe a plausible cognitive model. follows. On the one hand, by encoding concepts
    [Show full text]
  • Connectionist Models of Language Processing
    Cognitive Studies Preprint 2003, Vol. 10, No. 1, 10–28 Connectionist Models of Language Processing Douglas L. T. Rohde David C. Plaut Massachusetts Institute of Technology Carnegie Mellon University Traditional approaches to language processing have been based on explicit, discrete represen- tations which are difficult to learn from a reasonable linguistic environment—hence, it has come to be accepted that much of our linguistic representations and knowledge is innate. With its focus on learning based upon graded, malleable, distributed representations, connectionist modeling has reopened the question of what could be learned from the environment in the ab- sence of detailed innate knowledge. This paper provides an overview of connectionist models of language processing, at both the lexical and sentence levels. Although connectionist models have been applied to the full and processes of actual language users: Language is as lan- range of perceptual, cognitive, and motor domains (see Mc- guage does. In this regard, errors in performance (e.g., “slips Clelland, Rumelhart, & PDP Research Group, 1986; Quin- of the tongue”; Dell, Schwartz, Martin, Saffran, & Gagnon, lan, 1991; McLeod, Plunkett, & Rolls, 1998), it is in their 1997) are no less valid than skilled language use as a measure application to language that they have evoked the most in- of the underlying nature of language processing. The goal is terest and controversy (e.g., Pinker & Mehler, 1988). This not to abstract away from performance but to articulate com- is perhaps not surprising in light of the special role that lan- putational principles that account for it. guage plays in human cognition and culture.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Psychology for Deep Neural Networks: a Shape Bias Case Study
    Cognitive Psychology for Deep Neural Networks: A Shape Bias Case Study Samuel Ritter * 1 David G.T. Barrett * 1 Adam Santoro 1 Matt M. Botvinick 1 Abstract to think of these models as black boxes, and to question whether they can be understood at all (Bornstein, 2016; Deep neural networks (DNNs) have advanced Lipton, 2016). This opacity obstructs both basic research performance on a wide range of complex tasks, seeking to improve these models, and applications of these rapidly outpacing our understanding of the na- models to real world problems (Caruana et al., 2015). ture of their solutions. While past work sought to advance our understanding of these models, Recent pushes have aimed to better understand DNNs: none has made use of the rich history of problem tailor-made loss functions and architectures produce more descriptions, theories, and experimental methods interpretable features (Higgins et al., 2016; Raposo et al., developed by cognitive psychologists to study 2017) while output-behavior analyses unveil previously the human mind. To explore the potential value opaque operations of these networks (Karpathy et al., of these tools, we chose a well-established analy- 2015). Parallel to this work, neuroscience-inspired meth- sis from developmental psychology that explains ods such as activation visualization (Li et al., 2015), abla- how children learn word labels for objects, and tion analysis (Zeiler & Fergus, 2014) and activation maxi- applied that analysis to DNNs. Using datasets mization (Yosinski et al., 2015) have also been applied. of stimuli inspired by the original cognitive psy- Altogether, this line of research developed a set of promis- chology experiments, we find that state-of-the-art ing tools for understanding DNNs, each paper producing one shot learning models trained on ImageNet a glimmer of insight.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Modeling, Symbolic
    Cognitive modeling, symbolic Lewis, R.L. (1999). Cognitive modeling, symbolic. In Wilson, R. and Keil, F. (eds.), The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Symbolic cognitive models are theories of human cognition that take the form of working computer programs. A cognitive model is intended to be an explanation of how some aspect of cognition is accomplished by a set of primitive computational processes. A model performs a specific cognitive task or class of tasks and produces behavior that constitutes a set of predictions that can be compared to data from human performance. Task domains that have received considerable attention include problem solving, language comprehension, memory tasks, and human-device interaction. The scientific questions cognitive modeling seeks to answer belong to cognitive psychology, and the computational techniques are often drawn from artificial intelligence. Cognitive modeling differs from other forms of theorizing in psychology in its focus on functionality and computational completeness. Cognitive modeling produces both a theory of human behavior on a task and a computational artifact that performs the task. The theoretical foundation of cognitive modeling is the idea that cognition is a kind of COMPUTATION (see also COMPUTATIONAL THEORY OF MIND). The claim is that what the mind does, in part, is perform cognitive tasks by computing. (The claim is not that the computer is a metaphor for the mind, or that the architectures of modern digital computers can give us insights into human mental architecture.) If this is the case, then it must be possible to explain cognition as a dynamic unfolding of computational processes.
