Theory and Application of Roscoe Pound's Sociological Jurisprudence: Crime Prevention Or Control?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Theory and Application of Roscoe Pound's Sociological Jurisprudence: Crime Prevention Or Control? University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform Volume 2 1969 Theory and Application of Roscoe Pound's Sociological Jurisprudence: Crime Prevention or Control? Louis H. Masotti Case Western Reserve University Michael A. Weinstein Purdue University Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mjlr Part of the Criminal Law Commons, Law and Philosophy Commons, Law and Society Commons, and the Law Enforcement and Corrections Commons Recommended Citation Louis H. Masotti & Michael A. Weinstein, Theory and Application of Roscoe Pound's Sociological Jurisprudence: Crime Prevention or Control?, 2 U. MICH. J. L. REFORM 431 (1969). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mjlr/vol2/iss2/11 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THEORY AND APPLICATION OF ROSCOE POUND'S SOCIOLOGICAL JURISPRUDENCE: CRIME PREVENTION OR CONTROL? Louis H. Masotti* and Michael A. Weinstein** I. Introduction The current interest in reforming the administration of justice has been triggered by a number of factors including the 1967 report of the President's Commission on Law Enforcement and the Administration of Justice1 and the treatment afforded arrestees during the civil disorders of the past few years 2. The nation is alarmed at the reported annual in- creases in crime, and this alarm was manifested in the 1968 presidential election when "law and order" became a major issue. Superficially the answer may seem clear: more effective enforcement of the law and, when necessary, more stringent laws. The critical issue, however, is a jurisprudential-philosophical one: ought the "proper" approach to crime essentially be its prevention through methods such as the rehabilitation of criminal offenders, or its control through efficient administrative procedures? This is not a new question in jurisprudence, but it remains an important and unresolved one. This article will examine an analytical approach to this problem which was developed and applied by Roscoe Pound, one of America's most eminent jurists. After describing and interpreting Pound's concept of sociological jurisprudence, we will relate it generally to the reform of criminal justice administration and analyze Pound's attempt to apply his theory as -Director of the Cleveland Crime Survey of 1921. Finally, we *Associate Professor of Political Science, Case Western Reserve University. A.B. 1956, Princeton University; Ph.D. 1964, Northwestern University. **Assistant Professor of Political Science, Purdue University. A.B. 1964, New York University; Ph.D. 1967. Case Western Reserve University. This-article is drawn from a larger study of the Cleveland Crime Survey, CRIME, POLITICS & REFORM, to be published in the near future. The authors are indebted to the Institute of Law and Criminal Procedure, Georgetown University, for financial support of the project. 'NATIONAL COMMISSION ON LAW ENFORCEMENT & THE ADMINISTRATION OF JUSTICE, THE CHALLENGE OF CRIME IN A FREE SOCIETY (1967). See Comment, The Administration of Justice in the Wake of the Detroit Civil Disorder of July 1967, 66 MICH. L. REV. 1542 (1968). Prospectus [Vol. 2:2 will compare the recommendations of that Cleveland study and the recent report of the President's Commission in a modest effort to assess their impact on the administration of criminal justice and to draw some lessons for future reform endeavors. II. Pound's Sociological Jurisprudence: The General Theory Roscoe Pound defined the goals of sociological jurisprudence in an essay on the philosophy of law: What we-are seeking to do and must do in a civilized society is to adjust relations and or- der conduct in a world in which the goods of existence, the scope for free activity, and the objects on which to exert free activity are limited, and the demands upon those goods and those objects are infinite. To order the activities of men in their endeavor to satisfy their demands so as to enable satisfaction of as much of the whole scheme of demands with the least friction and waste has not merely been what lawmakers and tribunals and jurists have been striving for, it has also been put in one way or another by philoso- phers as what we ought to be doing. 3 This statement contains a summary of Pound's program. In the per- fect society all claims put forward by individuals would be immediately satisfied. However, such a utopia does not exist in the world and people cannot satisfy each of their demands. Further, men come into conflict when they desire the same scarce goods. The basic tenets of sociological jurisprudence place Pound in the tradition of Hobbes: And therefore if any two men desire the same thing, which nevertheless they cannot both enjoy, they become enemies: and in the way to their end, which is principally their own conservation, and sometimes their delectation only, 4endeavor to destroy or subdue one an- other. 