Proper Names

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Proper Names Proper Names Aaron Lambert A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy in conformity with the requtemeatr for the degree of Master of A~ts Queen's University Kingston, Ontario, Canada May, 1997 @ Aaron Lambert, 1997 National Library BiblioWque nationale 1+m ,ma& du Canada Acgusitions and Acquisitions et Bibl~ographiSe~~ces sewbibliogaphiques The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accord6 une licence non exclusive licence allowing the exclusive pennettant a la National biof Canada to BibIioth&quenationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distn'bate or sell reproduire, prh, distn'buerou copies of hismer thesis by any means vendre des copies de sa tWse de and in any form or fomat, making this thesis available to interested forme qut ce soit pour metbe des persons. exemplah.es de cette thbe a la disposition des pasonnes intQes&s. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conserve la propriCt6 du copyright in Merthesis. Neither hit#auteur qui prot&gesa thh. Ni the thesis nor substantial extracts la these ni des exftaits substantiels de from it may be printed or otherwise celIe-ci ne doivent &re imprim& ou reproduced with the author's autrement reproduits sans son permission. Abstract The problem of proper nun- iaccounting for their meaning, that ir, lot the ability to provide retuence to objects of the world. We want to be able to uay that proper nama refer directly to objecta, rince that t their aaaumcd function in the use of ordinary language. But when ukd to rupply the meaning of r proper name, in general we are only able to oupply dedptive knowledge of an ~umedobject to which it refen, knowIdge which dmconsiderably hmwr to uaer. ken when the object b 8emibly present, we can only appeal to knowledge of catah sensations, or of certain idea; we cannot produce any entity which is nonndly thought to be, or to provide, the meaning of a proper name. In thir the& I explore the ilolutiom to this problem offered by variouu philo~o- phers, including Mill, Fkege, Rumell, Strawson and Kripke, all of whom have very different approaches. I condude that while $L of these thinkets have valuable in- rights into how we ought to think of objecta, how we actually think of objecta, how knowledge of objecta k obtained and rhard amongut urur of language, and to what extent thia knowledge ia nguind in providing the connection between a proper name and the object to which it rders, dl ruffec from the uame bdc inadequacy. This b the failure to get to grips with the problem of how the mental concept of a paxticular entity is abtracted from senuorg experience of the world, how it is independent of any patticulsr LnowIedge of the companding entity, how it functions to allow the idea of rderence to take place in the we of proper namcl, and how this idea of reference ia diatiact ftom the determination of rderence in practice, which is the acquisition of knowledge, of vatioua kinda, of an object in the normal use of its name. Acknowledgements A rpedd and num thank-you gom to my ruptrvisos, ProfitLome la, who provided not only inrightful critidm and encouragement at the critical momenta, but .Ira much appreciated enthudam and patience, and who met dl difliculties with a great mnae of humout. I would ahlike to utclld thanka to Dan Chamberlain, Hazy Laycock, AdMe Mercier, and Sergio Siamondo for their ad* in the preparation of tbl work. I wodd like to upnu my gratitude to The Department d Philomphy, The School of Graduate Studiea, and Student Ad,mpeddly to Dt. David Bakhont, Profagor Ron Andemon, and Pat Boptad, for sympathetic dvband help in procuring the finand urbtance that enabled me to complete my utudieu at Queen's. Finally, I would Ueto aay thanks to Maxine Whnand Jackie Doh- fot never failing to be the friends and comrader wh- presence at the Philoaopby Department at Queeda would be aorely mimed, and to ail the rttldentu at the CFD lab for putting up with me. Contents Acknowledgements 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Theproblem ........................... 2 1.2 The Strategy ........................... 3 2 Backgro~d 6 2.1 J.S.MU .............................. 6 2.1.1 On Connotation and Denotation ............. 7 2.1.2 Concluding RemarIts ................... 9 2.2 Gottlobhge ........................... 11 2.2.1 OnSensemdRefmmct ................. 11 2.2.2 On B~~ffwchn'f..................... 13 2.2.3 Concluding Remarlca ................... 14 2.3 Bdand Ruad ......................... 15 2.3.1 Rurrell'e Metaphyric ................... 15 2.3.2 On the Role of Proper Names .............. 19 CONTENTS iv 2.3.3 On the Meaning of Proper Namea ............ 21 2.3.4 OntheMbrenaofProp~~N8m~~........... 24 2.3.5 Concluding Ramarks ................... 28 2.4 P.F. Strawson ........................... 31 2.4.1 On RddgExpraaionr ................ 31 2.4.2 On Proper Namm ..................... 34 2.4.3 Concluding baks ................... 38 2.5 Summary and Conclusions .................... 