A Coloring Theorem for Inaccessible Cardinals a Dissertation Presented

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Coloring Theorem for Inaccessible Cardinals a Dissertation Presented A Coloring Theorem for Inaccessible Cardinals A dissertation presented to the faculty of the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy Douglas J. Hoffman December 2013 c 2013. Douglas J. Hoffman. All Rights Reserved. 2 This dissertation titled A Coloring Theorem for Inaccessible Cardinals by DOUGLAS J. HOFFMAN has been approved for the Department of Mathematics and the College of Arts and Sciences Todd Eisworth Associate Professor of Mathematics Robert Frank Dean, College of Arts and Sciences 3 Abstract HOFFMAN, DOUGLAS J., Ph.D., December 2013, Mathematics A Coloring Theorem for Inaccessible Cardinals (73 pp.) Director of Dissertation: Todd Eisworth This dissertation proves a coloring theorem for inaccessible cardinals having a stationary subset S ⊂ fδ < κ : cf(δ) = λg that does not reflect in any inaccessible cardinal for a fixed regular uncountable cardinal λ. The theorem shows we can give 2 an \approximate" yes to κ 6! [κ]κ. Recent work of Eisworth has produced partition theorems in the case of successors of singular cardinals, and this dissertation extends his ideas to inaccessible cardinals with a stationary subset that does not reflect in any inaccessible cardinal and consists of singular cardinals of uncountable cofinality. Club- guessing sequences, minimal walks and elementary submodels are used in the proof of the theorem. First, the existence of a nice S-club guessing sequence is established κ when S ⊆ Sλ . After proving the existence of this club-guessing sequence, we look at constructing a club-guessing sequence when S consists of inaccessible cardinals and C is an S-club sequence satisfying ⊗C . Then, we study weakly normal ideals and the effects of a least function on an ideal. The behavior of a least function can have a strong affect on the ideal. When a least function fails to be regressive in a rather strong fashion, this failure forces the ideal to be weakly normal. After investigating weakly normal ideals, the ideal idp(C; I) is introduced, and a coloring is constructed to prove the main theorem in this paper. This coloring has the property that the range of any unbounded subset of κ is almost κ. Using this coloring, we show the 2 ideal idp(C; I) is weakly κ-saturated if κ ! [κ]κ holds. 4 To my wife, Beth, and to my parents, Michael and Lynnae 5 Acknowledgments I would like to thank my wife, Beth, for her love and support through the years. She has been with me for this stage of my life. From my first day of graduate school to the writing of this paper, she has been with me every step of the way and supporting me any way she can. It takes a lot of patience to hear someone talk about something only a few people would find interesting. I would like to thank my parents, Michael and Lynnae Hoffman. They let me do my own thing and taught me to always give it your best effort. Without their support, none of this would be possible. Also, I would like to express my gratitude to my advisor, Dr. Todd Eisworth. His help and advice was not limited to the writing of this dissertation. He got me interested in combinatorial set theory and introduced me to partition theorems. With his help, I was able to explore a rich fragment of combinatorial set theory and con- tribute to the theory. Under his guidance, I was able to go from a graduate student in mathematics to a mathematician. I would also like to thank the members of my dissertation committee for investing time in this manuscript. Chris Baily-Brown, Tammy Matson and Kelly Pero have my gratitude. They have helped me numerous times over the years with forms and deadlines I would have forgotten about. Lastly, I would like to thank Karen Ernst at Hawkeye Community College. She showed me that it was okay to be enthusiastic about mathematics, and doing so, she set me on the path to become a mathematician. 6 Table of Contents Abstract..............................3 Dedication..............................4 Acknowledgments...........................5 1 Introduction...........................7 1.1 What Has Been Done So Far..................7 1.2 Goals For The Paper..................... 15 2 Existence of Nice Club-Guessing Sequences.............. 17 2.1 Club-Guessing Sequences................... 17 2.2 Nice Club-Guessing Sequences: Uncountable Cofinality....... 23 2.3 Constructing A Club-Guessing Sequence Using ⊗C ........ 31 3 Weakly Normal Ideals....................... 37 3.1 An Introduction to Ideals and Filters.............. 37 3.2 Introduction to Weak Normality................ 39 3.3 Weak Normality Arises.................... 