Moore's Dilemma
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Load more
Recommended publications
-
Substance and the Concept of Personal Identity
AN OPEN ACCESS Ergo JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Substance and the Concept of Personal Identity JenS KIPPer University of Cologne In this paper, I identify and discuss the following feature of our judgments about hypothetical scenarios concerning the identity of persons: with respect to the vast majority of scenarios, both members of a pair of logically complementary proposi- tions about personal identity are conceivable. I consider a number of explanations of this feature that draw on the metaphysics and the epistemology of personal identity, none of which prove to be satisfactory. I then argue that in order to give an adequate explanation, one needs to recognize an important characteristic of our concept of personal identity: it is such that if there are mental substances (or the like), they constitute personal identity. At the same time, there can still be persons if there are no such substances. Since this finding casts doubts on the way that thought experi- ments about personal identity are usually set up, I end by outlining its potential consequences for the debate over the identity of persons. 1. Introduction The debate over the nature of personal identity is as replete with thought experi- ments as many other philosophical debates. But there is a nagging suspicion that thought experiments work differently when the identity of persons is concerned. For example, it is natural to think that our judgment that the person in Harry Frankfurt’s (1969) famous case is responsible for what he did is based on our conceptual competence. When John Locke argues, however, that the person in the body of a cobbler who has the memories of a prince is that prince (1694/1975: 340), he does not seem to be stating a conceptual truth. -
A Critique of Roderick Chisholm
DOI: https://doi.org/10.26512/rfmc.v8i2.35865 Intentionality and the Logico-Linguistic Commitment: A Critique of Roderick Chisholm [Intencionalidade e Compromisso Lógico-Linguístico: Uma crítica a Roderick Chisholm] Luis Niel* Abstract: The aim of this article is to analyze and criticize Roderick Chisholm’s con- ception of intentionality, which has, historically, served as the point of departure for most accounts of intentionality in analytic philosophy. My goal is to highlight the problematic ’logico-linguistic commitment’ presupposed by Chisholm, according to which mental concepts should be interpreted by means of semantic concepts. After addressing Chisholm’s differentiation between the ontological thesis (the idea that the intentional object might not exist) and the psychological thesis (the conception that only mental phenomena are intentional), as well as his defining criteria for intentionality (non-existential implication, independency of truth-value, and indirect reference), I fo- cus on the manifold problems presented by his theory. First, the two initial criteria entail a conceptual confusion between the semantic concept of ’intensionality’ and the mental concept of ’intentionality’. Second, according to these criteria-and against Chisholm’s explicit intention-perception and other cognitive activities should not be considered intentional. Third, there are no grounds for the artificial conflation of intentionality and the concept of ’propositional attitudes’-an equation which is an explicit tenet of the logico-linguistic commitment. In general, I argue that an interpretation of intentionality based on this commitment obscures the true meaning of the concept of intentionality, as it is presented, for instance, by phenomenology. Keywords: Chisholm. Intentionality. Intensionality. Propositional Attitudes. Logico- linguistic Commitment. -
Writings of Charles De Koninck, Volume
D E K O N I N The Writings C K of ልሎ CHARLES C H DE KONINCK A R T L h E e S W D r i E t i n K g O s o N f I N C K ልሎ Edited and Translated by Ralph McInerny The Writings of CHARLES DE KONINCK Charles De Koninck, University of Laval, Quebec. The Writings of CHARLES DE KONINCK volume one Edited and Translated by Ralph McInerny with a biography by Thomas De Koninck andልሎ an introduction by Leslie Armour University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, Indiana DeKoninck-000.FM 4/15/08 1:17 PM Page iv Copyright © by University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana www.undpress.nd.edu All Rights Reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Designed by Wendy McMillen Set in ./. Minion by Four Star Books Printed on # Nature’s Recycle paper by Sheridan Books, Inc. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Koninck, Charles de, d. [Works. English. ] The writings of Charles De Koninck / edited and translated by Ralph McInerny ; with a biography by Thomas De Koninck ; and an introduction by Leslie Armour. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. -: ---- (cloth : alk. paper) -: --- (cloth : alk. paper) . Koninck, Charles de, d. Science—Philosophy. I. McInerny, Ralph M. II. Title. '.—dc This book is printed on recycled paper. Contents Preface vii The Philosophy of Charles De Koninck 1 Leslie Armour Charles De Koninck: A Biographical Sketch 69 Thomas De Koninck ልሎ Works by Charles De Koninck The Philosophy of Sir Arthur Eddington (1934) 99 The Cosmos (1936) 235 The Problem of Indeterminism (1935) 355 Reflections on the Problem of Indeterminism (1937) 401 Are the Experimental Sciences Distinct from the Philosophy of Nature? (1941) 443 Index 457 Preface A few years ago, David Quackenbush, a tutor at Thomas Aquinas College in California, conceived the idea of photocopying the Charles De Koninck ar- chives at the University of Laval. -
JAMES TARTAGLIA CV, COMPLETE Revap
JAMES TARTAGLIA Areas of Specialisation PHILOSOPHY: Philosophy of Mind, Rorty, Metaphysics, Metaphilosophy, Meaning of Life JAZZ: Tenor Saxophone, Composition Areas of Competence PHILOSOPHY: History of Philosophy, Continental and Chinese Philosophy JAZZ: Alto Saxophone, Piano / Keyboards / Organ 1. PERSONAL DETAILS Born: 1973 Nationality: British Business Address: School of Politics, International Relations and Philosophy, Keele University, Staffordshire, ST5 5BG, United Kingdom Email: [email protected] Staff Webpage: http://www.keele.ac.uk/spire/staff/tartaglia/ Personal Website: http://www.jamestartaglia.com/ Tel: +44 (0) 1782-734-315 Fax: +44 (0) 1782-733-592 2. QUALIFICATIONS AND AWARDS 1989 Second place in Daily Telegraph Young Jazz Musician of the Year (GCSE category) 1991 Winner of Daily Telegraph Young Jazz Musician of the Year (Soloist category) 1992 Awarded major scholarship to study at Berklee College of Music, USA (from competitive auditions in Frankfurt, which I was invited to after sending a demo tape) 1992-3 Diploma in Performance Studies, Berklee College of Music, USA (saxophone teacher: George Garzone) 1993-6 BA (Hons) in Philosophy - First Class University College London 1996-8 M.Phil. in Philosophy – Passed, no amendments University College London Thesis Title: ‘Understanding intentionality in terms of natural selection’ 1998-2002 Ph.D. in Philosophy – Passed, no amendments (viva in 2001) 1 University College London Thesis Title: ‘The Obstinacy of Appearance: An analysis and attempted resolution of the explanatory gap debate about consciousness’. (Examiners: Galen Strawson and Scott Sturgeon) 2009 Teaching and Learning in Higher Education Postgraduate Certificate, Keele University 2011 Keele Award for Excellence in Teaching and Learning 3. RESEARCH FUNDING 1996-1998 British Academy Studentship, competition A 1998-2000 British Academy Studentship, competition B 2000-1 A.J. -
Prof. G. Dawes Hicks, F.B.A
No 3726, MARCH 29, 1941 NATURE 381 adequate explanation has so far been forthcoming. sections, each to be kept submerged for a different Other areas are also known which, after many period of time. The maximum period of inundation years in an almost disease-free state, are now will be eighteen months. This experiment is based becoming rapidly affected. The collective ex on the facts that soil fungi such as Fusarium perience, practical and scientific, in Central cubense require oxygen to live, and that, when America is that hydrogen ion concentration is the highly infected soil was submerged for one month master factor determining the severity of Panama under two feet of water, no F. cubense could be disease, followed by texture ; but, as Reinking'!! found in it. The outcome of this experiment will work shows, distribution of the pathogen and be awaited with the greatest interest by all assoc density of its population in the soil obviously iated with the extensive alluvial banana lands of require careful consideration •. Central America. Already it has been found that The Panama disease situation in Central in new land, built up by the sedimentation of America is being closely watched, and on the controlled flood water, and therefore subjected to properties of the larger companies every effort is several inundations, the incidence of Panama being made to check its spread and to test out disease has been negligible. This may be con any new idea which might eventually have some sidered as an indication of the probable success of economic value. An unusually interesting and flood-fallowing, but time alone will tell. -
Essence, Plenitude, and Paradox
PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES Philosophical Perspectives, 25, Metaphysics, 2011 ESSENCE, PLENITUDE, AND PARADOX Sarah-Jane Leslie Princeton University Essentialism in philosophy is the view that there are in principle two ways of having properties and including parts: the essential way and the accidental way (e.g, Fine, 1994, 1995; Johnston 1984, 2006; Kripke, 1980; Salmon 1986, 2005; Yablo 1987). As I understand the view, even an extreme essentialist — who takes every property and every part to be had essentially — should agree with the in-principle distinction while arguing that certain metaphysical considerations mean that the second way of having properties is not, and cannot be, exemplified. Such a view would contrast with the view of an anti-essentialist like Willard van Orman Quine who repudiates the very distinction between the two ways of having properties. Quine’s view is not that all properties are accidental, for that would be to use what he calls the “invidious distinction” (1953), rather than repudiate it. His view is that there is not even in principle these two ways of having properties (or satisfying predicates, as he would put it), about which we can ask “Which of these two ways do things have properties?” What then ostensibly distinguishes the essential way of having properties from the accidental way? An object’s essential properties are conditions on what it is to be that object, and this set of conditions fixes just which possibilities or possible worlds the object exists in, namely just those in which it satisfies those conditions. An object’s essential properties also fix how long it exists, namely only at those times at which it satisfies those conditions. -
INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS
INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS Volume 173 Robert Ginsberg Founding Editor Peter A. Redpath Executive Editor Associate Editors G. John M. Abbarno Matti Häyry Mary-Rose Barral Steven V. Hicks Gerhold K. Becker Richard T. Hull Raymond Angelo Belliotti Mark Letteri Kenneth A. Bryson Vincent L. Luizzi C. Stephen Byrum Alan Milchman H. G. Callaway George David Miller Robert A. Delfino Alan Rosenberg Rem B. Edwards Arleen L. F. Salles Andrew Fitz-Gibbon John R. Shook Francesc Forn i Argimon Eddy Souffrant William Gay Tuija Takala Dane R. Gordon Anne Waters J. Everet Green John R. Welch Heta Aleksandra Gylling Thomas F. Woods a volume in Cognitive Science CS Francesc Forn i Argimon, Editor INTENTIONALITY Past and Future Edited by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Cover Design: Studio Pollmann The paper on which this book is printed meets the requirements of “ISO 9706:1994, Information and documentation - Paper for documents - Requirements for permanence”. ISBN: 90-420-1817-8 ©Editions Rodopi B.V., Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Printed in the Netherlands CONTENTS Preface vii List of Abbreviations ix ONE The Necessity and Nature of Mental Content 1 LAIRD ADDIS TWO Reading Brentano on the Intentionality of the Mental 15 PHILIP J. BARTOK THREE Emotions, Moods, and Intentionality 25 WILLIAM FISH FOUR Lockean Ideas as Intentional Contents 37 GÁBOR FORRAI FIVE Normativity and Mental Content 51 JUSSI HAUKIOJA SIX The Ontological and Intentional Status of Fregean Senses: An Early Account of External Content 63 GREG JESSON -
Reflexive Monism
Reflexive Monism Max Velmans, Goldsmiths, University of London; email [email protected]; http://www.goldsmiths.ac.uk/psychology/staff/velmans.php Journal of Consciousness Studies (2008), 15(2), 5-50. Abstract. Reflexive monism is, in essence, an ancient view of how consciousness relates to the material world that has, in recent decades, been resurrected in modern form. In this paper I discuss how some of its basic features differ from both dualism and variants of physicalist and functionalist reductionism, focusing on those aspects of the theory that challenge deeply rooted presuppositions in current Western thought. I pay particular attention to the ontological status and seeming “out- thereness” of the phenomenal world and to how the “phenomenal world” relates to the “physical world”, the “world itself”, and processing in the brain. In order to place the theory within the context of current thought and debate, I address questions that have been raised about reflexive monism in recent commentaries and also evaluate competing accounts of the same issues offered by “transparency theory” and by “biological naturalism”. I argue that, of the competing views on offer, reflexive monism most closely follows the contours of ordinary experience, the findings of science, and common sense. Key words: Consciousness, reflexive, monism, dualism, reductionism, physicalism, functionalism, transparency, biological naturalism, phenomenal world, physical world, world itself, universe itself, brain, perceptual projection, phenomenal space, measured space, physical space, space perception, information, virtual reality, hologram, phenomenological internalism, phenomenological externalism, first person, third person, complementary What is Reflexive Monism? Monism is the view that the universe, at the deepest level of analysis, is one thing, or composed of one fundamental kind of stuff. -
Is the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature False?