39 3 The Causal Theory 46 3.1 Saul Kripke's Causal Chain Theory ............... 45 3.2 Against the Ref'Uae of Dcmiptione ............ 48 3.2.1 Reference in Possible Worlds ............... 49 On Rigid Designation in Possible Worlds ......... 51 On the Use of Deaiptions in Possible Worlds ...... 52 Concluding Remarks .................... 56 3.2.2 Reference in the Actual World .............. 57 On the Use of Vague and Chular Daaiptions..... 57 On the Use of Mistaken Descriptionb. .......... 60 Concluding Remarks .................... 62 3.3 The Elimination of Descriptive Refkrence ............ 64 3.3.1 InBaptism ........................ 65 3.3.2 Io Reidentification .................... 67 3.3.3 In the Communication of Names ............. 68 3.3.4 Concluding Remuks ................... 70 3.4 The Use of Intentions to Wkr .................. 71 CONTENTS v 3.4.1 htentiona are Necuaazy but not Suf6cient ....... 71 3.4.2 Inkntiom and Dcraiptive Refmace .......... 74 3.4.3 Concluding Rem~~~kr................... 76 3.5 Conrequcnar of Ktipke'~Theory ................ 77 3.5.1 Neamazy o poutcribti Knowbdge ............ 77 3.5.2 Contingent a priori Knowledge ............. 81 3.5.3 Etwentid Pmpertiea .................... 87 3.5.4 Concluding Remcvka ................... 93 3.6 SummaryandCondwiona ..................... 96 4 Conclusion 89 4.1 Thesolution ........................... 99 4.1.1 The Type Identity of Propa Nama ...........101 4.1.2 The Token Identity of Proper Namea ..........103 4.1.3 Concluding Ransrk~ ...................105 Notes and References 108 Selected Bibliography 119 Vita 122 Chapter 1 Introduction Generalisations of any kind are dangaous, and of such a broad and encorn- passing discipline as philosophy, they are perhaps doubly so. Nevertheless, I think it can be fairly raid that the greater part of the Weatern philomphical tradition has always been united in the common came of investigating ques- tions of truth, even if, as Bertrand Russell pointr out, it ir in the nature of philosophers to become disinterested in the problems of philosophy 6Wll as answers to them are in danger of being found.' A cursory glance over the history of philosophy tends to confirm that a great deal of time and effort has been spent on investigating both the nature of truthful statement8 about the world, and the word that maka them true. In recent times, however, science has become increasingly entnuted with investigations of the latter, while, not coincidmtdly, philosophy ha become increasingly dominated by questions of the formu. The result ir that language, alteady the medium of the investigation, is now also its primary focus.' CHAPTER 1. 1N.TRODUCTlON 2 If a philosophy of language ir to account for the capability of language to express t~ths,it must fint of all account for the capability of language to make reference to the world itself~rrtcogniuable partr of it-about which it expresses truths. It mmut, in dect, account for the relatiomhip between language and the world which justifha our speaking about the world. The most straightfonratd and convenient way, but by no means the only way, of referring to parts of the world in to we linguistic nipthat atand in for them directly. In ordinaxy language, these dgn8 are cakd proper naznea. The study of nameo provides an obvioua starting point for datifying the problems associated with the relatiomhip between language and the world. They are, if you like, the most primal of word types. The very fint linguistic acts of humans are to attach names to recognirable things of interat in their environment, and this is just ar true today, when each one of w starts out on the long road of learning language, as it waa when as a race we started out on the much longer road of creating it. 1.1 The Problem A name, of course, like any linguistic sign, is a sound ~pokenor a mark written; what makes it of interest is its meaning. What I am concerned to investigate here is the meaning, or significance, of proper names. But by this I am not concerned with the meaning of names m they might be discovered by looking in a dictionary. The name 'Jceebel' means, for example, according to the dictionary, 'A shameless or immoral wo~nm.'~But people who are shameless, immoral and female ate not all given the name 'Jezebel', aad CHAPTER 1. lNTROOUCTION neither ate all uses of the name applied ody to people who might have thae attributes; the name 'Jeaebel' could be given to amyone or, indeed, anything. As Hobbe8 said, a name is 'taken at phmre to 8me for a mark' of the individuality of some thing? Although a word that atarts out purely in that mode may come to be ~aociatedwith a general meaning by association with the qualities of the thing it happens to mark out, and a word may be chosen as a name for some thing because of such a genera meaning pmioudy picked up, this adjectival use of certain word8 that also act as propa names should not distract us from the separate issue of accounting for the relationship between a name, as a mark, and the particular thing it is a mask of.
