Gitik Used a Cardinal

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Gitik Used a Cardinal TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 353, Number 12, Pages 4863{4897 S 0002-9947(01)02853-7 Article electronically published on July 17, 2001 A MEASURABLE CARDINAL WITH A CLOSED UNBOUNDED SET OF INACCESSIBLES FROM o(κ)=κ WILLIAM MITCHELL Abstract. We prove that o(κ)=κ is sufficient to construct a model V [C]in which κ is measurable and C is a closed and unbounded subset of κ containing only inaccessible cardinals of V . Gitik proved that o(κ)=κ is necessary. We also calculate the consistency strength of the existence of such a set C together with the assumption that κ is Mahlo, weakly compact, or Ramsey. In addition we consider the possibility of having the set C generate the closed unbounded ultrafilter of V while κ remains measurable, and show that Radin forcing, which requires a weak repeat point, cannot be improved on. 1. Introduction In [2], Gitik used a cardinal κ with o(κ)=κ + 1 to give a forcing construction of amodelV [C]inwhichκ is measurable, while the set C is closed and unbounded in κ and contains only inaccessibles of V . Gitik also showed that no such construction is possible unless o(κ) ≥ κ in K. The main result of this paper is that the lower bound o(κ)=κ is correct: Theorem 1.1. The following are equiconsistent: 1. There is a cardinal κ with oK (κ)=κ. 2. There is a measurable cardinal κ andaclosedunboundedsubsetC of κ such that each member of C is inaccessible in K. We begin with a proof of Gitik's result that 1.1(2) implies that o(κ)=κ in the core model K. This proof is essentially the same as that of Gitik, but is reorganized to feature the Prikry generic sequence more prominently. Afterward we will reexamine the proof to gain some further insight into the general problem. The proof depends on the following lemma: Lemma 1.2. Suppose that ~κ =(κn : n<!) is K-generic for Prikry forcing by a measure U 2 K on κ, and suppose that each κn is inaccessible and has a closed and K unbounded subset Cn containing only cardinals inaccessible in K.Theno (κ) ≥ κ. In order to see that the lemma implies the direction (2)=)(1) of theorem 1.1, let κ and C be as in clause 1.1(2). Using the measure on κ, force to add a Prikry sequence ( κn : n<!) cofinal in κ. For all but finitely many n 2 !,thesetCn = C \ κn is a closed and unbounded subset of κn containing only inaccessibles of K, and hence the lemma implies that oK (κ) ≥ κ. Received by the editors March 30, 2001. 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 03E35, 03E45, 03E55. This work was partially supported by grant number DMS-962-6143 from the National Science Foundation. c 2001 American Mathematical Society 4863 License or copyright restrictions may apply to redistribution; see https://www.ams.org/journal-terms-of-use 4864 WILLIAM MITCHELL Proof of lemma 1.2. Assume, towards a contradiction, that δ = oK (κ) <κ. In order to allow a generalization of the proof, we will not use the assumption that ~κ is a Prikry sequence until the end of the proof. We begin by applying the covering lemma [3]. Let X be a precovering set such that ( κn : n<!) 2 X and ( Cn : n 2 ! ) 2 X and such that X contains all of its limit ordinals of cofinality at most δ. The assertion that X is a precovering set means that jXj <κ,thatX ≺ Vτ for some τ>κ=supκn,andthatX satisfies a certain closure condition. The covering lemma asserts that such a precovering set exists, and that if X is any such precovering set, then there is a function h 2 K,an X ordinal ρ<κ,andasystemSC of indiscernibles for K with the following properties, wherewewriteCX (λ)for CX(λ, β). β<oK (λ) 1. domain(C)= (α, β) 2 X : β<oK (α) ,andC(α, β) ⊂{ν 2 α \X : oK (ν)= β g. 2. If ν 2 X nρ, then either ν 2 h\ν or else ν 2CX(λ)whereλ =inf(h\ν nν) ≤ κ. 3. For any λ 2 X, CX (λ)isclosedinX \ λ. K 4.S If β0 <o (λ)andν is a ordinal of cofinality ! which is a limit point of CX (λ, β), then ν 2CX(λ, β)forsomeβ>β. β≥β0 0 5. If ν 2CX (λ) [fλg and CX (λ) is bounded in X \ ν, then there is η 2 X \ ν such that h\η is cofinal in X \ ν. We can assume, without loss of generality, that ρ<κ0.Foreachn<!,let λn be the least member of X \ h\κn.Thenκn ≤ λn ≤ κ,andifλn >κn,then X κn 2C (λn). The proof of lemma 1.2 relies on two observations: X Claim 1.3. 