Embodied Decisions and the Predictive Brain

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Embodied Decisions and the Predictive Brain Embodied Decisions and the Predictive Brain Christopher D. Burr A dissertation submitted to the University of Bristol in accordance with the requirements for award of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Faculty of Arts November 2016 Word count: 81766 Abstract Decision-making has traditionally been modelled as a serial process, consisting of a number of distinct stages. The traditional account assumes that an agent first acquires the necessary perceptual evidence, by constructing a detailed inner repre- sentation of the environment, in order to deliberate over a set of possible options. Next, the agent considers her goals and beliefs, and subsequently commits to the best possible course of action. This process then repeats once the agent has learned from the consequences of her actions and subsequently updated her beliefs. Under this interpretation, the agent's body is considered merely as a means to report the decision, or to acquire the relevant goods. However, embodied cognition argues that an agent's body should be understood as a proper part of the decision-making pro- cess. Accepting this principle challenges a number of commonly held beliefs in the cognitive sciences, but may lead to a more unified account of decision-making. This thesis explores an embodied account of decision-making using a recent frame- work known as predictive processing. This framework has been proposed by some as a functional description of neural activity. However, if it is approached from an embodied perspective, it can also offer a novel account of decision-making that ex- tends the scope of our explanatory considerations out beyond the brain and the body. We explore work in the cognitive sciences that supports this view, and argue that decision theory can benefit from adopting an embodied and predictive perspective. Dedication and Acknowledgements It is not uncommon to hear researchers state that their work can be a lonely task. I have not felt this to be the case, and I am confident that this is thanks to the support of my family and close friends. I should start by acknowledging the unending support of my wife, who has been by my side since my first years as an undergraduate. Without your support, encouragement, and love, I do not believe I would have been able to achieve as much as I have done. The same goes for my family, who help ground me and remind me not to take life too seriously! Special thanks go to my parents for all of their many forms of support over the years. I have had the pleasure of conducting my doctoral research at the University of Bristol, and during my time I have met many fantastic people. The Department of Philosophy is a friendly and supporting place, and I will be very sad to leave it behind. My thanks to all of the staff and students that I have interacted with, no matter how brief it may have been, and especially to the following (in no particular order): Finn Spicer, Samir Okasha, Havi Carel, Anya Farrenikova, James Ladyman, Tudor Baetu, Karim Thebault, Bengt Autzen, Alexander Bird, Anthony Everett, Kit Patrick, Vincenzo Politi, Seiriol Morgan and Andrew Pyle. In addition, I have really enjoyed being a part of the postgraduate community, and hope that I have helped make it enjoyable for others. My thanks to the following postgraduates: Niall Paterson, Nick Cosstick, Ben Springett, Richard Bowles, Prakhar Manas, Aaron Guthrie, Bon-Hyuk Koo, Sam Roberts, Alejandra Casas Munoz, Aadil Kurji, Jessica Laimann, Lilit Movsisyan, Alice Monypenny and Mo Abolkheir. I must also single out two postgraduates especially: Oliver Lean and Max Jones. You have both provided an enormous amount of support, and have been kind enough to help me with my research in so many ways. I am deeply indebted to the both of you, and wish you the very best in your own academic careers. You will always remain true rivals, in only the most positive of manners! As a member of the Epistemic Utility Theory: Foundations and Applications project|generously supported by the European Research Council|I have had the fortune of meeting many fantastic researchers who have visited the project over the last three years. In addition to these visits, I have had the pleasure of work- ing alongside Jason Konek, Ben Levinstein, Pavel Janda, Patricia Rich and Greg Gandenberger|my thanks to all of you. I wish you all the best of luck, and I hope that our paths continue to cross in the future. Thank you to the members of the Embodied Cognition and Bayesian Brain read- ing groups. I am very glad that I organised these groups, as it allowed me to meet so many interesting people from outside of the Philosophy department. My thanks to you all for the many stimulating