Recommended publications
  • Reference and Definite Descriptions1
    Philosophical Review !"#"$"%&"'(%)'*"#+%+,"'*"-&$+.,+/%- 01,2/$3-45'6"+,2'78'*/%%"99(% 7/1$&"5':2"';2+9/-/.2+&(9'!"<+"=>'?/98'@A>'B/8'C'3D198>'EFGG4>'..8'HIEJCKL ;1M9+-2")'MN5'*1O"'P%+<"$-+,N';$"--'/%'M"2(9#'/#';2+9/-/.2+&(9'!"<+"= 7,(M9"'P!Q5'http://www.jstor.org/stable/2183143 0&&"--")5'KARKIRHKEK'EA5HC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org REFERENCE AND DEFINITE DESCRIPTIONS1 I DEFINITE descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible func- tions.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottlob Frege Patricia A
    Gottlob Frege Patricia A. Blanchette This is the penultimate version of the essay whose final version appears in the Oxford Handbook of Nineteenth-Century German Philosophy, M. Forster and K. Gjesdal (eds), Oxford University Press 2015, pp 207-227 Abstract Gottlob Frege (1848-1925) made significant contributions to both pure mathematics and philosophy. His most important technical contribution, of both mathematical and philosophical significance, is the introduction of a formal system of quantified logic. His work of a more purely- philosophical kind includes the articulation and persuasive defense of anti-psychologism in mathematics and logic, the rigorous pursuit of the thesis that arithmetic is reducible to logic, and the introduction of the distinction between sense and reference in the philosophy of language. Frege’s work has gone on to influence contemporary work across a broad spectrum, including the philosophy of mathematics and logic, the philosophy of language, and the philosophy of mind. This essay describes the historical development of Frege’s central views, and the connections between those views. Introduction Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege was born on November 8, 1848 in the Hanseatic town of Wismar. He was educated in mathematics at the University of Jena and at the University of Göttingen, from which latter he received his doctorate in 1873. He defended his Habilitation the next year in Jena, and took up a position immediately at the University of Jena. Here he spent his entire academic career, lecturing in mathematics and logic, retiring in 1918. His death came on July 26, 1925 in the nearby town of Bad Kleinen.1 Frege is best known for three significant contributions to philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwig.Wittgenstein.-.Philosophical.Investigations.Pdf
    PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS By LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN Translated by G. E. M. ANSCOMBE BASIL BLACKWELL TRANSLATOR'S NOTE Copyright © Basil Blackwell Ltd 1958 MY acknowledgments are due to the following, who either checked First published 1953 Second edition 1958 the translation or allowed me to consult them about German and Reprint of English text alone 1963 Austrian usage or read the translation through and helped me to Third edition of English and German text with index 1967 improve the English: Mr. R. Rhees, Professor G. H. von Wright, Reprint of English text with index 1968, 1972, 1974, 1976, 1978, Mr. P. Geach, Mr. G. Kreisel, Miss L. Labowsky, Mr. D. Paul, Miss I. 1981, 1986 Murdoch. Basil Blackwell Ltd 108 Cowley Road, Oxford, OX4 1JF, UK All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purposes of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be NOTE TO SECOND EDITION reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or THE text has been revised for the new edition. A large number of otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher. small changes have been made in the English text. The following passages have been significantly altered: Except in the United States of America, this book is sold to the In Part I: §§ 108, 109, 116, 189, 193, 251, 284, 352, 360, 393,418, condition that it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise, be lent, re- 426, 442, 456, 493, 520, 556, 582, 591, 644, 690, 692.