3 TWENTIETH CENTURY PHILOSOPHY: LIVING SCHOOLS OF THOUGHT 69 (D. Runes ed. 1958) [hereinafter cited as Runes]. 4 T. HOBBES, LEVIATHAN -105 (1951 Bobbs-Merrill edition). April 1969] Sociological Jurisprudence Pound articulated a conflict theory founded on individual interest. To escape from a state of nature men devise systems of law which enable them to fulfill "as much of the whole scheme of demands with the least friction and waste." The legal system is made effective through a mo- nopoly of coercive power: I think of law as in one sense a highly special- ized form of social control in a developed politically organized society -a social control through the systematic and orderly appli- cation of the force of such a society.5 Thus, sociological jurisprudence introduces two components into its definition of law. On the one hand, law is a means of alleviating conflict through the imposition of organized force. On the other, law functions to secure the realization of as many individual interests as possible. An appropriate question arises here whether the second assertion is meant to state a fact or prescribe an ideal. We will examine this question, but for now we may accept these components as the starting point for Pound. Although the theory of interests was prefigured in nineteenth century jurisprudence, Pound brought the approach to maturity.6 He devised categories under which to subsume the demands enunciated in social systems: If we take, as it were, an inventory of the concrete claims which press upon the law for satisfaction and seek to classify those which the law recognizes and endeavors to secure, they fall conveniently into three groups: indi- vidual interests, public interests, and social interests. 7 Individual interest are demands which particular people consciously and immediately recognize as their own, such as a demand for non-discriminatory treatment in hiring. Public interests are the claims pressed on behalf of a politically organized society, such as the desire for a new courthouse. 8 Demands of the social group are social interests. These include the security of social institutions defined as the protection 5 Runes 67. 6 For the historical background of Pound's interest theory see H. REUSCHLEIN, JURISPRU- DENCE: ITS AMERICAN PROPHETS (1951). 7 R. POUND, CRIMINAL JUSTICE IN AMERICA 5 (1930). 8 Id. Prospectus ,Voi. 2:: of economic, social and religious organizations; the general morals defi- ned as the enforcement of social standards; the general progress defined as the increase of man's control over nature; the conservation of social resources defined as efficient use of the goods of existence; the general security defined as the defense of order; and the individual life.9 The social interest in the individual life consists of three demands: the desire for self-assertion, the demand for fair opportunity and the interest in a 0 minimum standard of life.' Since the law operates through general rules, specific "individual interests" or demands must be generalized before they are recognized as legal rights." When generalized they become the social interest in the individual life noted above. Thus, our example of non-discriminatory treatment in hiring becomes a recognized legal right subsumed under the social interest in an individual's "demand for fair opportunity". For purposes of comparing and weighing interests, then, Pound considers all interests on the social level. When we come to discuss the application of the general theory of sociological jurisprudence to the administration of criminal justice, we will see that the jurist is primarily concerned with balancing the social interests in the general security and in the individual life. Sociological jurisprudence is not a simple philosophy and there are many ambiguities in the argument as we have reproduced it in this simple form. In order to understand better what is meant by an "inter- est", it is worth noting how Pound's concept of "interest" has evolved. Contributions are drawn from several sources. Samuel Krislov points out that all interests must be traced to individual activity;' 2 he empha- sizes the danger that the term social interest might prompt us to believe that society has desires.' 3 Pierre Lepaulle adds to the concept by show- ing that if interests are to be balanced they must be consciously ex- pressed.' 4 Finally, Lester B. Snyder argues that Pound used an empiri- cal method to determine his matrix of interests: Pound did not ascertain these interests by use of logical presuppositions about the ideals of existence in society. Nor did he ascertain these interests through a study of the funda- mental behavioral tendencies of men. In a 9 Id. 'ld. at 9.
