Two Problems That Shaped a Century of Theory George Grätzer

century of lattice theory was shaped Acknowledgements to a large extent by two problems. I received manuscripts, lecture notes, and cor- This introductory article defines the rections from a number of individuals, including basic concepts, introduces these two H. Lakser, W. A. Lampe, R. Padmanabhan, V. Pratt, problems, and describes their effect R. W. Quackenbush, and F. Wehrung. On matters Aon lattice theory. historical, I was advised by J. B. Nation. In Parts 1 and 3 there is a very brief introduc- tion of the basic concepts. The reader may find a more detailed introduction in Part 1 of my 2006 Part 1—Lattice Theory 101 book, The Congruences of a Finite Lattice [8], and complete coverage of the topic in my 1998 book, Basic Concepts General Lattice Theory, second edition [7]. Orders. An order A = hA, ≤i (or A if ≤ is under- The two areas we discuss are stood) consists of a nonempty set A and a binary relation ≤ on A (that is, a subset of A2)—called Uniquely complemented lattices: discussed in an ordering—such that the relation ≤ is reflexive Part 2. (a ≤ a, for all a ∈ L), antisymmetric (a ≤ b and Congruence lattices of lattices: discussed in b ≤ a imply that a = b, for all a, b ∈ L), and Part 4. transitive (a ≤ b and b ≤ c imply that a ≤ c, for The two problems, the personalities, and the all a, b, c ∈ L). An order that is linear (a ≤ b or times are completely different for the solution of b ≤ a, for all a, b ∈ L) is called a chain. these two problems. But they also share a lot. Each In an order P, the element u is an upper bound problem has been around for half a century. It of H ⊆ P iff h ≤ u, for all h ∈ H. An upper bound is not clear—or known—who first proposed the u of H is the least upper bound of H iff, for any problem. Nevertheless, everybody knows about it. upper bound v of H, we have u ≤ v. We shall Everybody expects a positive solution. And then write u = H. The concepts of lower bound and somebody overcomes the psychology of the prob- greatest lowerW bound (denoted by H) are simi- lem and pushes really hard for a negative solution. larly defined. We use the notation aV∧ b = {a,b} However, the negative solution turns out to require and a ∨ b = {a,b} and call ∧ the meet andV ∨ the groundbreaking new ideas and is technically very join of the elementsW a and b. complicated. Lattices. An order L (or L if the ∧ and ∨ are understood) is a lattice iff a ∧ b and a ∨ b always exist. In lattices, the join and meet are both binary operations, which means that they George Grätzer is Distinguished Professor of Mathemat- ics at the University of Manitoba. His email address is can be applied to a pair of elements a, b of L to [email protected]. The research of the author yield again an element of L. They are idempotent was supported by the NSERC of Canada. (a ∧ a = a, a ∨ a = a, for all a ∈ L), commutative

696 Notices of the AMS Volume 54, Number 6 (a∧b = b∧a, a∨b = b∨a, for all a, b ∈ L), associa- Let me give one more example. An equivalence tive ((a∧b)∧c = a∧(b∧c), (a∨b)∨c = a∨(b∨c), relation ε on a set X is a reflexive, symmetric for all a, b, c ∈ L), and together satisfy the absorp- (a ≤ b iff b ≤ a, for all a, b ∈ L), and transitive tion identities (a ∧ (a ∨ b) = a, a ∨ (a ∧ b) = a, for binary relation. If x and y are in relation ε, that is, all a, b ∈ L). hx, yi ∈ ε, we write x ε y or x ≡ y (ε). On the set An L = hL, ∧, ∨i is a lattice iff L is a Part X of all equivalence relations on X, we can nonempty set; ∧ and ∨ are binary operations on introduce an ordering: ε1 ≤ ε2 if ε1 is a refinement L; both ∧ and ∨ are idempotent, commutative, of ε2; that is, xε1 y implies that xε2 y. Then Part X and associative; and they jointly satisfy the two is a lattice, called the partition lattice of X. Clearly, absorption identities. hx, yi ∈ ε1 ∧ ε2 iff hx, yi ∈ ε1 and hx, yi ∈ ε2. The It is the most intriguing aspect of lattice theory join, however, is more complicated to describe. that lattices can be viewed as orders, so we can use Diagrams. In the order P, a is covered by b (in order-theoretic concepts (such as completeness; notation, a ≺ b) iff a