Abolishing the Concept of Mental Illness

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Abolishing the Concept of Mental Illness ABOLISHING THE CONCEPT OF MENTAL ILLNESS In Abolishing the Concept of Mental Illness: Rethinking the Nature of Our Woes, Richard Hallam takes aim at the very concept of mental illness, and explores new ways of thinking about and responding to psychological distress. Though the concept of mental illness has infiltrated everyday language, academic research, and public policy-making, there is very little evidence that woes are caused by somatic dysfunction. This timely book rebuts arguments put forward to defend the illness myth and traces historical sources of the mind/body debate. The author presents a balanced overview of the past utility and current disadvantages of employing a medical illness metaphor against the backdrop of current UK clinical practice. Insightful and easy to read, Abolishing the Concept of Mental Illness will appeal to all professionals and academics working in clinical psychology, as well as psychotherapists and other mental health practitioners. Richard Hallam worked as a clinical psychologist, researcher, and lecturer until 2006, mainly in the National Health Service and at University College London and the University of East London. Since then he has worked independently as a writer, researcher, and therapist. ABOLISHING THE CONCEPT OF MENTAL ILLNESS Rethinking the Nature of Our Woes Richard Hallam First published 2018 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN and by Routledge 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2018 Richard Hallam The right of Richard Hallam to be identified as author of this work has been asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data A catalog record for this book has been requested ISBN: 978-1-138-06764-6 (hbk) ISBN: 978-1-138-06313-6 (pbk) ISBN: 978-1-315-16124-2 (ebk) Typeset in Bembo by Keystroke, Neville Lodge, Tettenhall, Wolverhampton CONTENTS Acknowledgements vii 1 Introducing the issues 1 2 Thomas Szasz and the myth of mental illness 22 3 ‘Mental’ and ‘bodily’ causes of woes: a brief history 43 4 ‘Major depression’: the creation of a mythical disease 57 5 Agency, rationality, and the concept of mental illness 80 6 Medicalisation: resistance or replacement? 103 7 Well-being and mental health 124 8 A future without the concept of mental illness 144 Index 171 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I am grateful for the astute comments and editorial suggestions of Glenn Shean, Chris Lee, and Gary Brown on early versions of the manuscript, and for innumerable conversations with other colleagues and friends. 1 INTRODUCING THE ISSUES Absurd! How can you abolish mental illness? I used to have a mental health problem myself. My great-uncle spent years in an asylum and he was definitely insane! The title of this book invites the reader to question the meaning of words in common use and to imagine a future in which we stop referring to mental illness. We have given up thinking about people as being ‘possessed by the devil’. Perhaps it is time to think differently about how to describe and explain the causes of our woes. At present, we seem content to leave it to experts to declare whether or not we are ‘mentally healthy’. The bleak terminology of mental disease or illness is reserved for rather obvious departures from ‘mental health’, but the idea of patho- logy is still present in watered-down terms such as ‘psychological disorder’ or ‘mental health issue’. Mental health professionals may rely on little more than answers to a questionnaire measuring ‘psychological symptoms’ to justify giving out a diagnostic label. If a problem seems to be a ‘serious’ one, a person’s suffering or difficulties will be matched against criteria set out in manuals for diagnosing ‘psychiatric illness’. The idea that the ability to live well has something to do with health and illness has infiltrated our social institutions to a remarkable degree. We have been invited to suppose that ‘mental illness’ is illness, in other words, like a physical illness, some- thing that we either have or don’t have. Mental ill-health encompasses a huge range of undesirable states of being, personal failings, and unacceptable behaviours. I will refer to them using the generic word ‘woes’, without assuming that the latter share anything in common with respect to their causes or how the woeful person experi- ences them. Rather than adopt the phrase ‘a problem in living’, which implies a problem for a particular person, I have chosen the word ‘woe’ to refer to a state of affairs that is social as well as personal. In its archaic use, a woe was a lament about 2 Introducing the issues being afflicted, wretched, or mournful. The thesis of this book is that woes have been medicalised, and recommends that we abandon the concept of mental illness, and imagine a future without it. This thesis is easily stated but immediately stirs up many questions. In this chapter, I set out the principal issues covered in the rest of the book. It needs to be said straight away that, more than fifty years ago, the psychiatrist Thomas Szasz declared that mental illness is a myth (Szasz, 2010 [1961]). I have therefore devoted a chapter to an analysis of his ideas and the arguments that critics have put forward to rebut them. The opposition Szasz encountered did not simply amount to a spat amongst academics