    [Show full text]
  • Connectionist Models of Cognition Michael S. C. Thomas and James L
    Connectionist models of cognition Michael S. C. Thomas and James L. McClelland 1 1. Introduction In this chapter, we review computer models of cognition that have focused on the use of neural networks. These architectures were inspired by research into how computation works in the brain and subsequent work has produced models of cognition with a distinctive flavor. Processing is characterized by patterns of activation across simple processing units connected together into complex networks. Knowledge is stored in the strength of the connections between units. It is for this reason that this approach to understanding cognition has gained the name of connectionism. 2. Background Over the last twenty years, connectionist modeling has formed an influential approach to the computational study of cognition. It is distinguished by its appeal to principles of neural computation to inspire the primitives that are included in its cognitive level models. Also known as artificial neural network (ANN) or parallel distributed processing (PDP) models, connectionism has been applied to a diverse range of cognitive abilities, including models of memory, attention, perception, action, language, concept formation, and reasoning (see, e.g., Houghton, 2005). While many of these models seek to capture adult function, connectionism places an emphasis on learning internal representations. This has led to an increasing focus on developmental phenomena and the origins of knowledge. Although, at its heart, connectionism comprises a set of computational formalisms,
    [Show full text]
  • Artificial Intelligence and Cognitive Science Have the Same Problem
    Artificial Intelligence and Cognitive Science have the Same Problem Nicholas L. Cassimatis Department of Cognitive Science, Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute 108 Carnegie, 110 8th St. Troy, NY 12180 [email protected] Abstract other features of human-level cognition. Therefore, not Cognitive scientists attempting to explain human understanding how the relatively simple and “unintelligent” intelligence share a puzzle with artificial intelligence mechanisms of atoms and molecules combine to create researchers aiming to create computers that exhibit human- intelligent behavior is a major challenge for a naturalistic level intelligence: how can a system composed of relatively world view (upon which much cognitive science is based). unintelligent parts (such as neurons or transistors) behave Perhaps it is the last major challenge. Surmounting the intelligently? I argue that although cognitive science has human-level intelligence problem also has enormous made significant progress towards many of its goals, that technological benefits which are obvious enough. solving the puzzle of intelligence requires special standards and methods in addition to those already employed in cognitive science. To promote such research, I suggest The State of the Science creating a subfield within cognitive science called For these reasons, understanding how the human brain intelligence science and propose some guidelines for embodies a solution to the human-level intelligence research addressing the intelligence puzzle. problem is an important goal of cognitive science. At least at first glance, we are nowhere near achieving this goal. There are no cognitive models that can, for example, fully The Intelligence Problem understand language or solve problems that are simple for a Cognitive scientists attempting to fully understand human young child.
    [Show full text]
  • Models of Cognition: Neurological Possiblity Does Not Indicate Neurological Plausibility
    UC Merced Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society Title Models of Cognition: Neurological Possiblity Does Not Indicate Neurological Plausibility Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/26t9426g Journal Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, 27(27) ISSN 1069-7977 Authors Kriete, Trenton E. Noelle, David C. Publication Date 2005 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Models of Cognition: Neurological possibility does not indicate neurological plausibility. Peter R. Krebs ([email protected]) Cognitive Science Program School of History & Philosophy of Science The University of New South Wales Sydney, NSW 2052, Australia Abstract level cognitive functions like the detection of syntactic and semantic features for words (Elman, 1990, 1993), Many activities in Cognitive Science involve complex learning the past tense of English verbs (Rumelhart and computer models and simulations of both theoretical and real entities. Artificial Intelligence and the study McClelland, 1996), or cognitive development (McLeod of artificial neural nets in particular, are seen as ma- et al., 1998; Schultz, 2003). SRNs have even been jor contributors in the quest for understanding the hu- suggested as a suitable platform \toward a cognitive man mind. Computational models serve as objects of neurobiology of the moral virtues" (Churchland, 1998). experimentation, and results from these virtual experi- ments are tacitly included in the framework of empiri- While some of the models go back a decade or more, cal science. Cognitive functions, like learning to speak, there is still great interest in some of these `classics', or discovering syntactical structures in language, have and similar models are still being developed, e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Artificial Neural Nets