discussions, which helped me produce the thesis that you are currently reading. My thanks to Wanja Wiese and Thomas Metzinger for organising a superb con- ference on the Philosophy of Predictive Processing. Your invitation to participate encouraged me to formulate many of the ideas that are contained within this thesis, and connected me with many superb researchers. A special thanks to Andy Clark for writing the paper that started me on a path that led to the production of this thesis, and for your encouragement along the way. Thank you also for agreeing to be my external examiner, along with Samir Okasha, and for what I imagine will be a challenging but rewarding conversation during my viva. I would also like to thank the following (in no particular order) for a variety of interesting discussions that have helped me with some of the ideas in this thesis: Zoe Drayson, Nathan Lepora, Giovanna Colombetti, Mark Sprevak, Dave Ward, Alistair Isaac, Michael Miller, Jakob Hohwy, Michael Anderson, Regina Fabry, Martin Butz, Lisa Quadt, Joe Dewhurst, Krys Dolega, Jonny Lee, Daniel Burnston, Roberto Fu- magalli, William Ramsey, Kevin O'Regan, William Bechtel, Robert Rupert, David Spurrett, Harry Farmer, Alexandra Georgescu, Anna Ciaunica and Catarina Dutilh- Novaes. Finally, my thanks to Richard Pettigrew. You truly embody the academic prin- ciples and standards that I hope to attain myself someday. You have been a superb supervisor and friend, and I am forever grateful for the opportunity that you have given me. I hope that I am able to offer the same encouragement, support and in- spiration, which you have shown me, to a student of my own in the not too distant future. Author's Declaration I declare that the work in this dissertation was carried out in accordance with the requirements of the University's Regulations and Code of Practice for Research De- gree Programmes and that it has not been submitted for any other academic award. Except where indicated by specific reference in the text, the work is the candidate's own work. Work done in collaboration with, or with the assistance of, others, is indicated as such. Any views expressed in the dissertation are those of the author. SIGNED: ............................................................. DATE:.......................... Publications Some of the material in this thesis is reprinted from the following publications: 1. Burr, Christopher and Max Jones (2016) \The body as laboratory: Prediction- error minimization, embodiment, and representation." In: Philosophical Psy- chology 29.4, pp. 586-600 2. Burr, C (Forthcoming) \Embodied Decisions and the Predictive Brain" In: OpenMIND: The Philosophy of Predictive Processing. Ed. by Thomas Met- zinger and Wanja Wiese. In line with the statement made in the Author's Declaration, where this is repre- sentative of collaborative work references have been provided, and only those sections of this previous research that were written by myself have been replicated in full. Contents Introduction 1 1 Cognitive Systems 9 1.1 The Birth of Cognitive Science . 10 1.2 Cognitivism . 12 1.2.1 The Computational Brain . 14 1.2.2 The Classical Sandwich . 22 1.3 Embodied Cognition . 24 1.3.1 Post-Cognitivism: The Symbol Grounding Problem . 26 1.3.2 Three Themes of Embodiment . 31 1.3.3 Proper Embodiment . 43 1.3.4 Whatever it is, it's not cognitivism! . 47 2 Predictive Processing: An Introduction 51 2.1 Overturning Tradition . 52 2.1.1 Evidence from Visual Cortex . 57 2.2 Predictions and Prediction Error in the Brain . 59 2.2.1 Evidence of Prediction Errors . 63 2.3 Hypothesis Testing . 66 2.3.1 Evidence from Binocular Rivalry . 71 2.4 Precision-Weighting . 74 2.4.1 Evidence from Neuromodulation . 78 2.5 Self-Evidencing . 79 2.6 Adding Action to the Picture . 89 3 Is Decision-Making Embodied? 95 3.1 The Traditional Cognitivist Account of Problem Solving and Decision- Making . 96 3.1.1 Criticisms of the Classical Cognitivist Picture . 103 3.2 Neuroeconomics . 115 3.2.1 Reward Prediction Error Hypothesis . 119 3.2.2 Common Currency and The Futile Search for True Utility . 122 3.3 Embodied Decisions . 129 3.3.1 Decision-Making as a Distributed Consensus . 130 3.3.2 Simultaneous Decisions . 134 3.3.3 Dynamic Choice Behaviour . 137 4 Dissolving Boundaries 145 4.1 Active Inference . 145 4.2 Predicting Choices . 151 4.3 Embodied Emotions . 162 4.3.1 Interoceptive Inference . 170 5 Effective Decisions in the Interactive Brain 179 5.1 Balancing Expectations . 180 5.1.1 Neuromodulation and Effective Connectivity . 183 5.2 The Interactive Brain . 188 5.2.1 Neural Reuse . 189 5.2.2 TALoNS: Some Proposed Mechanisms . 197 5.3 From Regions to Networks: Pluripotency and Degeneracy . 201 5.4 Towards a New Taxonomy . 206 5.4.1 NRP Factors . 208 5.5 Effective Decisions . 215 6 Scaling Up? 219 6.1 Deliberative and Habitual Decision-Making .