and professionals. The debate about mental illness as a myth goes much deeper than this because a connection between health, illness, and woes has existed in ordinary speech for millennia. Although the concept of mental illness is ancient, it competed with beliefs in divine intervention, witchcraft, and sorcery, which have now largely disappeared in Western societies. The phrase ‘mental illness’ is now so commonplace that it is assumed to describe a literal state of affairs rather than constituting an explanation. In brief, it attributes a woe to something amiss in the mind or body of a woeful person. In Chapter 3, I explore the historical origins of this myth. What, then, does it mean to locate the cause of a person’s woe in their dysfunc- tional mind or body? Definitions of disease and illness are controversial, and so this question is not easily answered. However, few people seem to dispute the idea that ‘mental illness’ is a matter of ‘health’. Governments see it as one of their duties to look after the health and welfare of their citizens, and the conceptualisation of woes as illnesses has been accepted across all strands of political opinion. Provisions for ‘mental illness’ form part of services for physical health and social welfare. I will argue that the concept of mental illness is an example of the medicalisation of woes, and that this has led to mystification about causation, misdirection of efforts, and, on occasions, has usurped human rights. The final chapter of the book critically evaluates the role played by a concept of mental illness in policy documents published recently in the UK. Mental illness as myth Thomas Szasz’s belief that mental illness is a myth was vigorously contested. He restated his position shortly before he died (Szasz, 2011) and this invoked a scornful commentary (Shorter, 2011), illustrating how little influence Szasz exerted in some quarters of psychiatry. Shorter dismisses the ‘weasel word’ disorder and places his money on disease. Other experts also express themselves in the uncompromising language of disease. Morgan (2016) states that ‘depression is a common and crippling disease’, even though he accepts that it ‘may be a response to bereavement or other life events’. Szasz’s thesis has been rejected for various reasons. One argument is that mental illness has always been with us, and that we can clearly trace its presence in ancient literature. Another is that no meaningful distinction can be made between diseases of the mind and body, and that the criteria for declaring someone physically ill are Introducing the issues 3 essentially the same as ones that define mental illness. Other critics believe that the causes of problematic behaviour must lie in defective genes or diseases of the brain, even though we have not yet discovered them. It is assumed that once we understand the neural basis of mental functions, we will be in a position to define and explain mental illnesses. None of these objections to Szasz question the concept of mental illness itself. It is as if our woes and suffering must be illnesses because there is nothing else they could be. The idea is so firmly lodged in our way of thinking that to challenge it seems childishly provocative. Belief in the mythical status of mental illness is quite compatible with an assump- tion that there is a biological basis to all behaviour and so, in principle, it is possible to reduce all explanations to bodily processes. However, in order to establish solid grounds for describing woes as illness, it needs to be demonstrated that bodily func- tions deviate (i.e. function differently) when they serve ‘normal’ and ‘distressing or problematic’ behaviour.
Recommended publications
  • Psychosurgery for Political Purposes
    Psychosurgery for Political Purposes Peter R. Breggin, M.D. * INTRODUCTION Neurosurgeons and psychiatrists who favor psychosurgery some­ times show dismay that anyone would accuse them of harboring political aims, and it is true that the average psychosurgeon has little or no interest in the application of his technology to overtly political problems. But it is equally true that several of the nation's leading psychosurgeons have persistently linked their work to the control of urban violence, ghetto disorders and political dissent. These men rode the wave of hysteria generated by the urban upris­ ings of the late 1960's and parlayed the nation's fear into federal and state grants for themselves. As I review their statements and ac­ tions, keep in mind their shared political characteristics. Each of the psychosurgeons targeted potential patients according to well-recognized political categories. They began with a political issue of grave national concern, the inner-city uprisings of 1967 and 1968, and then attempted to redefine it as a medical disease or syndrome to justify their own interventions. This is analogous to the Russian practice of redefining political dissent into psychiatric cate­ gories in order to subject the dissenters to psychiatric authority and treatment. Even if "violence" were a recognized medical disease or syn­ drome, focus on a politically volatile segment of the population would raise the probability of a primarily political interest. In the absence of any such medical disease or syndrome, I the attempt to .. Psychiatrist and Executive Director of the Center for the Study of Psychiatry. 1. Kaimowitz v. Department of Mental Health, Civil No.