41 4 Partition Results......................... 55 4.1 Motivation For The Main Theorem............... 55 4.2 Minimal Walks........................ 55 4.3 The Ideal idp(C; I)...................... 59 4.4 The Main Theorem...................... 63 Bibliography............................. 72 7 1 Introduction 1.1 What Has Been Done So Far The ultimate goal of this dissertation is prove a coloring theorem for certain infinite cardinals. In particular, our focus will be on the negation of the square- bracket relation in the realm of inaccessible cardinals. There has been a lot of work done with the negation of the square-bracket relation. Todorˇcevi´c'swork in [15] describes what happens in the case of the successor of a regular cardinal. Eisworth's work [5, 6, 4] has produced results in the case of successors of singular cardinals. Chapters III and IV of [13] are dedicated to square-bracket partition relations on inaccessible cardinals. Our goals for this paper focus on extending the techniques used on successors of singular cardinals to inaccessible cardinals. Our work builds on a long line of research. In [15], Todorˇcevi´ccreated his method of minimal walks and established a relation between stationary reflection and the failure of a square-bracket relation. Shelah created a plethora of tools utilized in the case of the successor of a singular cardinal. Such tools include club-guessing sequences, club-guessing ideals and scales. In a series of papers, Eisworth has obtained many results dealing with the successors of a singular cardinals. Eisworth's result in [4] is Todorˇcevi´c-like; it relates the failure of a square-bracket relation to stationary reflection. To understand the failure of the square-bracket relation, we start with a brief look at ordinary partition relations. Then, we will see that the failure of an ordinary partition relation leads us to a weak form of homogeneity: the square-bracket relation. From there, we look at the results of Todorˇcevi´cand Eisworth, and end with the goals of this paper. 8 To begin, we look at the following famous theorem in combinatorial set theory: Ramsey's Theorem. THEOREM 1.1.1 (Ramsey's Theorem, [11]) Suppose c :[!]2 ! f0; 1g. Then 2 there is an H ⊆ ! such that f [H] is constant. The function c is referred to as a coloring, and the subset H is said to be homo- geneous for c. A natural question to ask is to what extent does Ramsey's theorem generalize to uncountable cardinals? Before we consider generalizations of Ramsey's theorem, we will remind the reader of arrow notation introduced by Erd}osand Hajnal in [8]. DEFINITION 1.1.1 Let γ be an ordinal, and let κ, λ, τ be cardinals. The symbol λ κ ! (τ)γ is used to indicate that the following assertion holds: For an arbitrary set X of cardinality κ and for every γ-partition f :[X]λ ! γ, there is a set Y ⊆ X and ordinal ν < γ such that jY j = τ and f"[Y ]λ = fνg: Relations of this form are called ordinary partition relations. Ramsey's theo- rem can be restated using this notation. THEOREM 1.1.2 (Ramsey's Theorem) 2 ! ! (!)2 When an ordinary partition relation holds, we know that no matter how [X]λ is partitioned into γ pieces, there will always be a set Y ⊆ X of size τ and ν < γ such that set [Y ]λ is contained in the νth piece of the partition. When dealing with 9 partition relations, we sometimes think of a partition of [κ]λ as a coloring of subsets of κ of size λ. Back to generalizing Ramsey's theorem. One can ask if there are other cardinals for which Ramsey's theorem holds? Equivalently, is there an uncountable cardinal κ for which 2 κ ! (κ)2 @0 2 holds? Sierpi´nksiproved it does not hold in general by showing 2 6! (@1)2. His proof was generalized to show that if Ramsey's theorem holds for an un- countable κ, then κ has to be a strong limit cardinal. Another easy argument shows 2 that Ramsey's theorem fails for singular cardinals, so if κ ! (κ)2, then κ has to be 2 strongly inaccessible. Much more is known: uncountable cardinals for which κ ! (κ)2 are called weakly compact, and they have been studied extensively. Now, we consider the situation when an ordinary partition relation fails. When λ λ κ ! (µ)2 fails, there is a way to partition [κ] into two sets such that for any Y ⊆ κ with jY j = µ,[Y ]λ intersects both parts of the partition. Said another way, there is a function c :[κ]2 ! f0; 1g such that for any Y ⊆ κ with jY j = µ, we have λ rng(f [A] ) = f0; 1g: When an ordinary partition relation fails, it says the partition is complicated in the sense it takes on both colors when restricted to each unbounded subset. If we increase the number of colors, we get a more drastic failure of Ramsey's theorem.
Recommended publications
  • Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive?
    Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive? Neil Barton∗ 24 June 2020y Abstract The independence phenomenon in set theory, while perva- sive, can be partially addressed through the use of large cardinal axioms. A commonly assumed idea is that large cardinal axioms are species of maximality principles. In this paper, I argue that whether or not large cardinal axioms count as maximality prin- ciples depends on prior commitments concerning the richness of the subset forming operation. In particular I argue that there is a conception of maximality through absoluteness, on which large cardinal axioms are restrictive. I argue, however, that large cardi- nals are still important axioms of set theory and can play many of their usual foundational roles. Introduction Large cardinal axioms are widely viewed as some of the best candi- dates for new axioms of set theory. They are (apparently) linearly ordered by consistency strength, have substantial mathematical con- sequences for questions independent from ZFC (such as consistency statements and Projective Determinacy1), and appear natural to the ∗Fachbereich Philosophie, University of Konstanz. E-mail: neil.barton@uni- konstanz.de. yI would like to thank David Aspero,´ David Fernandez-Bret´ on,´ Monroe Eskew, Sy-David Friedman, Victoria Gitman, Luca Incurvati, Michael Potter, Chris Scam- bler, Giorgio Venturi, Matteo Viale, Kameryn Williams and audiences in Cambridge, New York, Konstanz, and Sao˜ Paulo for helpful discussion. Two anonymous ref- erees also provided helpful comments, and I am grateful for their input. I am also very grateful for the generous support of the FWF (Austrian Science Fund) through Project P 28420 (The Hyperuniverse Programme) and the VolkswagenStiftung through the project Forcing: Conceptual Change in the Foundations of Mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Set-Theoretical Background 1.1 Ordinals and Cardinals
    Set-Theoretical Background 11 February 2019 Our set-theoretical framework will be the Zermelo{Fraenkel axioms with the axiom of choice (ZFC): • Axiom of Extensionality. If X and Y have the same elements, then X = Y . • Axiom of Pairing. For all a and b there exists a set fa; bg that contains exactly a and b. • Axiom Schema of Separation. If P is a property (with a parameter p), then for all X and p there exists a set Y = fx 2 X : P (x; p)g that contains all those x 2 X that have the property P . • Axiom of Union. For any X there exists a set Y = S X, the union of all elements of X. • Axiom of Power Set. For any X there exists a set Y = P (X), the set of all subsets of X. • Axiom of Infinity. There exists an infinite set. • Axiom Schema of Replacement. If a class F is a function, then for any X there exists a set Y = F (X) = fF (x): x 2 Xg. • Axiom of Regularity. Every nonempty set has a minimal element for the membership relation. • Axiom of Choice. Every family of nonempty sets has a choice function. 1.1 Ordinals and cardinals A set X is well ordered if it is equipped with a total order relation such that every nonempty subset S ⊆ X has a smallest element. The statement that every set admits a well ordering is equivalent to the axiom of choice. A set X is transitive if every element of an element of X is an element of X.
    [Show full text]
  • Florida State University Libraries
    )ORULGD6WDWH8QLYHUVLW\/LEUDULHV 2020 Justifying Alternative Foundations for Mathematics Jared M. Ifland Follow this and additional works at DigiNole: FSU's Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected] THE FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF ARTS & SCIENCES JUSTIFYING ALTERNATIVE FOUNDATIONS FOR MATHEMATICS By JARED M. IFLAND A Thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation with Honors in the Major Degree Awarded: Spring, 2020 The members of the Defense Committee approve the thesis of Jared M. Ifland defended on July 17, 2020. ______________________________ Dr. James Justus Thesis Director ______________________________ Dr. Ettore Aldrovandi Outside Committee Member ______________________________ Dr. J. Piers Rawling Committee Member Abstract: It is inarguable that mathematics serves a quintessential role in the natural sciences and that ZFC — extended by large cardinal axioms — provides a foundation for vast swaths of contemporary mathematics. As such, it is understandable that the naturalistic philosopher may inquire into the ontological status of mathematical entities and sets. Many have argued that the indispensability of mathematics from scientific enterprise warrants belief in mathematical platonism, but it is unclear how knowledge of entities that exist independently of the natural world is possible. Furthermore, indispensability arguments are notoriously antithetical to mathematical practice: mathematicians typically do not refer to scientific
    [Show full text]
  • SET THEORY for CATEGORY THEORY 3 the Category Is Well-Powered, Meaning That Each Object Has Only a Set of Iso- Morphism Classes of Subobjects
    SET THEORY FOR CATEGORY THEORY MICHAEL A. SHULMAN Abstract. Questions of set-theoretic size play an essential role in category theory, especially the distinction between sets and proper classes (or small sets and large sets). There are many different ways to formalize this, and which choice is made can have noticeable effects on what categorical constructions are permissible. In this expository paper we summarize and compare a num- ber of such “set-theoretic foundations for category theory,” and describe their implications for the everyday use of category theory. We assume the reader has some basic knowledge of category theory, but little or no prior experience with formal logic or set theory. 1. Introduction Since its earliest days, category theory has had to deal with set-theoretic ques- tions. This is because unlike in most fields of mathematics outside of set theory, questions of size play an essential role in category theory. A good example is Freyd’s Special Adjoint Functor Theorem: a functor from a complete, locally small, and well-powered category with a cogenerating set to a locally small category has a left adjoint if and only if it preserves small limits. This is always one of the first results I quote when people ask me “are there any real theorems in category theory?” So it is all the more striking that it involves in an essential way notions like ‘locally small’, ‘small limits’, and ‘cogenerating set’ which refer explicitly to the difference between sets and proper classes (or between small sets and large sets). Despite this, in my experience there is a certain amount of confusion among users and students of category theory about its foundations, and in particular about what constructions on large categories are or are not possible.