    [Show full text]
  • The Theory of Descriptions 1. Bertrand Russell (1872-1970): Mathematician, Logician, and Philosopher
    Louis deRosset { Spring 2019 Russell: The Theory of Descriptions 1. Bertrand Russell (1872-1970): mathematician, logician, and philosopher. He's one of the founders of analytic philosophy. \On Denoting" is a founding document of analytic philosophy. It is a paradigm of philosophical analysis. An analysis of a concept/phenomenon c: a recipe for eliminating c-vocabulary from our theories which still captures all of the facts the c-vocabulary targets. FOR EXAMPLE: \The Name View Analysis of Identity." 2. Russell's target: Denoting Phrases By a \denoting phrase" I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the present King of France, the centre of mass of the Solar System at the first instant of the twentieth century, the revolution of the earth round the sun, the revolution of the sun round the earth. (479) Includes: • universals: \all F 's" (\each"/\every") • existentials: \some F " (\at least one") • indefinite descriptions: \an F " • definite descriptions: \the F " Later additions: • negative existentials: \no F 's" (480) • Genitives: \my F " (\your"/\their"/\Joe's"/etc.) (484) • Empty Proper Names: \Apollo", \Hamlet", etc. (491) Russell proposes to analyze denoting phrases. 3. Why Analyze Denoting Phrases? Russell's Project: The distinction between acquaintance and knowledge about is the distinction between the things we have presentation of, and the things we only reach by means of denoting phrases. [. ] In perception we have acquaintance with the objects of perception, and in thought we have acquaintance with objects of a more abstract logical character; but we do not necessarily have acquaintance with the objects denoted by phrases composed of words with whose meanings we are ac- quainted.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI 565-Russell
    Philosophy 565: Philosophy of Language Prof. Clare Batty Russell, “On Denoting” 1. More Philosophical Jargon definite description: a singular noun phrase which applies to exactly one person, often beginning with the definite article: e.g., ‘the funniest woman in Canada’, the present King of France’. According to Russell, a phrase is denoting solely “in virtue of its form”. This is to say, the phrase needn’t actually denote in order to be a denoting phrase. Law of the Excluded Middle: By the law of the excluded middle, either ‘A is B’ or ‘A is not B’ must be true. 2. Frege and Russell We now know that Frege is committed to: (F3) Ordinary proper names and definite descriptions are singular terms. (F4) Ordinary proper names and definite descriptions all have sense (and perhaps reference). (ST1) The business of a singular term is to refer to an object. (ST2) A sentence containing a singular term has no truth-value if there is no object corresponding to that singular term. Russell’s focus is on definite descriptions. Not under discussion at this point: proper names (e.g. ‘Clare’, ‘Kentucky’, etc.) Russell denies (F3) and, as a result (he claims), (F4). Like Frege, Russell thinks that his alternative view can deal with certain problems. “The evidence for [my] theory is derived from difficulties which seem unavoidable if we regard denoting phrases as standing for genuine constituents of the propositions in whose verbal expressions they occur." We have seen some of these before: (P1) Frege’s Puzzle About Identity (P2) Substitutivity (P3) Apparent Reference to Non-Existents And some more: (P4) Law of the Excluded Middle (LEM) By the LEM, either (S1) ‘The King of France is bald’ or (S2) ‘The King of France is not bald’ had better be true.
    [Show full text]
  • Kripke's Naming and Necessity: Lecture II
    Kripke’s Naming and Necessity: Lecture II PHIL 83104 October 12, 2011 1. Varieties of descriptivism (end of Lecture I) ....................................................................1 2. Kripke’s arguments against descriptivism (71-90) ...........................................................2 2.1. The modal argument (48-49, 71-77) 2.1.1. Rigidified descriptions 2.1.2. Wide-scoping descriptions 2.2. The semantic argument (78-85) 2.3. The epistemic argument (86-87) 3. Kripke’s alternative picture of reference (91-97) ..............................................................5 4. Identity sentences and the necessary a posteriori (97-105) ..............................................7 4.1. The necessity of identity 4.2. A prioricity and qualitatively identical situations 4.3. Some sources of skepticism about Kripke’s claim 4.3.1. Contingent identities? 4.3.2. The illusion of contingency 4.3.3. Millianism about names 1. VARIETIES OF DESCRIPTIVISM (END OF LECTURE I) We’ve already seen two distinctions Kripke makes between different versions of descriptivism: • The distinction between descriptivist views which let a single description do the work, and those which rely on a cluster of descriptions • The distinctiopn between views according to which a description gives the meaning of a name, and those according to which it merely fixes the reference of the name Here Kripke introduces a third distinction: between circular and non-circular descriptivist views. This distinction is not like the others; it is less a distinction between varieties of descriptivism than a constraint on descriptivist views. What exactly is this constraint? Suppose we identified the meaning of the name “Aristotle” with the meaning of the description “the person called ‘Aristotle’” or “the referent of ‘Aristotle.’” These would be examples of descriptivist views which fail to meet the non-circularity condition, since to determine what object satisfies the description, we must first know which object is the referent of the name in question.