Recommended publications
  • Self-Deception Within the Predictive Coding Framework
    Self-deception within the predictive coding framework Iuliia Pliushch Mainz 2016 Table of contents Table of contents __________________________________________________ ii List of figures ____________________________________________________ iv List of tables _____________________________________________________ v Introduction ______________________________________________________ 1 1 Review: Desiderata for the concept of self-deception _________________ 4 1.1 Motivation debate: intentionalists vs. deflationary positions __________ 5 1.1.1 Intentionalist positions ________________________________________________ 5 1.1.2 Deflationary positions _______________________________________________ 24 1.1.3 Constraints on a satisfactory theory of self-deception ______________________ 51 1.2 “Product” or kind of misrepresentation debate ____________________ 62 1.2.1 Belief (Van Leeuwen) vs. avowal (Audi) ________________________________ 66 1.2.2 Belief decomposed: regarding-as-true-stances (Funkhouser) and degrees of belief (Lynch, Porcher) ___________________________________________________________ 69 1.2.3 Dispositionalism (Bach, Schwitzgebel) vs. constructivism (Michel) __________ 73 1.2.4 Pretense (Gendler) __________________________________________________ 76 1.2.5 Emotional micro-takings (Borge) ______________________________________ 78 1.2.6 Self-deceptive process: belief formation or narrative construction? ___________ 82 1.2.7 Non-doxastic conception of self-deception _______________________________ 88 1.3 Classic psychological experiments
    [Show full text]
  • Bootstrap Hell: Perceptual Racial Biases in a Predictive Processing Framework
    Bootstrap Hell: Perceptual Racial Biases in a Predictive Processing Framework Zachariah A. Neemeh ([email protected]) Department of Philosophy, University of Memphis Memphis, TN 38152 USA Abstract This enables us to extract patterns from ambiguous signals Predictive processing is transforming our understanding of the and establish hypotheses about how the world works. brain in the 21st century. Whereas in the 20th century we The training signals that we get from the world are, understood the brain as a passive organ taking in information however, biased in all the same unsightly ways that our from the world, today we are beginning to reconceptualize it societies are biased: by race, gender, socioeconomic status, as an organ that actively creates and tests hypotheses about its nationality, and sexual orientation. The problem is more world. The promised revolution of predictive processing than a mere sampling bias. Our societies are replete with extends beyond cognitive neuroscience, however, and is prejudice biases that shape the ways we think, act, and beginning to make waves in the philosophy of perception. Andy Clark has written that predictive processing creates a perceive. Indeed, a similar problem arises in machine “bootstrap heaven,” enabling the brain to develop complex learning applications when they are inadvertently trained on models of the world from limited data. I argue that the same socially biased data (Avery, 2019; N. T. Lee, 2018). The principles also create a “bootstrap hell,” wherein prejudice basic principle in operation here is “garbage in, garbage biases inherent in our inegalitarian societies result in out”: a predictive system that is trained on socially biased permanent perceptual modifications.