Recommended publications
  • Libertarianism, Culture, and Personal Predispositions
    Undergraduate Journal of Psychology 22 Libertarianism, Culture, and Personal Predispositions Ida Hepsø, Scarlet Hernandez, Shir Offsey, & Katherine White ​ Kennesaw​ State University Abstract The United States has exhibited two potentially connected trends – increasing individualism and increasing interest in libertarian ideology. Previous research on libertarian ideology found higher levels of individualism among libertarians, and cross-cultural research has tied greater individualism to making dispositional attributions and lower altruistic tendencies. Given this, we expected to observe positive correlations between the following variables in the present research: individualism and endorsement of libertarianism, individualism and dispositional attributions, and endorsement of libertarianism and dispositional attributions. We also expected to observe negative correlations between libertarianism and altruism, dispositional attributions and altruism, and individualism and altruism. Survey results from 252 participants confirmed a positive correlation between individualism and libertarianism, a marginally significant positive correlation between libertarianism and dispositional attributions, and a negative correlation between individualism and altruism. These results confirm the connection between libertarianism and individualism observed in previous research and present several intriguing questions for future research on libertarian ideology. Key Words: Libertarianism, individualism, altruism, attributions individualistic, made apparent
    [Show full text]
  • Roscoe Pound-The Judge
    January, x942 ROSCOE POUND-THE JUDGE HAROLD GILL REUSCHLEIN t "Experience made him sage" -John Gay' To Roscoe Pound was given an invaluable experience rarely granted to a legal philosopher and teacher, 2 the experience afforded by a position upon a judicial tribunal of high rank. In April i9oi the Supreme Court of the State of Nebraska, then consisting of a chief jus- tice and two judges,3 found itself confronted with a docket hopelessly in arrears. The legislature, coming to the aid of the court, created the Nebraska Supreme Court Commission.4 Nine commissioners were appointed by unanimous vote of the supreme court to prepare and submit opinions in over fifteen hundred cases which had accumulated in the court. The commissioners were organized into three "depart- ments" each consisting of three members, one of whom served as chairman of his department. Appointed as one of the original commissioners, Roscoe Pound, was assigned to the "Second Department".5 During Pound's tenure as a commissioner, the members of the supreme court itself wrote almost no opinions. As the (locket was called, the cases were assigned equally to the departments and the chairman of each department re- assigned these cases to its members. There followed the usual hearing, t A. B., 1927, University of Iowa; LL. B., 1933, Yale University; J. S. D., 1934, Cornell University; Professor of Law, Georgetown University; author of Aludminum and Monopoly: A Phase of an Uisolved Problem (1939) 87 U. OF PA. L. REV. 509; Municipal Debt Readjustment: Present Relief and Future Policy (1938) 23 CORN.
    [Show full text]
  • EMMA GOLDMAN, ANARCHISM, and the “AMERICAN DREAM” by Christina Samons
    AN AMERICA THAT COULD BE: EMMA GOLDMAN, ANARCHISM, AND THE “AMERICAN DREAM” By Christina Samons The so-called “Gilded Age,” 1865-1901, was a period in American his­ tory characterized by great progress, but also of great turmoil. The evolving social, political, and economic climate challenged the way of life that had existed in pre-Civil War America as European immigration rose alongside the appearance of the United States’ first big businesses and factories.1 One figure emerges from this era in American history as a forerunner of progressive thought: Emma Goldman. Responding, in part, to the transformations that occurred during the Gilded Age, Goldman gained notoriety as an outspoken advocate of anarchism in speeches throughout the United States and through published essays and pamphlets in anarchist newspapers. Years later, she would synthe­ size her ideas in collections of essays such as Anarchism and Other Essays, first published in 1917. The purpose of this paper is to contextualize Emma Goldman’s anarchist theory by placing it firmly within the economic, social, and 1 Alan M. Kraut, The Huddled Masses: The Immigrant in American Society, 1880­ 1921 (Wheeling, IL: Harlan Davidson, 2001), 14. 82 Christina Samons political reality of turn-of-the-twentieth-century America while dem­ onstrating that her theory is based in a critique of the concept of the “American Dream.” To Goldman, American society had drifted away from the ideal of the “American Dream” due to the institutionalization of exploitation within all aspects of social and political life—namely, economics, religion, and law. The first section of this paper will give a brief account of Emma Goldman’s position within American history at the turn of the twentieth century.