    [Show full text]
  • PROPER NAMES: ONE CENTURY of DISCUSSION Uxía RIVAS
    Logica Trianguli, 3, 1999, 119-138 PROPER NAMES: ONE CENTURY OF DISCUSSION Uxía RIVAS MONROY Abstract The main objective of this paper is to offer an overview of some of the most relevant and at the same time controversial aspects of proper names over this last century. Therefore, the intention is not to go deeply into all the issues re- lated to proper names, though special attention will be paid to one of them for its importance, namely, the discussion as to whether proper names have sense or meaning associated to them or whether they are directly referential expressions. In the same way, only a few of all the authors who have made theories, comments or analyses about proper names will be mentioned in this article. The subject of proper names is complex enough in spite of its apparent simplicity, so as to leave many lines of analysis open, which are not deeply dealt with in this pres- entation. 1. Introduction Proper names form part of the most general category of singular terms, that is, of expressions characterised for referring or denoting only one object or individual; therefore, and taking this consideration into account, definite descriptions and the wide range of indexicals will also be singular terms. Following Strawson’s terminology we could say that singular terms, and in particular proper names, are the types of expressions generally used to make singularizing references, i.e. they are the expressions which tend to have a “uniquely referring use”. What we generally have in mind as speakers of a language when talking about proper names is the most paradigmatic examples of them, such as Galicia, Paris, Socrates, Atenea, Ulises, Mary, John; however, we may also consider “The Holy Roman Empire”, “The United States of America”, “The Hercules Tower”, “The Second World War” as proper names; and surely we would not consider “The dean of the Faculty of Philosophy”, “The present king of France”, “The director of the gen- eral library of Santiago” as proper names.
    [Show full text]
  • Frege and the Logic of Sense and Reference
    FREGE AND THE LOGIC OF SENSE AND REFERENCE Kevin C. Klement Routledge New York & London Published in 2002 by Routledge 29 West 35th Street New York, NY 10001 Published in Great Britain by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane London EC4P 4EE Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper. Copyright © 2002 by Kevin C. Klement All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any infomration storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Klement, Kevin C., 1974– Frege and the logic of sense and reference / by Kevin Klement. p. cm — (Studies in philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index ISBN 0-415-93790-6 1. Frege, Gottlob, 1848–1925. 2. Sense (Philosophy) 3. Reference (Philosophy) I. Title II. Studies in philosophy (New York, N. Y.) B3245.F24 K54 2001 12'.68'092—dc21 2001048169 Contents Page Preface ix Abbreviations xiii 1. The Need for a Logical Calculus for the Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 3 Introduction 3 Frege’s Project: Logicism and the Notion of Begriffsschrift 4 The Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 8 The Limitations of the Begriffsschrift 14 Filling the Gap 21 2. The Logic of the Grundgesetze 25 Logical Language and the Content of Logic 25 Functionality and Predication 28 Quantifiers and Gothic Letters 32 Roman Letters: An Alternative Notation for Generality 38 Value-Ranges and Extensions of Concepts 42 The Syntactic Rules of the Begriffsschrift 44 The Axiomatization of Frege’s System 49 Responses to the Paradox 56 v vi Contents 3.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defense of Denotative Theory from Kripke's Criticism
    Tomoya Imaizumi 57 A Defense of Denotative Theory from Kripke’s Criticism Tomoya Imaizumi n Naming and Necessity, Kripke criticizes the denotative theory of reference and proposes a version of the causal theory of ref- erence. The outline of the discussion between these two theo- I ries is the following: the denotative theory is advocated by Rus- sell, who thinks that the reference of a name is determined by the definite description the name gives. Kripke, however, opposes this idea; he thinks that names can designate objects without description, and proposes his version of the causal theory. In this paper, I attempt to examine the criticism given by Kripke and defend the denotative theory from it. I then challenge the causal theory. Finally, I will show the ad- vantages and disadvantages of the denotative theory and the causal theory, along with a comparison between the two. To achieve this goal, it is first necessary to explain the denotative theory, the foundation of which is the notion of definite descriptions, before moving to an expla- nation of Kripke's version of the causal theory, the foundation of which is the notion of rigid designators. I. Description Theory and Denotative Theory In this section, I will explain what the description theory is, Tomoya Imaizumi is a senior studying philosophy at Kyoto University in Japan. His philosophical interests lie in philosophy of mathematics, philosophical logic and philosophy of physics. He is particularly inter- ested in Dummettian generalization from intuitionism to anti-realism, on which he is writing his senior thesis. He would like to continue studying philosophy at a graduate school in the U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • Proper Names, Beliefs, and Definite Descriptions