1. For each n<!,thesetC (λn) is cofinal in κn \ X. K X 2. If X contains all of its limit points of cofinality at most o (λn),thenC (λn) is bounded in κn \ X. X Proof of claim. For clause 1, suppose to the contrary that C (λn) is bounded in X \ κn. It follows by property 5 of the precovering set that there is η 2 X \ κn so that h\η is cofinal in X \ κn.LetA be the set of limit points of X \ h\η.Then 0 \ A is closed and unbounded in κn = sup(X κn), which has uncountable cofinality since X contains all of its limit points of cofinality !. Hence A \ Cn is closed and 0 th \ unbounded in κn; but this is impossible since the ! member τ of A Cn is singular in K,sinceh\η is cofinal in τ, contradicting the assumption that every member of Cn is inaccessible in K. K To prove clause 2, let τ = o (λn) and define a sequence of ordinals ηξ for ξ ≤ τ·!, as follows: 8 >0ifξ =0; <> supξ0<ξ ηξ0 if ξ is a limit ordinal; ηξ = X X >inf C (λ ,ι) n η − if ξ = τ · k + ι +1andC (λ ,ι) 6⊂ η ; :> k ξ 1 k ξ ηξ−1 otherwise: Since X contains all of its limit points of cofinality at most τ, each of the ordinals ηξ is in X for ξ ≤ τ · !. Furthermore, all of the ordinals ηξ are less than κn:The ordinals η0 and ηξ+1 are less than κn by definition, while if ξ is a limit ordinal then 0 either ηξ = ηξ0 =6 κn for some ξ <ξ,orelseηξ is singular while κn is regular. K Thus η = ητ·! is in C(λn,β)forsomeβ<o (λn). For each k<!it follows · C n 6 ? 2C that if ξk = τ k + β then (λn,β) ηξk = and hence ηξk <ηξk +1 (λn,β). License or copyright restrictions may apply to redistribution; see https://www.ams.org/journal-terms-of-use A MEASURABLE CARDINAL 4865 It follows that ητ·! is a limit point of C(λn,β), but this is impossible, as it would 0 0 follow by (3) that η 2C(λn,β )forsomeβ >β. We can now complete the proof of lemma 1.2 by observing that the assumption that ~κ is a Prikry sequence implies that λn = κ for all but finitely many n<!. K Thus o (λn)=o(κ)=δ, but this is impossible by claim 1.3 since the precovering set X was chosen to contain all of its limit points of cofinality at most δ. Hence oK (κ) ≥ κ. 1.1. A warm up. Before proving the other direction of theorem 1.1 we state the similar but simpler theorem 1.5. One direction of the proof is given by a second look at the proof of lemma 1.2, while other direction will be used to introduce some of the ideas of the proof of the main theorem in an easier context. Definition 1.4. We write E for the class of inaccessible cardinals of K,andD for the class of cardinals λ 2 E such that f α<λ: oK (α)=β g is stationary in λ for all β<λ. Gitik [2, theorem 1.1] proves that κ 2 D is equiconsistent with the existence of a closed, unbounded set C ⊂ E \ κ,whereκ is inaccessible. The following theorem shows that this construction cannot be directly iterated to obtain infinitely many such cardinals κ: Theorem 1.5. The following are equiconsistent: 1. There is an infinite increasing sequence ~κ =(κn : n<!) of inaccessible car- dinals such that for each n<!there is a closed unbounded set Cn ⊂ κn \ E. 2. There is an infinite increasing sequence ~λ of cardinals λn 2 D with κ = K sup~λ = limn<! o (λn). K Furthermore, the model in clause (1) can be constructed so that o (κn)=0for all n 2 !. Proof of (1)=)(2). Assume that ~κ is a sequence satisfying condition (1) and, as in the proof of lemma 1.2, pick a precovering set X and use it to define the sequence K ~λ. We will show that δ = limn o (λn) ≥ κ. Suppose to the contrary that δ<κ, and pick a second precovering set X0 ⊃ X such that X0 contains all of its limit points of cofinality at most δ. We now need to apply one further consequence of 0 0 the covering lemma, which states that if the ordinals λn are defined from X in the 0 same way as the ordinals λn were defined from X,thenλn = λn for all but finitely many n<!.