    [Show full text]
  • State Courts and Federalism in the 1980'S: Comment
    William & Mary Law Review Volume 22 (1980-1981) Issue 4 National Center for State Courts Marshall-Wythe School of Law Symposium on Article 9 "State Courts and Federalism in the 1980's" May 1981 State Courts and Federalism in the 1980's: Comment Ruggero J. Aldisert Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmlr Part of the Jurisdiction Commons Repository Citation Ruggero J. Aldisert, State Courts and Federalism in the 1980's: Comment, 22 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 821 (1981), https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmlr/vol22/iss4/9 Copyright c 1981 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmlr STATE COURTS AND FEDERALISM IN THE 1980's: COMMENT RUGGERO J. ALDISERT* Each of the four highly analytical, uniformly thoughtful and stimulating papers that are the subject of these comments deserves an exhaustive commentary. My role is not to respond in kind by setting forth an essay of my own, but to react informally to the intellectual feast so temptingly displayed in the preceding pages. My reaction is, of necessity, personal and unabashedly influenced by my experience, and, therefore, these contentions are intuitive rather than conclusive. Moreover, my reaction is probably atypical because it is colored (or shall I say jaundiced?) by twenty years in the state and federal judiciary and about a dozen years of intimate involvement in continuing education programs for state and fed- eral appellate judges. My experience prevents me from looking upon state and federal courts as inanimate institutions, or state and federal judges as faceless dancers in a bloodless ballet.
    [Show full text]
  • Holmes, Cardozo, and the Legal Realists: Early Incarnations of Legal Pragmatism and Enterprise Liability
    Holmes, Cardozo, and the Legal Realists: Early Incarnations of Legal Pragmatism and Enterprise Liability EDMUND URSIN* TABLE OF CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................. 538 II. SETTING THE STAGE: TORT AND CONSTITUTIONAL LAW AT THE TURN OF THE TWENTIETH CENTURY ............................................................................ 545 III. HOLMES AND THE PATH OF THE LAW ................................................................. 550 A. Holmes and the Need for Judicial Creativity in Common Law Subjects ............................................................................................ 550 B. The Path Not Followed ............................................................................ 554 IV. THE INDUSTRIAL ACCIDENT CRISIS, THE WORKERS’ COMPENSATION SOLUTION, AND A CONSTITUTIONAL CONFRONTATION ....................................... 558 A. The Industrial Accident Crisis and the Workers’ Compensation Solution ............................................................................ 558 * © 2013 Edmund Ursin. Professor of Law, University of San Diego School of Law. Thanks to Richard Posner for valuable comments on an earlier draft of this Article and to Roy Brooks and Kevin Cole for always helpful comments on previous articles upon which I expand in this Article. See Edmund Ursin, Clarifying the Normative Dimension of Legal Realism: The Example of Holmes’s The Path of the Law, 49 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 487 (2012) [hereinafter Ursin, Clarifying];
    [Show full text]
  • Ross and Olivecrona on Rights
    Scholarship Repository University of Minnesota Law School Articles Faculty Scholarship 2009 Ross and Olivecrona on Rights Brian H. Bix University of Minnesota Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/faculty_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Brian H. Bix, Ross and Olivecrona on Rights, 34 AUSTL. J. LEG. PHIL. 103 (2009), available at https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/faculty_articles/211. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in the Faculty Scholarship collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Ross and Olivecrona on Rights BRIAN H. BIX1 Introduction The Scandinavian legal realists, critically-inclined theorists from Denmark, Norway, and Sweden, who wrote in the early and middle decades of the 20t century,2 are not as widely read as they once were in Britain, and they seemed never to have received much attention in the United States. This is unfortunate, as the work of those theorists, at their best, is as sharp in its criticisms and as sophisticated philosophically as anything written by the better known (at least better known in Britain and the United States) American legal realists, who were writing at roughly the same time. The focus of the present article, Alf Ross and Karl Olivecrona, were arguably the most accessible of the Scandinavian legal realists, with their clear prose, straight- forward style of argumentation, and the availability of a number of works in English.
    [Show full text]
  • Rules of Law, Laws of Science
    Rules of Law, Laws of Science Wai Chee Dimock* My Essay is a response to legal realism,' to its well-known arguments against "rules of law." Legal realism, seeing itself as an empirical practice, was not convinced that there could be any set of rules, formalized on the grounds of logic, that would have a clear determinative power on the course of legal action or, more narrowly, on the outcome of litigated cases. The decisions made inside the courtroom-the mental processes of judges and juries-are supposedly guided by rules. Realists argued that they are actually guided by a combination of factors, some social and some idiosyncratic, harnessed to no set protocol. They are not subject to the generalizability and predictability that legal rules presuppose. That very presupposition, realists said, creates a gap, a vexing lack of correspondence, between the language of the law and the world it purports to describe. As a formal system, law operates as a propositional universe made up of highly technical terms--estoppel, surety, laches, due process, and others-accompanied by a set of rules governing their operation. Law is essentially definitional in this sense: It comes into being through the specialized meanings of words. The logical relations between these specialized meanings give it an internal order, a way to classify cases into actionable categories. These categories, because they are definitionally derived, are answerable only to their internal logic, not to the specific features of actual disputes. They capture those specific features only imperfectly, sometimes not at all. They are integral and unassailable, but hollowly so.