    Artificial Neural Nets: a critical analysis of their effectiveness as empirical technique for cognitive modelling Peter R. Krebs A thesis submitted in fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. University of New South Wales August 2007 COPYRIGHT, AUTHENTICITY, and ORIGINALITY STATEMENT I hereby grant the University of New South Wales or its agents the right to archive and to make available my thesis or dissertation in whole or part in the University libraries in all forms of media, now or here after known, subject to the provisions of the Copyright Act 1968. I retain all proprietary rights, such as patent rights. I also retain the right to use in future works (such as articles or books) all or part of this thesis or dissertation. I also authorise University Microfilms to use the 350 word abstract of my thesis in Dissertation Abstract International. I have either used no substantial portions of copyright material in my thesis or I have obtained permission to use copyright material; where permission has not been granted I have applied/will apply for a partial restric- tion of the digital copy of my thesis or dissertation, and I certify that the Library deposit digital copy is a direct equivalent of the final officially approved version of my thesis. No emendation of content has occurred and if there are any minor variations in formatting, they are the result of the conversion to digital format, and I hereby declare that this submission is my own work and to the best of my knowledge it contains no materials previously published or written by another person, or substantial proportions of material which have been accepted for the award of any other degree or diploma at UNSW or any other educational institution, except where due acknowledgment is made in the thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • A Cognitive Model of Drivers Attention
    A Cognitive Model of Drivers Attention Kerstin Sophie Haring ([email protected]) Research Center for Advanced Science and Technology, The University of Tokyo 4-6-1, Komaba, Meguro-ku, Tokyo, 153-8904, Japan Marco Ragni ([email protected]) Lars Konieczny ([email protected]) Center for Cognitive Science, University of Freiburg Friedrichstr. 50, 79098 Freiburg, Germany Abstract open source LISP, which not only guarantees support and accountability, but also enables the research community to Cognitive architectures can account for highly complex tasks. One of the greatest challenges is understanding and modeling use the developed model for further research. It is able to human driving behavior. This paper describes an integrated keep a traffic lane, initiate and decide about a change of the cognitive model of human attention during the performance lane in case of upfront traffic, identify prevalent situations at of car driving. In this task, the attention process can be crossroads and react to traffic signs. divided into at least three basic components: the control process, the monitoring process, and finally, the decision making process. Of these basic tasks, the first has the highest priority. All three phases are implemented in a cognitive model in the cognitive Architecture ACT-R 6.0. The model is able to keep a traffic lane, overtake another vehicle by lane change, identifies traffic signs and different situations emerging at crossroads. Keywords: Driver behavior model; cognitive architecture; ACT-R; Attention Introduction Even for long-time practitioners driving a car is a highly complex task. This becomes evident by the still high number of accidents.
    [Show full text]
  • Using Recurrent Neural Networks to Understand Human Reward Learning
    Using Recurrent Neural Networks to Understand Human Reward Learning Mingyu Song ([email protected]), Yael Niv ([email protected]) Princeton Neuroscience Institute, Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08540, United States Ming Bo Cai ([email protected]) International Research Center for Neurointelligence, (WPI-IRCN), UTIAS, The University of Tokyo Bunkyo City, Tokyo 113-0033, Japan Abstract Understandably, most cognitive modeling work focus on relative model comparison, which identifies the best-fit model Computational models are greatly useful in cognitive science in revealing the mechanisms of learning and decision making. out of a number of alternatives under consideration. Studies However, it is hard to know whether all meaningful variance do not, however, commonly evaluate the absolute goodness in behavior has been account for by the best-fit model selected of fit of models, or estimate how far they are from the best through model comparison. In this work, we propose to use recurrent neural networks (RNNs) to assess the limits of pre- possible model. In theory, there exists an upper bound for dictability afforded by a model of behavior, and reveal what (if model log likelihood (i.e., the negative entropy of the data anything) is missing in the cognitive models. We apply this ap- (Cover, 1999)). However, estimating this bound is practically proach in a complex reward-learning task with a large choice space and rich individual variability. The RNN models outper- impossible in sequential tasks, because the exact same expe- form the best known cognitive model through the entire learn- rience is never repeated (it may be possible, however, in sim- ing phase.
    [Show full text]