    [Show full text]
  • Predictive Processing As a Systematic Basis for Identifying the Neural Correlates of Consciousness
    Predictive processing as a systematic basis for identifying the neural correlates of consciousness Jakob Hohwya ([email protected]) Anil Sethb ([email protected]) Abstract The search for the neural correlates of consciousness is in need of a systematic, principled foundation that can endow putative neural correlates with greater predictive and explanatory value. Here, we propose the predictive processing framework for brain function as a promis- ing candidate for providing this systematic foundation. The proposal is motivated by that framework’s ability to address three general challenges to identifying the neural correlates of consciousness, and to satisfy two constraints common to many theories of consciousness. Implementing the search for neural correlates of consciousness through the lens of predictive processing delivers strong potential for predictive and explanatory value through detailed, systematic mappings between neural substrates and phenomenological structure. We con- clude that the predictive processing framework, precisely because it at the outset is not itself a theory of consciousness, has significant potential for advancing the neuroscience of consciousness. Keywords Active inference ∙ Consciousness ∙ Neural correlates ∙ Prediction error minimization This article is part of a special issue on “The Neural Correlates of Consciousness”, edited by Sascha Benjamin Fink. 1 Introduction The search for the neural correlates of consciousness (NCCs) has now been under- way for several decades (Crick & Koch, 1990b). Several interesting and suggestive aCognition & Philosophy Lab, Monash University bSackler Center for Consciousness Science and School of Engineering and Informatics, University of Sussex; Azrieli Program in Brain, Mind, and Consciousness Toronto Hohwy, J., & Seth, A. (2020). Predictive processing as a systematic basis for identifying the neural correlates of consciousness.
    [Show full text]
  • To Err and Err, but Less and Less
    TOERRANDERR,BUTLESSANDLESS Predictive coding and affective value in perception, art, and autism sander van de cruys Dissertation offered to obtain the degree of Doctor of Psychology (PhD) supervisor: Prof. Dr. Johan Wagemans Laboratory of Experimental Psychology Faculty of Psychology and Pedagogical Sciences KU Leuven 2014 © 2014, Sander Van de Cruys Cover image created by randall casaer. Title adapted from the poem The road to wisdom by the Danish scientist piet hein. Back cover image from Les Songes Drolatiques de Pantagruel (1565) attributed to françois desprez, but based on the fabulous, chimerical characters invented by françois ra- belais. Typographical style based on classicthesis developed by andré miede (GNU General Public Licence). Typeset in LATEX. abstract The importance of prediction or expectation in the functioning of the mind is appreciated at least since the birth of psychology as a separate discipline. From minute moment-to-moment predictions of the movements of a melody or a ball, to the long-term plans of our friends and foes, we continuously predict the world around us, because we learned the statistical regularities that govern it. It is often only when predictions go awry —when the sensory input does not match with the predictions we implicitly formed— that we become conscious of this incessant predictive activity of our brains. In the last decennia, a computational model called predictive coding emerged that attempts to formalize this matching pro- cess, hence explaining perceptual inference and learning. The predictive coding scheme describes how each level in the cortical processing hierarchy predicts inputs from levels below. In this way resources can be focused on that part of the input that was unpredicted, and therefore signals important changes in the environment that are still to be explained.
    [Show full text]
  • What Do Predictive Coders Want?
    Synthese manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) What do Predictive Coders Want? Colin Klein Macquarie University Sydney NSW, 2109 Australia Tel: +61 02 9850 8876 Fax: +61 02 9850 8892 [email protected] Abstract The so-called “dark room problem” makes vivd the challenges that purely predictive models face in accounting for motivation. I argue that the problem is a serious one. Proposals for solving the dark room problem via predictive coding architectures are either empirically inadequate or computa- tionally intractable. The Free Energy principle might avoid the problem, but only at the cost of setting itself up as a highly idealized model, which is then literally false to the world. I draw at least one optimistic conclusion, however. Real-world, real-time systems may embody motivational states in a variety of ways consistent with idealized principles like FEP, including ways that are intuitively embodied and extended. This may allow predictive coding theo- rists to reconcile their account with embodied principles, even if it ultimately undermines loftier ambitions. Keywords Predictive Coding, Free Energy Principle, Homeostasis, Good Regulator The- orem, Extended Mind, Explanation Acknowledgements Research on this work was funded by Australian Research Council Grant FT140100422. For helpful discussions, thanks to Esther Klein, Julia Sta↵el, Wolfgang Schwartz, the ANU 2013 reading group on predictive coding, and participants at the 2015 CAVE “”Predictive Coding, Delusions, and Agency” workshop at Macquarie University. For feedback on earlier drafts of this work, additional thanks to Pe- ter Clutton, Jakob Hohwy, Max Coltheart, Michael Kirchho↵, Bryce Huebner, 2 Luke Roelofs, Daniel Stoljar, two anonymous referees, the ANU Philosophy of Mind work in progress group, and an audience at the “Predictive Brains and Embodied, Enactive Cognition” workshop at the University of Wollongong.