    [Show full text]
  • Judicial Process As an Empirical Study: a Comment on Justice Brennan’S Essay
    Yeshiva University, Cardozo School of Law LARC @ Cardozo Law Articles Faculty 1988 Judicial Process as an Empirical Study: A Comment on Justice Brennan’s Essay Charles M. Yablon Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://larc.cardozo.yu.edu/faculty-articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Charles M. Yablon, Judicial Process as an Empirical Study: A Comment on Justice Brennan’s Essay, 10 Cardozo Law Review 149 (1988). Available at: https://larc.cardozo.yu.edu/faculty-articles/208 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty at LARC @ Cardozo Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by an authorized administrator of LARC @ Cardozo Law. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. JUDICIAL PROCESS AS AN EMPIRICAL STUDY: A COMMENT ON JUSTICE BRENNAN'S ESSAY Charles M. Yablon* I. LOOKING AT WHAT JUDGES ACTUALLY DO One of the enduring accomplishments of the Legal Realist move­ ment was to shift at least some of the attention of academic lawyers away from their favorite occupation—telling judges what to do—and to get them to consider what it is that judges actually do. The genera­ tion of legal scholars who immediately preceded the Realists had at­ tacked the formalism of judicial decisionmaking, criticizing judges for mechanically applying formal rules without considering social needs or public policy.' The Realists, while sympathetic to this prescriptive claim about the proper role of judges, added to it a descriptive claim, that judges did not in fact decide cases through mechanical applica­ tion of general rules, that such formal rules were indeterminate at the level of practice, and did not yield certainty or predictable results.^ Certainty and predictability, to the extent they existed in the legal system, were the product of the "personality of the judge," not the • Professor of Law, Benjamin N.
    [Show full text]
  • Jurisprudence and Ethics Roscoe Pound
    NORTH CAROLINA LAW REVIEW Volume 23 | Number 3 Article 1 4-1-1945 Law and Morals -- Jurisprudence and Ethics Roscoe Pound Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.unc.edu/nclr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Roscoe Pound, Law and Morals -- Jurisprudence and Ethics, 23 N.C. L. Rev. 185 (1945). Available at: http://scholarship.law.unc.edu/nclr/vol23/iss3/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Carolina Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in North Carolina Law Review by an authorized editor of Carolina Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1945] LAW AND MORALS-JURISPRUDENCE AND ETHICS RoscoE POUND* I PRELIMINA Y :1 MORALS AND MORALITY The relation of law to morals was one of the three subjects chiefly debated by nineteenth-century jurists, the other two being the nature of law and the interpretation of legal history. Jhering said that it was the Cape Horn of jurisprudence. The juristic navigator who would over- come its perils ran no little risk of fatal shipwreck.2 Commenting on this, Ahrens said that the question called for a good philosophical com- pass and strict logical method.3 But Jhering showed later that the root of the difficulty lay in juristic and ethical vocabulary. On the one side, there was a poverty of terms which required the one word which we translate as "law" to carry many meanings. On the other side, there was in German an abundance of words of different degrees of ethical connotation with meanings not always clearly differentiated.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to the Philosophy of Law / by Roscoe Pound
    the pResence of this Book thej.m.kelly LIBRARY has Been made possiBle th Rough the qeneRosity Stephen B. Roman From the Library of Daniel Binchy AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW THE ADDRESSES CONTAINED IN THIS BOOK WERE DELIVERED IN THE WILLIAM L. STORRS LECTURE SERIES, IQ2I, BEFORE THE LAW SCHOOL OF YALE UNIVER SITY, NEW HAVEN, CONNECTICUT STORKS LECTURES PUBLISHED BY YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS THE REFORM OF LEGAL PROCEDURE. By Moorfield Storey. THE JUDICIARY AND THE PEOPLE. By Frederick N. Judson. CONCERNING JUSTICE. By Lucilius A. Emery. WOMAN'S SUFFRAGE BY CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT. By Henry St. George Tucker. THE NATURE OF THE JUDICIAL PROCESS. By Benjamin N. Cardozo. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Law BY ROSCOE POUND NEW HAVEN: YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS LONDON: HUMPHREY MILFORD OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS COPYRIGHT, 1922, BY YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA First Published, May, 1922. Second Printing, December, 1924. Third Printing, May, 1925. Fourth Printing, April, 1930. TO JOSEPH HENRY BEALE IN GRATEFUL ACKNOWLEDGMENT OF MANY OBLIGATIONS THE present volume is the second work published under the imprint of the Yale University Press in memory of Arthur P. McKinstry, who died in New York City, July 21, 1921. Born in Winnebago City, Minnesota, on De cember 22, 1 88 1, he was graduated from Yale College in 1905, and in 1907 received the degree of LL.B. magna cum laude from the Yale Law School, graduating at the head of his class. Throughout his career at Yale he was noted both for his scholarship and for his active interest in debating, which won for him first the presidency of the Freshman Union and subsequently the presidency of the Yale Union.