    [Show full text]
  • Soteria – a Treatment Model and a Reform Movement in Psychiatry
    1 Soteria – a treatment model and a reform movement in psychiatry By Volkmar Aderhold - Translated by Peter Stastny - September 2006 In honour of Loren Mosher “Everyone is much more simply human than otherwise” H.S.Sullivan - The interpersonal theory of psychiatry Introduction The Soteria treatment model was originated by the American Psychiatrist Loren Mosher during the early 1970s. As director of the Schizophrenia Branch at the National Institute Mental Health (1968-1980) he developed two federally-funded research demonstration projects: “Soteria” (1971-1983) and “Emanon” (1974-1980). The aim was to investigate the effects of a supportive milieu therapy (“being with”) for individuals diagnosed with “schizophrenia” (DSM-II), who were experiencing acute psychotic episodes for the first or second time in their lives. In these programs neuroleptics were either completely avoided, or given in low dosages only. Since the founding of Soteria Bern by Luc Ciompi in 1984, similar programs have been developed in Europe, mostly in the form of residential facilities situated in proximity to psychiatric hospitals. Initiatives to promote such programs are currently active around the world. Due to the expectation that neuroleptics would be used selectively, in acute as well as long-term situations, the program’s challenge to the medical model of “schizophrenia,” and the wide acceptance of inpatient treatment provided by mental health professionals (Mosher & Hendrix 2004, p. 282), the Soteria model has been consistently marginalized in psychiatric discourse and largely ignored in the scientific literature. On the other hand, during the past twenty years the Soteria approach has become quite influential within the debate about the optimal therapeutic methods and the development of state-of-the-art acute inpatient services.
    [Show full text]
  • Mental Health
    BRITISH JOURNAL OF PSYCH IAT RY ( 1007). 191 ( s upp l. 50 ), 171 -177. d ol: I0 .1191/ b j p . 191.5 0 .s71 REVIEW ARTICLE Schizophrenia outcome measures in the wider including clinical symptoms and their im­ provement, and social functioning, espe­ cially the ability to relate to people and international community performance at work (including employ­ ment, housework and tasks). Cognitive MOHAN ISAAC , PRABHAT CHAND and PRAT I MA MURT HY function, family burden and quality of life are other outcome measures. Outcome is also influenced by the course of schizo­ phrenia. The possible contribution of fac­ tors to the good prognosis observed in low- and middle-income countries is shown in the Appendix. Background Outcome of Schizophrenia may have a better outcome schizophrenia has been described as in low- and middle-income countries. The initial evidence for this came from the Inter­ Clinical symptoms favourable in low- and middle-income national Pilot Study of Schizophrenia (!PSS; The Present State Examination-9 (PSE-9; countries. Recently. researchers have World Health Organization, 1979) and was Wing et al, 1974) has been used as the mea­ questioned these findings. further strengthened by rwo subsequent sure of clinical symptoms at baseline and studies, the Determinants of Outcome of during follow-up in almost all long-term Aims To examine the outcome studies Severe Mental Disorders (DoSMED; studies from low- and middle-income coun­ carried out in different countries Jablensky et al, 1992) and the recently con­ tries. The PSE-9 assesses 140 symptoms specifically looking at those from low- and cluded International Study on Schizo­ grouped into 36 syndromes and measures phrenia (ISoS; Harrison et al, 2001).
    [Show full text]
  • The Case Against Psychiatric Coercion
    SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* FREE! “The Independent Review does not accept “The Independent Review is pronouncements of government officials nor the excellent.” conventional wisdom at face value.” —GARY BECKER, Noble Laureate —JOHN R. MACARTHUR, Publisher, Harper’s in Economic Sciences Subscribe to The Independent Review and receive a free book of your choice* such as the 25th Anniversary Edition of Crisis and Leviathan: Critical Episodes in the Growth of American Government, by Founding Editor Robert Higgs. This quarterly journal, guided by co-editors Christopher J. Coyne, and Michael C. Munger, and Robert M. Whaples offers leading-edge insights on today’s most critical issues in economics, healthcare, education, law, history, political science, philosophy, and sociology. Thought-provoking and educational, The Independent Review is blazing the way toward informed debate! Student? Educator? Journalist? Business or civic leader? Engaged citizen? This journal is for YOU! *Order today for more FREE book options Perfect for students or anyone on the go! The Independent Review is available on mobile devices or tablets: iOS devices, Amazon Kindle Fire, or Android through Magzter. INDEPENDENT INSTITUTE, 100 SWAN WAY, OAKLAND, CA 94621 • 800-927-8733 • [email protected] PROMO CODE IRA1703 The Case against Psychiatric Coercion —————— ✦ —————— THOMAS SZASZ “To commit violent and unjust acts, it is not enough for a government to have the will or even the power; the habits, ideas, and passions of the time must lend themselves to their committal.” —ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE (1981, 297) olitical history is largely the story of the holders of power committing violent and unjust acts against their people.