Recommended publications
  • Set-Theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms
    Set-theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms Justin William Henry Cavitt (860) 949-5686 [email protected] Advisor: W. Hugh Woodin Harvard University March 20, 2017 Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts in Mathematics and Philosophy Contents 1 Introduction 2 1.1 Author’s Note . .4 1.2 Acknowledgements . .4 2 The Independence Problem 5 2.1 Gödelian Independence and Consistency Strength . .5 2.2 Forcing and Natural Independence . .7 2.2.1 Basics of Forcing . .8 2.2.2 Forcing Facts . 11 2.2.3 The Space of All Forcing Extensions: The Generic Multiverse 15 2.3 Recap . 16 3 Approaches to New Axioms 17 3.1 Large Cardinals . 17 3.2 Inner Model Theory . 25 3.2.1 Basic Facts . 26 3.2.2 The Constructible Universe . 30 3.2.3 Other Inner Models . 35 3.2.4 Relative Constructibility . 38 3.3 Recap . 39 4 Ultimate L 40 4.1 The Axiom V = Ultimate L ..................... 41 4.2 Central Features of Ultimate L .................... 42 4.3 Further Philosophical Considerations . 47 4.4 Recap . 51 1 5 Set-theoretic Geology 52 5.1 Preliminaries . 52 5.2 The Downward Directed Grounds Hypothesis . 54 5.2.1 Bukovský’s Theorem . 54 5.2.2 The Main Argument . 61 5.3 Main Results . 65 5.4 Recap . 74 6 Conclusion 74 7 Appendix 75 7.1 Notation . 75 7.2 The ZFC Axioms . 76 7.3 The Ordinals . 77 7.4 The Universe of Sets . 77 7.5 Transitive Models and Absoluteness .
    [Show full text]
  • O&ONSTRUCTIBLE UNIVERSE and MEASURABLE CARDINALS 0
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 30 (1986) 293-320 293 North-Holland o&ONSTRUCTIBLE UNIVERSE AND MEASURABLE CARDINALS Claude SURESON Dkpartement de Mathkmatiques, Universitk de Caen, 1403.2 Caen, France Communicated by A. Nerode Received 23 September 1984 In analogy with K. Godel’s model L, C. Chang [l] formulated the wr- constructible universe C”‘, using the infinitary language L,,,, instead of the language of Set Theory L,,. The cumulative hierarchy of sets obtained in this way has many similarities with the hierarchy of the constructible universe (except for a major point: the axiom of choice [l], [9]). C”’ can also be characterized as the least inner model closed under arbitrary countable sequences. This paper is inspired by results of R. Jensen and J. Silver concerning the existence of O# and the covering property for L. We consider here a stronger notion of indiscernibles for the model C”’ and we say that C”’ satisfies the ‘covering property’ if any set of ordinals X in the universe can be covered by a set in C”’ of cardinality ]X]‘O. The existence of ‘indiscernibles’ for C”’ is also linked to large cardinal assumptions, and our main result (in ZFC) can be summarized as shown in Diagram 1: Diagram 1. The first part is devoted to the study of indiscernibles for PI. We prove the implications (1) and (2). In the second section, we deal with the covering property and show (3).
    [Show full text]
  • Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive?
    Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive? Neil Barton∗ 24 June 2020y Abstract The independence phenomenon in set theory, while perva- sive, can be partially addressed through the use of large cardinal axioms. A commonly assumed idea is that large cardinal axioms are species of maximality principles. In this paper, I argue that whether or not large cardinal axioms count as maximality prin- ciples depends on prior commitments concerning the richness of the subset forming operation. In particular I argue that there is a conception of maximality through absoluteness, on which large cardinal axioms are restrictive. I argue, however, that large cardi- nals are still important axioms of set theory and can play many of their usual foundational roles. Introduction Large cardinal axioms are widely viewed as some of the best candi- dates for new axioms of set theory. They are (apparently) linearly ordered by consistency strength, have substantial mathematical con- sequences for questions independent from ZFC (such as consistency statements and Projective Determinacy1), and appear natural to the ∗Fachbereich Philosophie, University of Konstanz. E-mail: neil.barton@uni- konstanz.de. yI would like to thank David Aspero,´ David Fernandez-Bret´ on,´ Monroe Eskew, Sy-David Friedman, Victoria Gitman, Luca Incurvati, Michael Potter, Chris Scam- bler, Giorgio Venturi, Matteo Viale, Kameryn Williams and audiences in Cambridge, New York, Konstanz, and Sao˜ Paulo for helpful discussion. Two anonymous ref- erees also provided helpful comments, and I am grateful for their input. I am also very grateful for the generous support of the FWF (Austrian Science Fund) through Project P 28420 (The Hyperuniverse Programme) and the VolkswagenStiftung through the project Forcing: Conceptual Change in the Foundations of Mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Determinacy and Large Cardinals