    [Show full text]
  • How Set Theory Impinges on Logic
    1 Jesús Mosterín HOW SET THEORY IMPINGES ON LOGIC The set-theoretical universe Reality often cannot be grasped and understood in its unfathomable richness and mind-blowing complexity. Think only of the trivial case of the shape of the Earth. Every time the wind blows, a bird flies, a tree drops a leave, every time it rains, a car moves or we get a haircut, the form of the Earth changes. No available or conceivable geometry can describe the ever changing form of the surface of our planet. Sometimes the best we can do is to apply the method of theoretical science: to pick up a mathematical structure from the set-theoretical universe, a structure that has some formal similarities with some features of the real world situation we are interested in, and to use that structure as a model of that parcel of the world. In the case of the Earth, the structure can be an Euclidean sphere, or a sphere flattened at the poles, or an ellipsoid, but of course these structures do not represent the car and the hair, and so are realistic only up to a point. The largest part of scientific activity results in data, in contributions to history (in a broad sense). Only exceptionally does scientific activity result in abstract schemata, in formulas, in theories. In history there is truth and falsity, but we are not sure whether it makes sense to apply these same categories to an abstract theory. We pick up a mathematical structure and construct a theory. We still have to determine its scope of application or validity, the range of its realizations.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2009.07164V1 [Math.LO] 15 Sep 2020 Ai—U Nta Eeyb Etoigfaue Htuiul Char Uniquely That Isomorphism
    CATEGORICAL LARGE CARDINALS AND THE TENSION BETWEEN CATEGORICITY AND SET-THEORETIC REFLECTION JOEL DAVID HAMKINS AND HANS ROBIN SOLBERG Abstract. Inspired by Zermelo’s quasi-categoricity result characterizing the models of second-order Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory ZFC2, we investigate when those models are fully categorical, characterized by the addition to ZFC2 ei- ther of a first-order sentence, a first-order theory, a second-order sentence or a second-order theory. The heights of these models, we define, are the categor- ical large cardinals. We subsequently consider various philosophical aspects of categoricity for structuralism and realism, including the tension between categoricity and set-theoretic reflection, and we present (and criticize) a cat- egorical characterization of the set-theoretic universe hV, ∈i in second-order logic. Categorical accounts of various mathematical structures lie at the very core of structuralist mathematical practice, enabling mathematicians to refer to specific mathematical structures, not by having carefully to prepare and point at specially constructed instances—preserved like the one-meter iron bar locked in a case in Paris—but instead merely by mentioning features that uniquely characterize the structure up to isomorphism. The natural numbers hN, 0,Si, for example, are uniquely characterized by the Dedekind axioms, which assert that 0 is not a successor, that the successor func- tion S is one-to-one, and that every set containing 0 and closed under successor contains every number [Ded88, Ded01]. We know what we mean by the natural numbers—they have a definiteness—because we can describe features that com- pletely determine the natural number structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:Math/0009240V1
    A simple maximality principle Joel David Hamkins∗ The City University of New York† Carnegie Mellon University‡ http://math.gc.cuny.edu/faculty/hamkins October 24, 2018 Abstract. In this paper, following an idea of Christophe Chalons, I propose a new kind of forcing axiom, the Maximality Principle, which asserts that any sentence ϕ holding in some ˙ forcing extension V P and all subsequent extensions V P∗Q holds already in V . It follows, in fact, that such sentences must also hold in all forcing extensions of V . In modal terms, therefore, the Maximality Principle is expressed by the scheme (✸ ϕ) =⇒ ϕ, and is equivalent to the modal