    [Show full text]
  • Was the Inca Empire a Socialist State? A
    INCA EMPIRE 55 WAS THE INCA EMPIRE A SOCIALIST STATE? A HISTORICAL DISCUSSION meadow, and they tilled in common a portion of the agricultural land for the support of the chief, the cult 2 Kevin R. Harris and the aged. However, not all land was used for communal purposes all Before the Spanish conquest of the Americas in the fifteenth and the time. Sometimes individual members of the community used sixteenth centuries, the Inca Empire spread down much of the the land for a period of time for personal use. Llamas and modern South American coast in the Andes Mountains. The alpacas also grazed on the land. These large animals were used empire consisted of more than ten million inhabitants and had, for work and their wool was used to make clothing in the Inca 3 at the time, a very unique political and economic system. The State. When a common couple was married the community 4 government divided land and animals amongst members of the built them a modest house. It was a custom in Incan society for nation, not necessarily equally, and a system was in place to take people to help others in the community who were in need. care of the elderly and sick. Social scientists have been debating “People were expected to lend their labor to cultivate neighbors’ how to classify the Inca Empire for centuries. Arguments have land, and expected that neighbors would help them in due been made which classified the Inca Empire as a socialist state. course. All capable people were collaborated to support the Many elements of socialism existed in the Inca Empire, but can incapable—orphans, widows, the sick—with food and 5 the state really be classified as socialistic? housing.” Inca commoners expected this courtesy from their The Incas moved into the area which is now known as the neighbors.
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of Sociology on American Jurisprudence: from Oliver Wendell Holmes to Critical Legal Studies
    THE INFLUENCE OF SOCIOLOGY ON AMERICAN JURISPRUDENCE: FROM OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES TO CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES A. Javier Trevino Marquette University Mid-American Review ofSociology, 1994, Vol XVIII, No. I& 2: 23-46 This paper analyzes the distinctive influence that sociology has had on legal scholarship during the past century. II examines some of Ihe more significant contributions that sociology has made to four of the major jurisprudential "movements" of the twentieth-century: Holmesian legal science, soci%gical jurisprudence. legal Realism. and Critical Legal Studies. In essence, this paper shows how sociology has: (1) contributed to the language of the law some of its more important concepts, (2) given jurisprudence penetrating insight inlo the social dynamics ofthe law, (3) revealed the close relationship which exists between law andthe other social institutions, (4) provided jurisprudence with a positivistic. structural methodology by which to study the law. and (5) inspired a legal approach thaI is perspectival andhermeneutical in orientation. Introduction Several scholars (Geis 1964; Hunt ]978; Hall, Wiecek, and Finkelman 1991 :456457; Horwitz ]992; Vago 1994) have noted the tremendous impact that social science has made on American jurisprudence. My intention in this paper is to engage in a more detailed. extended, and updated analysis than that previously rendered by these scholars, of the distinctive influence that sociology has had on legal scholarship during the last one hundred years or so. The rationale fOf .undertakil)gsl~~h a~ analysis -is to clarify and accentuate the contours of the ongoing discourse between theoretical sociology and jurisprudential thought. In this paper I will examine some of the contributions that sociology has made to four inteJlectual legal traditions or "movements" of the twentieth century: (I) Holmesian legal science, (2) sociological jurisprudence, (3) legal Realism, and (4) Critical Legal Studies.2 Holmesian Legal Science It may well be that Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.
    [Show full text]