    Determinacy and Large Cardinals Itay Neeman∗ Abstract. The principle of determinacy has been crucial to the study of definable sets of real numbers. This paper surveys some of the uses of determinacy, concentrating specifically on the connection between determinacy and large cardinals, and takes this connection further, to the level of games of length ω1. Mathematics Subject Classification (2000). 03E55; 03E60; 03E45; 03E15. Keywords. Determinacy, iteration trees, large cardinals, long games, Woodin cardinals. 1. Determinacy Let ωω denote the set of infinite sequences of natural numbers. For A ⊂ ωω let Gω(A) denote the length ω game with payoff A. The format of Gω(A) is displayed in Diagram 1. Two players, denoted I and II, alternate playing natural numbers forming together a sequence x = hx(n) | n < ωi in ωω called a run of the game. The run is won by player I if x ∈ A, and otherwise the run is won by player II. I x(0) x(2) ...... II x(1) x(3) ...... Diagram 1. The game Gω(A). A game is determined if one of the players has a winning strategy. The set A is ω determined if Gω(A) is determined. For Γ ⊂ P(ω ), det(Γ) denotes the statement that all sets in Γ are determined. Using the axiom of choice, or more specifically using a wellordering of the reals, it is easy to construct a non-determined set A. det(P(ωω)) is therefore false. On the other hand it has become clear through research over the years that det(Γ) is true if all the sets in Γ are definable by some concrete means.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ultrafilter Characterization of Huge Cardinals 587
    proceedings of the american mathematical society Volume 90, Number 4, April 1984 THE ULTRAFILTERCHARACTERIZATION OF HUGE CARDINALS ROBERT J. MIGNONE1 Abstract. A huge cardinal can be characterized using ultrafilters. After an argu- ment is made for a particular ultrafilter characterization, it is used to prove the existence of a measurable cardinal above the huge cardinal, and an ultrafilter over the set of all subsets of this measurable cardinal of size smaller than the huge cardinal. Finally, this last ultrafilter is disassembled intact by a process which often produces a different ultrafilter from the one started out with. An important point of this paper is given the existence of the particular ultrafilter characterization of a huge cardinal mentioned above these results are proved in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice. Introduction. The notion of a huge cardinal was first introduced by Kunen. Its primary definition is given in terms of elementary embeddings. And just as measura- ble and supercompact cardinals have ultrafilter characterizations in ZFC, a huge cardinal can also be characterized by ultrafilters. In §1, after the elementary embedding definition for a huge cardinal and two equivalent ultrafilter characterizations are given, an argument is made for one characterization above the other in instances where the axiom of choice is not available. Once an ultrafilter characterization for k being huge is settled upon—which defines k as huge if for some X > k there exists a K-complete, normal ultrafilter over {x C X: x = k}—two theorems are proved in §2 which state that providing such an ultrafilter exists over {x czX: x = k}, then X is measurable and k is A-supercompact.
    [Show full text]
  • Set-Theoretical Background 1.1 Ordinals and Cardinals
    Set-Theoretical Background 11 February 2019 Our set-theoretical framework will be the Zermelo{Fraenkel axioms with the axiom of choice (ZFC): • Axiom of Extensionality. If X and Y have the same elements, then X = Y . • Axiom of Pairing. For all a and b there exists a set fa; bg that contains exactly a and b. • Axiom Schema of Separation. If P is a property (with a parameter p), then for all X and p there exists a set Y = fx 2 X : P (x; p)g that contains all those x 2 X that have the property P . • Axiom of Union. For any X there exists a set Y = S X, the union of all elements of X. • Axiom of Power Set. For any X there exists a set Y = P (X), the set of all subsets of X. • Axiom of Infinity. There exists an infinite set. • Axiom Schema of Replacement. If a class F is a function, then for any X there exists a set Y = F (X) = fF (x): x 2 Xg. • Axiom of Regularity. Every nonempty set has a minimal element for the membership relation. • Axiom of Choice. Every family of nonempty sets has a choice function. 1.1 Ordinals and cardinals A set X is well ordered if it is equipped with a total order relation such that every nonempty subset S ⊆ X has a smallest element. The statement that every set admits a well ordering is equivalent to the axiom of choice. A set X is transitive if every element of an element of X is an element of X.