    [Show full text]
  • Behavioral and Brain Sciences | Cambridge Core
    2/14/2020 Prediction, embodiment, and representation | Behavioral and Brain Sciences | Cambridge Core Home> Journals> Behavioral and Brain Sciences> Volume 42 > Prediction, embodiment, and rep... English | Français Behavioral and Brain Sciences Volume 42 2019 , e216 Prediction, embodiment, and representation István Aranyosi (a1) DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X19001274 Published online by Cambridge University Press: 28 November 2019 In response to: Is coding a relevant metaphor for the brain? Related commentaries (27) Author response Abstract First, I argue that there is no agreement within non-classical cognitive science as to whether one should eliminate representations, hence, it is not clear that Brette's appeal to it is going to solve the problems with coding. Second, I argue that Brette's criticism of predictive coding as being intellectualistic is not justified, as predictive coding is compatible with embodied cognition. Copyright COPYRIGHT: © Cambridge University Press 2019 Hide All https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/behavioral-and-brain-sciences/article/prediction-embodiment-and-representation/D38B6A8329371101F9… 1/2 Among the shortcomings that the metaphor of coding involves, Brette mentions its inability to truly function as a representation. At the same time, he seeks an alternative to coding in non-classical cognitive science, such as dynamic systems, ecological psychology, and embodied cognition, which, in their most radical and most interesting versions are precisely anti-representationalist approaches. How is the former complaint to be squared with the latter alleged solution? Brette does not tell us, but his critical discussion of predictive coding indicates that, ultimately, his problem with coding is the alleged intellectualism involved in it, hence, it is the alternative, embodied and embedded cognition theory that he thinks should be understood as currently the best remedy.
    [Show full text]
  • Vanilla PP for Philosophers: a Primer on Predictive Processing
    Vanilla PP for Philosophers: A Primer on Predictive Processing Wanja Wiese & Thomas Metzinger The goal of this short chapter, aimed at philosophers, is to provide an overview and brief Keywords explanation of some central concepts involved in predictive processing (PP). Even those who consider themselves experts on the topic may find it helpful to see how the central Active inference | Attention | Bayesian terms are used in this collection. To keep things simple, we will first informally define a set Inference | Environmental seclusion of features important to predictive processing, supplemented by some short explanations | Free energy principle | Hierarchi- and an alphabetic glossary. cal processing | Ideomotor principle The features described here are not shared in all PP accounts. Some may not be nec- | Perception | Perceptual inference | essary for an individual model; others may be contested. Indeed, not even all authors of Precision | Prediction | Prediction error this collection will accept all of them. To make this transparent, we have encouraged con- minimization | Predictive processing | tributors to indicate briefly which of the features arenecessary to support the arguments Predictive control | Statistical estima- they provide, and which (if any) are incompatible with their account. For the sake of clar- tion | Top-down processing ity, we provide the complete list here, very roughly ordered by how central we take them to be for “Vanilla PP” (i.e., a formulation of predictive processing that will probably be Acknowledgments accepted by most researchers working on this topic). More detailed explanations will be We are extremely grateful to Regina given below. Note that these features do not specify individually necessary and jointly suf- Fabry and Jakob Hohwy for providing ficient conditions for the application of the concept of “predictive processing”.