    [Show full text]
  • Mapping Coils of Paranoia in a Neocolonial Security State
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 6-2016 Becoming Serpent: Mapping Coils of Paranoia in a Neocolonial Security State Rachel J. Liebert Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/1286 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] BECOMING SERPENT: MAPPING COILS OF PARANOIA IN A NEOCOLONIAL SECURITY STATE By RACHEL JANE LIEBERT A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Psychology in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2016 © 2016 RACHEL JANE LIEBERT All Rights Reserved ii BECOMING SERPENT: MAPPING COILS OF PARANOIA IN A NEOCOLONIAL SECURITY STATE By RACHEL JANE LIEBERT This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Psychology to satisfy the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Michelle Fine Date Chair of Examining Committee Maureen O’Connor Date Executive Officer Michelle Fine Sunil Bhatia Cindi Katz Supervisory Committee THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii ABSTRACT Becoming Serpent: Mapping Coils of Paranoia in a Neocolonial Security State By Rachel Jane Liebert Advisor: Michelle Fine What follows is a feminist, decolonial experiment to map the un/settling circulation of paranoia – how it is done, what it does, what it could do – within contemporary conditions of US white supremacy.
    [Show full text]
  • BREAKDOWN Phoebe Sengers
    Document generated on 09/27/2021 8:55 p.m. Surfaces BREAKDOWN Phoebe Sengers SUR LA PUBLICATION ÉLECTRONIQUE Article abstract ON ELECTRONIC PUBLICATION The psychiatric institution mechanizes the patient. Absorbed into the workings Volume 4, 1994 of the psychiatric machine, the patient is reduced to a sign. Breakdown: the machine exceeds its own logic and the patient exceeds the institution's URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1064953ar totalizing grasp. Primary references to Deleuze and Guattari, Blanchot and DOI: https://doi.org/10.7202/1064953ar Goffman. See table of contents Publisher(s) Les Presses de l’Université de Montréal ISSN 1188-2492 (print) 1200-5320 (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Sengers, P. (1994). BREAKDOWN. Surfaces, 4. https://doi.org/10.7202/1064953ar Copyright © Phoebe Sengers, 1994 This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. Érudit is a non-profit inter-university consortium of the Université de Montréal, Université Laval, and the Université du Québec à Montréal. Its mission is to promote and disseminate research. https://www.erudit.org/en/ BREAKDOWN Phoebe Sengers ABSTRACT The psychiatric institution mechanizes the patient. Absorbed into the workings of the psychiatric machine, the patient is reduced to a sign. Breakdown: the machine exceeds its own logic and the patient exceeds the institution's totalizing grasp. Primary references to Deleuze and Guattari, Blanchot and Goffman. RÉSUMÉ L'institution psychiatrique mécanise le patient.
    [Show full text]
  • A Hunger Strike to Challenge International Domination by Biopsychiatry
    A Hunger Strike to Challenge International Domination by Biopsychiatry This fast is about human rights in mental health. The psychiatric pharmaceutical complex is heedless of its oath to "first do no harm." Psychiatrists are able with impunity to: *** Incarcerate citizens who have committed crimes against neither persons nor property. *** Impose diagnostic labels on people that stigmatize and defame them. *** Induce proven neurological damage by force and coercion with powerful psychotropic drugs. *** Stimulate violence and suicide with drugs promoted as able to control these activities. *** Destroy brain cells and memories with an increasing use of electroshock (also known as electro-convulsive therapy) *** Employ restraint and solitary confinement - which frequently cause severe emotional trauma, humiliation, physical harm, and even death - in preference to patience and understanding. *** Humiliate individuals already damaged by traumatizing assaults to their self-esteem. These human rights violations and crimes against human decency must end. While the history of psychiatry offers little hope that change will arrive quickly, initial steps can and must be taken. At the very least, the public has the right to know IMMEDIATELY the evidence upon which psychiatry bases its spurious claims and treatments, and upon which it has gained and betrayed the trust and confidence of the courts, the media, and the public. WHY WE FAST There are many different ways to help people experiencing severe mental and emotional crises. People labeled with a psychiatric disability deserve to be able to choose from a wide variety of these empowering alternatives. Self-determination is important to achieve real recovery. However, choice in the mental health field is severely limited.