    [Show full text]
  • Florida State University Libraries
    )ORULGD6WDWH8QLYHUVLW\/LEUDULHV 2020 Justifying Alternative Foundations for Mathematics Jared M. Ifland Follow this and additional works at DigiNole: FSU's Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected] THE FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF ARTS & SCIENCES JUSTIFYING ALTERNATIVE FOUNDATIONS FOR MATHEMATICS By JARED M. IFLAND A Thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation with Honors in the Major Degree Awarded: Spring, 2020 The members of the Defense Committee approve the thesis of Jared M. Ifland defended on July 17, 2020. ______________________________ Dr. James Justus Thesis Director ______________________________ Dr. Ettore Aldrovandi Outside Committee Member ______________________________ Dr. J. Piers Rawling Committee Member Abstract: It is inarguable that mathematics serves a quintessential role in the natural sciences and that ZFC — extended by large cardinal axioms — provides a foundation for vast swaths of contemporary mathematics. As such, it is understandable that the naturalistic philosopher may inquire into the ontological status of mathematical entities and sets. Many have argued that the indispensability of mathematics from scientific enterprise warrants belief in mathematical platonism, but it is unclear how knowledge of entities that exist independently of the natural world is possible. Furthermore, indispensability arguments are notoriously antithetical to mathematical practice: mathematicians typically do not refer to scientific
    [Show full text]
  • Paul B. Larson a BRIEF HISTORY of DETERMINACY §1. Introduction
    Paul B. Larson A BRIEF HISTORY OF DETERMINACY x1. Introduction. Determinacy axioms are statements to the effect that certain games are determined, in that each player in the game has an optimal strategy. The commonly accepted axioms for mathematics, the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms with the Axiom of Choice (ZFC; see [??, ??]), im- ply the determinacy of many games that people actually play. This applies in particular to many games of perfect information, games in which the players alternate moves which are known to both players, and the out- come of the game depends only on this list of moves, and not on chance or other external factors. Games of perfect information which must end in finitely many moves are determined. This follows from the work of Ernst Zermelo [??], D´enesK}onig[??] and L´aszl´oK´almar[??], and also from the independent work of John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern (in their 1944 book, reprinted as [??]). As pointed out by Stanis law Ulam [??], determinacy for games of perfect information of a fixed finite length is essentially a theorem of logic. If we let x1,y1,x2,y2,::: ,xn,yn be variables standing for the moves made by players player I (who plays x1,::: ,xn) and player II (who plays y1,::: ,yn), and A (consisting of sequences of length 2n) is the set of runs of the game for which player I wins, the statement (1) 9x18y1 ::: 9xn8ynhx1; y1; : : : ; xn; yni 2 A essentially asserts that the first player has a winning strategy in the game, and its negation, (2) 8x19y1 ::: 8xn9ynhx1; y1; : : : ; xn; yni 62 A essentially asserts that the second player has a winning strategy.1 We let ! denote the set of natural numbers 0; 1; 2;::: ; for brevity we will often refer to the members of this set as \integers".
    [Show full text]
  • SET THEORY for CATEGORY THEORY 3 the Category Is Well-Powered, Meaning That Each Object Has Only a Set of Iso- Morphism Classes of Subobjects
    SET THEORY FOR CATEGORY THEORY MICHAEL A. SHULMAN Abstract. Questions of set-theoretic size play an essential role in category theory, especially the distinction between sets and proper classes (or small sets and large sets). There are many different ways to formalize this, and which choice is made can have noticeable effects on what categorical constructions are permissible. In this expository paper we summarize and compare a num- ber of such “set-theoretic foundations for category theory,” and describe their implications for the everyday use of category theory. We assume the reader has some basic knowledge of category theory, but little or no prior experience with formal logic or set theory. 1. Introduction Since its earliest days, category theory has had to deal with set-theoretic ques- tions. This is because unlike in most fields of mathematics outside of set theory, questions of size play an essential role in category theory. A good example is Freyd’s Special Adjoint Functor Theorem: a functor from a complete, locally small, and well-powered category with a cogenerating set to a locally small category has a left adjoint if and only if it preserves small limits. This is always one of the first results I quote when people ask me “are there any real theorems in category theory?” So it is all the more striking that it involves in an essential way notions like ‘locally small’, ‘small limits’, and ‘cogenerating set’ which refer explicitly to the difference between sets and proper classes (or between small sets and large sets). Despite this, in my experience there is a certain amount of confusion among users and students of category theory about its foundations, and in particular about what constructions on large categories are or are not possible.