    [Show full text]
  • Psychology 3131 Professor June Gruber Human Emotion
    Human Emotion Psychology 3131 Professor June Gruber Human Emotion What is an Emotion? QUESTIONS? William James “To the psychologist alone can such questions occur as: Why do we smile, when pleased, and not scowl? Why are we unable to talk to a crowd as we talk to a single friend? Why does a particular maiden turn our wits upside-down?” James, W. (1982). Psychology - Briefer course. New York: Henry Holt. New edition, New York: Harper & Row, 1961. William James “The common man can only say: "Of course we smile, of course our heart palpitates at the sight of the crowd, of course we love the maiden. And so, probably, does each animal feel about the particular things it tends to do in the presence of certain objects...” James, W. (1982). Psychology - Briefer course. New York: Henry Holt. New edition, New York: Harper & Row, 1961. Roadmap Theories of emotion Components Classification Expert Interview Roadmap TheoriesTheories ofof emotionemotion Components Classification Expert Interview Theories of Emotion Timeline Theories ofEmotion Ancient Greek Enlightenment Darwin William James James-Lange Cannon-Bard Schachter-Singer Lazarus Theories of Emotion Timeline Hippocrates: 4 Humors Aristotle: Moderation principle Ancient Greek “Getting angry or sad is easy and anyone can do it; but doing it... in the right amount, at the right time, and in the right way is not easy, nor can everyone do it.” - ARISTOTLE, Nicomachean Ethics, 11.9, 1109a27 Theories of Emotion Timeline Descartes Spinoza Hume Enlightenment Theories of Emotion Timeline Evolutionary Approach Expression of Emotions in Man & Animals Emotions evolutionarily evolved, serve survival purpose Darwin Immediately a bestseller of it’s time (over 5,000 copies) 1st Scientific Treatment of Emotion Includes survey data Observations of healthy and mentally ill individuals Personal anecdotes (e.g., grief expressions in Darwin’s own family after death) Darwin’s Three Principles Darwin’s Three Principles I.
    [Show full text]
  • Solving the Emotion Paradox: Categorization and the Experience of Emotion
    Personality and Social Psychology Review Copyright © 2006 by 2006, Vol. 10, No. 1, 20–46 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc. Solving the Emotion Paradox: Categorization and the Experience of Emotion Lisa Feldman Barrett Department of Psychology Boston College In this article, I introduce an emotion paradox: People believe that they know an emo- tion when they see it, and as a consequence assume that emotions are discrete events that can be recognized with some degree of accuracy, but scientists have yet to pro- duce a set of clear and consistent criteria for indicating when an emotion is present and when it is not. I propose one solution to this paradox: People experience an emo- tion when they conceptualize an instance of affective feeling. In this view, the experi- ence of emotion is an act of categorization, guided by embodied knowledge about emotion. The result is a model of emotion experience that has much in common with the social psychological literature on person perception and with literature on em- bodied conceptual knowledge as it has recently been applied to social psychology. Humans experience emotion. For many, experience people feel fear when their fear mechanism has trig- serves as an emotion’s central and defining aspect. We gered, such that this feeling shapes perception and feel the heat of anger, the despair of sadness, the dread decision making and can have important conse- of fear. Most days, at least in North America, each of us quences for social relationships. asks and answers about our emotional state. We talk Although there is accumulating evidence that the about our experiences of emotion over coffee, or dur- experience of emotion can have great consequence for ing a telephone conversation, or in a therapist’s office.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Bayes and Bullets: an Embodied, Situated, Targeting-Based Account of Predictive Processing
    Western University Scholarship@Western Brain and Mind Institute Researchers' Publications Brain and Mind Institute 2017 Of Bayes and bullets: An embodied, situated, targeting-based account of predictive processing M.L. Anderson Philosophy, Rotman Institute Western University Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/brainpub Part of the Neurosciences Commons, and the Psychology Commons Citation of this paper: Anderson, M.L., "Of Bayes and bullets: An embodied, situated, targeting-based account of predictive processing" (2017). Brain and Mind Institute Researchers' Publications. 53. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/brainpub/53 Of Bayes and Bullets: An Embodied, Situated, Targeting-Based Account of Predictive Processing Michael L. Anderson Here I argue that Jakob Hohwy’s (Hohwy 2013) cognitivist interpretation of pre- Keywords dictive processing (a) does not necessarily follow from the evidence for the im- portance of Bayesian processing in the brain; (b) is rooted in a misunderstanding Bayesian brain | Ecological psychol- of our epistemic position in the world; and (c) is undesirable in that it leads to ogy | Embodied cognition epistemic internalism or idealism. My claim is that the internalist/idealist conclu- sions do not follow from predictive processing itself, but instead from the model of perceptionHohwy ’s adopts, and that there are alternate models of perception that do not lend themselves to idealist conclusions. The position I advocate is similar to Andy Clark’s embodied/embedded interpretation of Bayesian process- ing (Clark 2015); however, I argue that Clark’s position, as currently stated, also potentially leads to idealist conclusions. I offer a specific emendation toClark’s view that I believe avoids this pitfall.