Portland State University PDXScholar Systems Science Faculty Publications and Presentations Systems Science 10-2013 Is the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature False? Martin Zwick Portland State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/sysc_fac Part of the Philosophy Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Citation Details Zwick, M. (2013). "Is the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature False?" Presented at the 65th Annual Northwest Philosophy Conference, Pacific University, Oct. 4-5, 2013. This Conference Proceeding is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Systems Science Faculty Publications and Presentations by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. NORTHWEST PHILOSOPHY CONFERENCE Pacific University, Forest Grove, Oregon, Oct 4-5, 2013 Is the Materialist Nao-Darwinian Conception of Nature False? Professor Martin Zwick Systems Science Graduate Program Portland State University P.O. Box 751 Portland OR 97207-0751 July 19, 2013 [email protected] 503-725-4987 Abstract: This paper assesses the main argument of Thomas Nagel's recent book, Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception ofNature Is Almost Certainly False. The paper agrees with Nagel that, as an approach to the relation between mind and matter and the mystery of subjective experience, neutral monism is more likely to be true than either materialism or idealism. It disagrees with Nagel by favoring a version of neutral monism based on emergence rather than on a reductive pan-psychism. -
Jeff Buechner.POMSIGMAA 2017 Invited Address
Computers, mathematical proof, and the nature of the human mind POMSIGMAA Keynote Address Philosophy of Mathematics American Mathematical Society and Mathematical Association of America Joint Meetings Jeff Buechner Rutgers University-Newark and The Saul Kripke Center, CUNY, The Graduate Center January 6th, 2017 1 1976 Appel and Haken prove the four- color theorem • June 21, 1976 Wolfgang Haken and Kenneth Appel, with the aid of John Koch, completed their proof of the Four-Color Theorem (4CT). (Haken turned 48 years old on that day.) • Their proof was published in 1977: “Every planar map is four colorable,” Parts 1 and II, and Supplements I and II, Illinois Journal of Mathematics, XXI, 84, September 1977 2 1976 Appel and Haken prove the four- color theorem • At one place in the proof of the 4CT, Appel and Haken need to find a finite list of reducible configurations with the property that every graph contains at least one configuration in the list. To do this, a lemma must be proved: that every configuration in an unavoidable set is reducible. A computer is needed to prove that all of the configurations are reducible. For instance, to show that one kind of configuration in the set is reducible requires 1,000,000 steps. 3 1976 Appel and Haken prove the four- color theorem • Although computers had already been used to prove theorems in mathematics before the Appel-Haken proof, the importance of the 4CT brought the use of a computer in proving it to the forefront of attention of mathematicians, as well as a lay public. -
Neurath's Boat, Theseus' Ship and Chisholm's Nonintactly Persisting Universe ABSTRACT
1 Neurath’s Boat, Theseus’ Ship and Chisholm’s Nonintactly Persisting Universe ABSTRACT: Neurath’s famous boat metaphor paints a picture of a coherentist system of knowledge where every statement (protocol or otherwise) is always open to revision. However, his total rejection of correspondence theory, I argue, raises questions about what “statements” actually are, since they can no longer be defined with reference to an external world. I believe that, if Neurath’s coherentism is taken seriously, statements must be ontological entities that make up a universe that is a nonintactly persisting object, in Roderick Chisolm’s sense. I explain this concept with recourse to the classic metaphysical riddle of the ship of Theseus. Otto Neurath famously compared our experience of the world to our being on a ship at sea that never reaches land. Instead, we have to constantly make repairs on the open water. His point was that we don’t have the benefit of being able to stop and check our theories of the world from a detached perspective. There are no absolute, indubitable certainties to which our theories must conform. We must be prepared to revise anything and everything as necessary, in order to maintain the coherence of our world system—to stay afloat: “We are like sailors who must rebuild their ship on the open sea, never able to dismantle it in dry-dock and to reconstruct it there out of the best materials” (Neurath 1932/33, 201). Neurath’s metaphor is reminiscent of the ancient metaphysical riddle of Theseus’ ship: if the parts of a ship are slowly replaced over time, until the ship has none of its original parts, would it still be the same ship? In what follows, I use Roderick Chisholm’s language to suggest that, if Neurath’s metaphor is accurate, our world is a nonintactly persisting object, dropping and gaining parts over time according to the pragmatic needs of coherence. -
The Mind–Body Problem: an Overview
The Mind–Body Problem: An Overview Chapter 1 The Mind–Body Problem: An Overview Kirk Ludwig I have said that the soul is not more than the body, And I have said that the body is not more than the soul, And nothing, not God, is greater to one than one’s self is. Walt Whitman 1.1 Introduction Understanding the place of thought and feeling in the natural world is central to that general comprehension of nature, as well as that special self-understanding, which are the primary goals of science and philosophy. The general form of the project, which has exercised scientists and philosophers since the ancient world, is given by the question, ‘What is the relation, in general, between mental and physical phenomena?’ There is no settled agreement on the correct answer. This is the single most important gap in our understanding of the natural world. The trouble is that the question presents us with a problem: each possible answer to it has consequences that appear unacceptable. This problem has traditionally gone under the heading ‘The Mind–Body Problem.’1 My primary aim in this chapter is to explain in what this traditional mind–body problem consists, what its possible solutions are, and what obstacles lie in the way of a resolution. The discussion will develop in two phases. The first phase, sections 1.2–1.4, will be concerned to get clearer about the import of our initial question as a precondition of developing an account of possible responses to it. The second phase, sections 1.5–1.6, explains how a problem arises in our attempts to answer the question we have characterized, and surveys the various solutions that can be and have been offered.