    [Show full text]
  • How Set Theory Impinges on Logic
    1 Jesús Mosterín HOW SET THEORY IMPINGES ON LOGIC The set-theoretical universe Reality often cannot be grasped and understood in its unfathomable richness and mind-blowing complexity. Think only of the trivial case of the shape of the Earth. Every time the wind blows, a bird flies, a tree drops a leave, every time it rains, a car moves or we get a haircut, the form of the Earth changes. No available or conceivable geometry can describe the ever changing form of the surface of our planet. Sometimes the best we can do is to apply the method of theoretical science: to pick up a mathematical structure from the set-theoretical universe, a structure that has some formal similarities with some features of the real world situation we are interested in, and to use that structure as a model of that parcel of the world. In the case of the Earth, the structure can be an Euclidean sphere, or a sphere flattened at the poles, or an ellipsoid, but of course these structures do not represent the car and the hair, and so are realistic only up to a point. The largest part of scientific activity results in data, in contributions to history (in a broad sense). Only exceptionally does scientific activity result in abstract schemata, in formulas, in theories. In history there is truth and falsity, but we are not sure whether it makes sense to apply these same categories to an abstract theory. We pick up a mathematical structure and construct a theory. We still have to determine its scope of application or validity, the range of its realizations.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2009.07164V1 [Math.LO] 15 Sep 2020 Ai—U Nta Eeyb Etoigfaue Htuiul Char Uniquely That Isomorphism
    CATEGORICAL LARGE CARDINALS AND THE TENSION BETWEEN CATEGORICITY AND SET-THEORETIC REFLECTION JOEL DAVID HAMKINS AND HANS ROBIN SOLBERG Abstract. Inspired by Zermelo’s quasi-categoricity result characterizing the models of second-order Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory ZFC2, we investigate when those models are fully categorical, characterized by the addition to ZFC2 ei- ther of a first-order sentence, a first-order theory, a second-order sentence or a second-order theory. The heights of these models, we define, are the categor- ical large cardinals. We subsequently consider various philosophical aspects of categoricity for structuralism and realism, including the tension between categoricity and set-theoretic reflection, and we present (and criticize) a cat- egorical characterization of the set-theoretic universe hV, ∈i in second-order logic. Categorical accounts of various mathematical structures lie at the very core of structuralist mathematical practice, enabling mathematicians to refer to specific mathematical structures, not by having carefully to prepare and point at specially constructed instances—preserved like the one-meter iron bar locked in a case in Paris—but instead merely by mentioning features that uniquely characterize the structure up to isomorphism. The natural numbers hN, 0,Si, for example, are uniquely characterized by the Dedekind axioms, which assert that 0 is not a successor, that the successor func- tion S is one-to-one, and that every set containing 0 and closed under successor contains every number [Ded88, Ded01]. We know what we mean by the natural numbers—they have a definiteness—because we can describe features that com- pletely determine the natural number structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:Math/0009240V1
    A simple maximality principle Joel David Hamkins∗ The City University of New York† Carnegie Mellon University‡ http://math.gc.cuny.edu/faculty/hamkins October 24, 2018 Abstract. In this paper, following an idea of Christophe Chalons, I propose a new kind of forcing axiom, the Maximality Principle, which asserts that any sentence ϕ holding in some ˙ forcing extension V P and all subsequent extensions V P∗Q holds already in V . It follows, in fact, that such sentences must also hold in all forcing extensions of V . In modal terms, therefore, the Maximality Principle is expressed by the scheme (✸ ϕ) =⇒ ϕ, and is equivalent to the modal theory S5. In this article, I prove that the Maximality Principle is relatively consistent with zfc. A boldface version of the Maximality Principle, obtained by allowing real parameters to appear in ϕ, is equiconsistent with the scheme asserting that Vδ ≺ V for an inaccessible cardinal δ, which in turn is equiconsistent with the scheme asserting that ord is mp mp V Mahlo. The strongest principle along these lines is ∼ , which asserts that ∼ holds in and all forcing extensions. From this, it follows that 0# exists, that x# exists for every set x, that projective truth is invariant by forcing, that Woodin cardinals are consistent and much more. Many open questions remain. 1 The Maximality Principle arXiv:math/0009240v1 [math.LO] 28 Sep 2000 Christophe Chalons has introduced a delightful new axiom, asserting in plain language that anything that is forceable and not subsequently unforceable is true. Specifically, in [2] he proposes the following principle: ∗My research has been supported by grants from the PSC-CUNY Research Foundation and the NSF.
    [Show full text]