    [Show full text]
  • What Might Interoceptive Inference Reveal About Consciousness?
    Preprint Embodied Computation Group 1 What might interoceptive inference reveal about consciousness? NIIA NIKOLOVAa,1,*,P ETER THESTRUP WAADEa,1,2,K ARL J. FRISTON3, AND MICAH ALLEN1,4,5 aEqual contribution *Corresponding author: niia@cfin.au.dk 1Center for Functionally Integrative Neuroscience, Aarhus University, Denmark 2Interacting Minds Center, Aarhus University, Denmark 3Wellcome Centre for Human Neuroimaging, UCL, United Kingdom 4Aarhus Institute of Advanced Studies, Denmark 5Cambridge Psychiatry, University of Cambridge, United Kingdom The mainstream science of consciousness offers a few predominate views of how the brain gives rise to awareness. Chief among these are the Higher Order Thought Theory, Global Neuronal Workspace The- ory, Integrated Information Theory, and hybrids thereof. In parallel, rapid development in predictive pro- cessing approaches have begun to outline concrete mechanisms by which interoceptive inference shapes selfhood, affect, and exteroceptive perception. Here, we consider these new approaches in terms of what they might offer our empirical, phenomenological, and philosophical understanding of consciousness and its neurobiological roots. INTRODUCTION thought? How might the body, or emotion, interact with these properties of consciousness? What is Consciousness? Answering these questions is no easy task. Certainly, most If you have ever been under general anaesthesia, you surely who study consciousness have heard the joke that there are as remember the experience of waking up. However, this awak- many theories of consciousness as there are consciousness theo- ening is different from the kind we do every morning, in that rists. Our goal here is not to provide a comprehensive predictive it is preceded by a complete lack of subjective experience, a processing or active inference theory of consciousness, of which dark nothingness, without even the awareness of time passing.
    [Show full text]
  • Predictive Brains, Embodied Minds, and the Puzzle of the Evidentiary Veil
    Busting out: predictive brains, embodied minds, and the puzzle of the evidentiary veil Article (Accepted Version) Clark, Andy (2017) Busting out: predictive brains, embodied minds, and the puzzle of the evidentiary veil. Nous, 51 (4). pp. 727-753. ISSN 0029-4624, This version is available from Sussex Research Online: http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/id/eprint/82328/ This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies and may differ from the published version or from the version of record. If you wish to cite this item you are advised to consult the publisher’s version. Please see the URL above for details on accessing the published version. Copyright and reuse: Sussex Research Online is a digital repository of the research output of the University. Copyright and all moral rights to the version of the paper presented here belong to the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. To the extent reasonable and practicable, the material made available in SRO has been checked for eligibility before being made available. Copies of full text items generally can be reproduced, displayed or performed and given to third parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes without prior permission or charge, provided that the authors, title and full bibliographic details are credited, a hyperlink and/or URL is given for the original metadata page and the content is not changed in any way. http://sro.sussex.ac.uk Busting Out: Predictive Brains, Embodied Minds, and the Puzzle of the Evidentiary Veil Andy Clark School of Philosophy, Psychology, and Language Sciences University of Edinburgh, UK Abstract Biological brains are increasingly cast as ‘prediction machines’: evolved organs whose core operating principle is to learn about the world by trying to predict their own patterns of sensory stimulation.
    [Show full text]