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1984 Proper names, beliefs, and definite descriptions. Thomas C. Ryckman University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Ryckman, Thomas C., "Proper names, beliefs, and definite descriptions." (1984). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 1789. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/1789 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. •'iuV'j » *-!'< Vr.’ — /: ' " FIVE COLLEGE , V V 'v DEPOSITORY PROPER NAMES, BELIEFS, AND DEFINITE DESCRIPTIONS A Dissertation Presented By THOMAS CHARLES RYCKMAN Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY September 1 984 Department of Philosophy Thomas Charles Ryckman © All Rights Reserved 11 PROPER NAMES, BELIEFS, AND DEFINITE DESCRIPTIONS A Dissertation Presented By THOMAS CHARLES RYCKMAN Approved as to style and content by: Edmund L. Gettier , III, ChairpersonChairpe of Committee Barbara Partee, Member obison, Member Michael Jubien, Department Head Department of Philosophy Dedicated, with love, to Susanne Burgess Ryckman IV . — ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I Wish to acknowledge my debt and gratitude to certain persons and institutions Edmund L. Gettier, III, has read and commented on three prior drafts of this dissertation, and on additional versions of some of its parts. He has patiently and -ski Hfu! guided !y me to more fully appreciate the complexity and subtlety of the issues I have considered.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter V Wittgenstein and the Composers
    Chapter V Wittgenstein and the Composers 1. Not Only Science But Art Also Teaches Writing about the influences on Ludwig Wittgenstein’s work, Georg Henrik von Wright remarks that Wittgenstein received deeper impressions from some writers in the borderlands between philosophy, religion, and poetry than from professional philosophers.1 Surprisingly, von Wright does not mention composers of music despite the fact that Wittgenstein also criss-crossed the borderlands between music and philosophy and received nourishing ideas for his line of thinking from composers. The question that recurs, and that I now address from a different angle, is: who are these composers and tone poets whom Wittgenstein took up for his own work and why? What motivates this question is an unexamined assumption in the modern culture of the West about a division of labour: scientists instruct us and artists entertain us. This assumption, as we have seen already in our discussion of Hanslick, is a prominent feature of the scientistic culture that developed in the second half of the nineteenth century, became pervasive in the twentieth century and is now part of the prevailing cultural ideology. Wittgenstein rejected this complacent dichotomy between scientists and artists: “People nowadays think, scientists are there to instruct them, poets, musicians etc. to entertain them. That the latter have something to teach them; that never occurs to them”.2 Examining this assumption in light of Wittgenstein’s remarks about the composers he engages in his writings—Bach, Mozart, Haydn, Beethoven, Mendelssohn, Schumann, Schubert, Wagner, Mahler and Labor—may help us to understand why he read and listened to composers and how the allusions to music and “tone poets” have 1 Von Wright, Wittgenstein, 33.
    [Show full text]
  • Donnellan: “Reference and Definite Descriptions”
    Donnellan: “Reference and Definite Descriptions” TWO USES OF DESCRIPTIONS Donnellan argues that neither Russell nor Strawson is right. Each is partly right, because each focuses on just one of two different uses of definite descriptions. And, in spite of their opposition, they share some false assumptions in common. The two uses: attributive and referential. Attributive “A speaker who uses a definite description attributively in an assertion states something about whoever or whatever is the so-and-so” (p. 267, left) Referential “A speaker who uses a definite description referentially in an assertion … uses the description to enable his audience to pick out whom or what he is talking about and states something about that person or thing” (p. 267, left) An illustration of the difference: “Smith’s murderer is insane.” Attributive: the speaker says this without having any particular person in mind, basing his claim solely on the particularly brutal manner in which Smith has been murdered. Referential: Jones has been charged with the murder and has been put on trial, where his behavior is distinctly odd. The speaker (having Jones in mind) utters the same sentence. CRITICISM OF RUSSELL AND STRAWSON Against Russell: Russell’s theory applies at most to the attributive use of descriptions. He fails to account for the referential use. So Russell gets one of the two uses (the attributive), but misses the other. Against Strawson: Strawson’s theory accommodates the referential use, but “it goes too far in this direction” (p. 271, bottom left). For it fails to allow for the referential use to occur successfully even though nothing satisfies the description.
    [Show full text]