theory S5. In this article, I prove that the Maximality Principle is relatively consistent with zfc. A boldface version of the Maximality Principle, obtained by allowing real parameters to appear in ϕ, is equiconsistent with the scheme asserting that Vδ ≺ V for an inaccessible cardinal δ, which in turn is equiconsistent with the scheme asserting that ord is mp mp V Mahlo. The strongest principle along these lines is ∼ , which asserts that ∼ holds in and all forcing extensions. From this, it follows that 0# exists, that x# exists for every set x, that projective truth is invariant by forcing, that Woodin cardinals are consistent and much more. Many open questions remain. 1 The Maximality Principle arXiv:math/0009240v1 [math.LO] 28 Sep 2000 Christophe Chalons has introduced a delightful new axiom, asserting in plain language that anything that is forceable and not subsequently unforceable is true. Specifically, in [2] he proposes the following principle: ∗My research has been supported by grants from the PSC-CUNY Research Foundation and the NSF.
    [Show full text]
  • TOPICS in SET THEORY: Example Sheet
    TOPICS IN SET THEORY: Example Sheet 4 1 Department of Pure Mathematics and Mathematical Statistics, University of Cambridge Michaelmas 2014-2015 Dr Oren Kolman; [email protected] This Example Sheet involves questions that require significant extensions of the material covered in lectures. Most are optional; on the other hand, several are core results, which are chosen to illustrate the richness and flexibility of forcing and set-theoretic methods. 1 Absoluteness Results (i) Show that the following properties are expressible by Σ1 -formulas: (a) α is not a cardinal; (b) cf(α) ≤ β ; (c) α is singular; (d) j x j ≤ j y j . (ii) Show that the following properties are expressible by Π1 -formulas: (a) α is a cardinal; (b) cf(α) is regular; (c) α is weakly inaccessible (i.e. α 6= λ+ for all λ ); (d) y = P (x); (e) the formula Vx = y . 2 Well-founded Relations and Absoluteness of P -names An L2 -formula '(v) is downward absolute (respectively, upward absolute) if whenever M is a transitive class, (8x 2 M)('(x) ! '(x)M) (respectively, (8x 2 M)('(x)M ! '(x)) . A class M is an inner model of ZF if M is transitive, Ord ⊆ M , and for every axiom ' of ZF , M j= ' (i.e. ZF ` 'M ). (i) Show that Σ1 -formulas are upward absolute and Π1 -formulas are downward abso- lute. (ii) Prove that if V j= (κ is an inaccessible cardinal ) , then A j= (κ is an inaccessible cardinal ) whenever A is an inner model of ZF . (iii) Let R be a binary relation over X .
    [Show full text]
  • Incompatible Ω-Complete Theories∗
    Incompatible Ω-Complete Theories∗ Peter Koellner and W. Hugh Woodin July 25, 2009 Abstract In 1985 the second author showed that if there is a proper class of mea- surable Woodin cardinals and V B1 and V B2 are generic extensions of V B1 B2 2 satisfying CH then V and V agree on all Σ1-statements. In terms of the strong logic Ω-logic this can be reformulated by saying that un- der the above large cardinal assumption ZFC + CH is Ω-complete for 2 2 Σ1. Moreover, CH is the unique Σ1-statement with this feature in the 2 sense that any other Σ1-statement with this feature is Ω-equivalent to CH over ZFC. It is natural to look for other strengthenings of ZFC that have an even greater degree of Ω-completeness. For example, one can ask for recursively enumerable axioms A such that relative to large cardinal axioms ZFC + A is Ω-complete for all of third-order arithmetic. Going further, for each specifiable segment Vλ of the uni- verse of sets (for example, one might take Vλ to be the least level that satisfies there is a proper class of huge cardinals), one can ask for recursively enumerable axioms A such that relative to large cardinal axioms ZFC + A is Ω-complete for the theory of Vλ. If such theories exist, extend one another, and are unique in the sense that any other such theory B with the same level of Ω-completeness as A is actually Ω-equivalent to A over ZFC, then this would show that there is a unique Ω-complete picture of the successive fragments of the universe of sets and it would make for a very strong case for axioms comple- menting large cardinal axioms.