    [Show full text]
  • Where Involuntary Commitment, Civil Liberties, and the Right to Mental Health Care Collide: an Overview of California's Mental Illness System Meredith Karasch
    Hastings Law Journal Volume 54 | Issue 2 Article 5 1-2003 Where Involuntary Commitment, Civil Liberties, and the Right to Mental Health Care Collide: An Overview of California's Mental Illness System Meredith Karasch Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_law_journal Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Meredith Karasch, Where Involuntary Commitment, Civil Liberties, and the Right to Mental Health Care Collide: An Overview of California's Mental Illness System, 54 Hastings L.J. 493 (2003). Available at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_law_journal/vol54/iss2/5 This Note is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hastings Law Journal by an authorized editor of UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Where Involuntary Commitment, Civil Liberties, and the Right to Mental Health Care Collide: An Overview of California's Mental Illness System by MEREDITH KARASCH* Introduction Buford George is a fifty-three-year-old diagnosed schizophrenic with violent and criminal tendencies who can often be found on the sidewalk along Mission Street in San Francisco. Over the past twenty years, George has been in and out of jail, mental institutions, and homelessness.2 In 1980, he was arrested for assaulting a woman and released when the case resulted in a deadlocked jury.' He was placed under conservatorship between 1984 and 1986, arrested again in 1998, and released after fifteen months of treatment because he was found competent to stand trial.4 In between episodes such as these, he can usually be found near Fourth and Mission Streets with a "constantly evolving collection of old luggage and clothing" and speaking mostly in unintelligible mumbles.
    [Show full text]
  • Coercion: the Only Constant in Psychiatric Practice? Tomi Gomory, David Cohen, and Stuart A
    Florida State University Libraries Faculty Publications College of Social Work 2013 Coercion: The Only Constant In Psychiatric Practice? Tomi Gomory, David Cohen, and Stuart A. Kirk Follow this and additional works at the FSU Digital Library. For more information, please contact [email protected] Coercion 1 Coercion: The Only Constant In Psychiatric Practice? Tomi Gomory, Associate Professor, Florida State University1 David Cohen, Professor, Florida International University Stuart A. Kirk, Professor Emeritus, University of California, Los Angeles To allow every maniac liberty consistent with safety; to proportion the degree of coercion to the … extravagance of behavior; … that bland art of conciliation, or the tone of irresistible authority pronouncing an irreversible mandate … are laws of fundamental importance … to the … successful management of all lunatic institutions. Philippe Pinel (1806) Introduction In the Western world, since at least the 15th century, state-sanctioned force has been employed to control those who disturb others by their violent or existentially destabilizing behaviors such as threatening or inflicting self-harm. Coercing the mad into madhouses, separating and detaining them from the rest of society, and forcing them to comply with their keepers’ wishes, occurred before physicians became involved in theorizing about the meaning or origins of madness, and it continues to distinguish psychiatric practice to this day. It is widely recognized that the mad used to be confined, beaten, tied, shocked or whirled into submission, but it seems less appreciated today by 1 Co-authors of Mad Science: The Disorders of American Psychiatry (Transaction Publishers, due in March 2013). Coercion 2 scholars, practitioners, and the general public that the physical control of “dangerous” mental patients remains a central function, and perhaps the only constant function, of public mental health systems.