    [Show full text]
  • AN Ω-LOGIC PRIMER Introduction One Family of Results in Modern Set
    AN ­-LOGIC PRIMER JOAN BAGARIA, NEUS CASTELLS, AND PAUL LARSON Abstract. In [12], Hugh Woodin introduced ­-logic, an approach to truth in the universe of sets inspired by recent work in large cardinals. Expository accounts of ­-logic appear in [13, 14, 1, 15, 16, 17]. In this paper we present proofs of some elementary facts about ­-logic, relative to the published literature, leading up to the generic invariance of ­- logic and the ­-conjecture. Introduction One family of results in modern set theory, called absoluteness results, shows that the existence of certain large cardinals implies that the truth values of certain sentences cannot be changed by forcing1. Another family of results shows that large cardinals imply that certain de¯nable sets of reals satisfy certain regularity properties, which in turn implies the existence of models satisfying other large cardinal properties. Results of the ¯rst type suggest a logic in which statements are said to be valid if they hold in every forcing extension. With some technical modi¯cations, this is Woodin's ­- logic, which ¯rst appeared in [12]. Results of the second type suggest that there should be a sort of internal characterization of validity in ­-logic. Woodin has proposed such a characterization, and the conjecture that it succeeds is called the ­-conjecture. Several expository papers on ­-logic and the ­-conjecture have been published [1, 13, 14, 15, 16, 17]. Here we briefly discuss the technical background of ­-logic, and prove some of the basic theorems in this area. This paper assumes a basic knowledge of Set Theory, including con- structibility and forcing.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructing Cardinals from Below
    Constructing Cardinals from Below W. W. Tait∗ The totality Ω of transfinite numbers was first introduced in [Cantor, 1883] by means of the principle If the initial segment Σ of Ω is a set, then it has a least strict upper bound S(Σ) ∈ Ω. Thus, for numbers α = S(Σ) and β = S(Σ0), α < β iff α ∈ Σ0; α = β iff Σ = Σ0; S(∅) is the least number 0 (although Cantor himself took the least number to be 1); if Σ has a greatest element γ, then α is its successor γ + 1; and if Σ is non-null and has no greatest element, then α is the least upper bound of Σ. The problem with the definition, of course, is in determining what it means for an initial segment to be a set. Obviously, not all of them are: for the totality Ω of all numbers is an initial segment, but to admit it as a set would yield S(Ω) < S(Ω), contradicting the assumption that Ω is well-ordered by <. Cantor himself understood this already in 1883. In his earlier writings, e.g. [1882], he had essentially defined a set ‘in some conceptual sphere’ such as arithmetic or geometry, to be the extension of a well-defined property. But in these cases, he was considering sets of objects of some type A, where being an object of type A is itself is not defined in terms of the notion of a set of objects of type A. But with his definition of the transfinite numbers, an entirely novel situation arises: the definition of Ω depends on the notion of a subset of Ω.
    [Show full text]
  • Large Cardinals and the Iterative Conception of Set
    Large cardinals and the iterative conception of set Neil Barton∗ 4 December 2017y Abstract The independence phenomenon in set theory, while pervasive, can be par- tially addressed through the use of large cardinal axioms. One idea sometimes alluded to is that maximality considerations speak in favour of large cardinal ax- ioms consistent with ZFC, since it appears to be ‘possible’ (in some sense) to continue the hierarchy far enough to generate the relevant transfinite number. In this paper, we argue against this idea based on a priority of subset formation under the iterative conception. In particular, we argue that there are several con- ceptions of maximality that justify the consistency but falsity of large cardinal axioms. We argue that the arguments we provide are illuminating for the debate concerning the justification of new axioms in iteratively-founded set theory. Introduction Large cardinal axioms (discussed in detail below) are widely viewed as some of the best candidates for new axioms of set theory. They are (apparently) linearly ordered by consistency strength, have substantial mathematical consequences for indepen- dence results (both as a tool for generating new models and for consequences within the models in which they reside), and often appear natural to the working set theo- rist, providing fine-grained information about different properties of transfinite sets. They are considered mathematically interesting and central for the study of set the- ory and its philosophy. In this paper, we do not deny any of the above views. We will, however, argue that the status of large cardinal axioms as maximality principles is questionable.
    [Show full text]