    [Show full text]
  • Deinstitutionalization: Its Impact on Community Mental Health Centers and the Seriously Mentally Ill Stephen P
    Page 40 Deinstitutionalization: Its Impact on Community Mental Health Centers and the Seriously Mentally Ill Stephen P. Kliewer Melissa McNally Robyn L. Trippany Walden University Abstract Deinstitutionalization has had a significant impact on the mental health system, including the client, the agency, and the counselor. For clients with serious mental illness, learning to live in a community setting poses challenges that are often difficult to overcome. Community mental health agencies must respond to these specific needs, thus requiring a shift in how services are delivered and how mental health counselors need to be trained. The focus of this article is to explore the dynamics and challenges specific to deinstitution- alization, discuss implications for counselors, and identify solutions to respond to the identified challenges and resulting needs. State run psychiatric hospitals have traditionally been the primary component in the treatment of people with severe and persistent mental illness. For many years, individuals with severe mental illness (SMI) were kept out of the community setting. This isolation occurred for many reasons: a) the attitude of the public about people with mental illness, b) a belief that the mentally ill could only be helped in such settings, and c) a lack of resources at the community level (Patrick, Smith, Schleifer, Morris & McClennon, 2006). However, the institutional approach was not without its problems. A primary problem was the absence of hope and expecta- tion that patients would recover (Patrick, et al., 2006). In short, institutions seemed to become warehouses where mentally ill were kept for long periods of time with little expectation of improvement.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Work 618 Systems of Recovery from Mental Illness in Adults
    Social Work 618 Systems of Recovery From Mental Illness in Adults 3 Units Instructor: Marco Formigoni, LCSW Course Day: E-Mail: [email protected] Monday Office Hours: By appointment Course Location: VAC I. COURSE PREREQUISITES This advanced level practice course is only open to Mental Health Concentrations students who are working, in their current field placement, with adult clients who have been diagnosed with mental illnesses. II. CATALOGUE DESCRIPTION This advanced mental health practice course focuses on the multi-level impact of mental illness on adults and families. Evidence-based interventions promoting increased quality of life and stability are emphasized. III. COURSE DESCRIPTION This advanced-level elective course offers students the opportunity to learn about effective, leading -edge social work approaches to providing humane care for persons with mental illness, especially those clients with concomitant substance abuse, developmental disabilities and severe socioeconomic disadvantage who are commonly considered “difficult” to treat. The course offers students a comprehensive approach to social work practice with this population which includes outreach, clinical assessment; treatment planning that includes strengths orientation with client’s environment and collaboration with other systems, advocacy and program development as well as management. The contribution of discrimination and social inequalities to clients’ difficulties is considered throughout the course, including discrimination based on gender, race, ethnicity, socioeconomic status, sexual orientation, disability and diagnosis. Many different understandings related to the nature of the problem of severe mental illness are included and the required readings draw from various theoretical approaches to treatment, ranging from psychodynamic to ecological. The perspective of the course is client-centered in that the emphasis is on understanding the persons who have a severe mental illness, their strengths and the processes associated with acquiring care.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Critical Psychology, Counselling and Psychotherapy Appropriate, and Have to Use Force, Which Constitutes a Threat
    Winter 2010 Peter Lehmann 209 Medicalization and Peter * Lehmann Irresponsibility Through the example of an adolescent harmed by a variety of psychiatric procedures this paper concludes that bioethical and legal action (involving public discussion of human rights violations) should be taken to prevent further uninhibited unethical medicalization of problems that are largely of a social nature. Each human being loses, if even one single person allows himself to be lowered for a purpose. (Theodor Gottlieb von Hippel the Elder, 1741–1796, German enlightener) Beside imbalance and use of power, medicalization – the social definition of human problems as medical problems – is the basic flaw at the heart of the psychiatric discipline in the opinion of many social scientists, of users and survivors of psychiatry and critical psychiatrists. Like everywhere, in the discussion of medicalization there are many pros and cons as well as intermediate positions. When we discuss medicalization, we should have a very clear view, what medicalization can mean in a concrete way for an individual and which other factors are connected with medicalization; so we can move from talk to action. Medicalization and irresponsibility often go hand in hand. Psychiatry as a scientific discipline cannot do justice to the expectation of solving mental problems that are largely of a social nature. Its propensity and practice are not * Lecture, June 29, 2010, presented to the congress ‘The real person’, organized by the University of Preston (Lancashire), Institute for Philosophy, Diversity and Mental Health, in cooperation with the European Network of (ex-) Users and Survivors of Psychiatry (ENUSP) in Manchester within the Parallel Session ‘Psychiatric Medicalization: User and Survivor Perspectives’ (together with John Sadler, Professor of Medical Ethics & Clinical Sciences at the UT Southwestern, Dallas, and Jan Verhaegh, philosopher and ENUSP board-member, Valkenburg aan de Geul, The Netherlands).
    [Show full text]