A Companion to Applied Blackwell Companions to Philosophy

This outstanding student reference series offers a comprehensive and authoritative survey of philosophy as a whole. Written by today’s leading philosophers, each volume provides lucid and engaging coverage of the key figures, terms, topics, and problems of the field. Taken together, the volumes provide the ideal basis for course use, representing an unparalleled work of reference for students and specialists alike. Already published in the series: 1. The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy, Second Edition 33. A Companion to Nietzsche Edited by Nicholas Bunnin and Eric Tsui‐James Edited by Keith Ansell Pearson 2. A Companion to 34. A Companion to Socrates Edited by Peter Singer Edited by Sara Ahbel‐Rappe and Rachana Kamtekar 3. A Companion to Aesthetics, Second Edition 35. A Companion to Phenomenology and Existentialism Edited by Stephen Davies, Kathleen Marie Higgins, Edited by Hubert L. Dreyfus and Mark A. Wrathall Robert Hopkins, Robert Stecker, and David E. Cooper 36. A Companion to Kant 4. A Companion to Epistemology, Second Edition Edited by Graham Bird Edited by Jonathan Dancy, Ernest Sosa and Matthias Steup 37. A Companion to Plato 5. A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy Edited by Hugh H. Benson (two‐volume set), Second Edition 38. A Companion to Descartes Edited by Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit Edited by Janet Broughton and John Carriero 6. A Companion to Philosophy of Mind 39. A Companion to the Philosophy of Biology Edited by Samuel Guttenplan Edited by Sahotra Sarkar and Anya Plutynski 7. A Companion to Metaphysics, Second Edition 40. A Companion to Hume Edited by Jaegwon Kim, Ernest Sosa and Gary S. Rosenkrantz Edited by Elizabeth S. Radcliffe 8. A Companion to Philosophy of Law and 41. A Companion to the Philosophy of History and Legal Theory, Second Edition Historiography Edited by Dennis Patterson Edited by Aviezer Tucker 9. A Companion to Philosophy of Religion, Second Edition 42. A Companion to Aristotle Edited by Charles Taliaferro, Paul Draper, and Philip L. Quinn Edited by Georgios Anagnostopoulos 10. A Companion to the Philosophy of Language 43. A Companion to the Philosophy of Technology Edited by Bob Hale and Crispin Wright Edited by Jan‐Kyrre Berg Olsen, Stig Andur Pedersen, 11. A Companion to World and Vincent F. Hendricks Edited by Eliot Deutsch and Ron Bontekoe 44. A Companion to Latin American Philosophy 12. A Companion to Continental Philosophy Edited by Susana Nuccetelli, Ofelia Schutte, Edited by Simon Critchley and William Schroeder and Otávio Bueno 13. A Companion to Feminist Philosophy 45. A Companion to the Philosophy of Literature Edited by Alison M. Jaggar and Iris Marion Young Edited by Garry L. Hagberg and Walter Jost 14. A Companion to Cognitive Science 46. A Companion to the Philosophy of Action Edited by William Bechtel and George Graham Edited by Timothy O’Connor and Constantine Sandis 15. A Companion to Bioethics, Second Edition 47. A Companion to Relativism Edited by Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer Edited by Steven D. Hales 16. A Companion to the Philosophers 48. A Companion to Hegel Edited by Robert L. Arrington Edited by Stephen Houlgate and Michael Baur 17. A Companion to Business Ethics 49. A Companion to Schopenhauer Edited by Robert E. Frederick Edited by Bart Vandenabeele 18. A Companion to the Philosophy of Science 50. A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy Edited by W. H. Newton‐Smith Edited by Steven M. Emmanuel 19. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy 51. A Companion to Foucault Edited by Dale Jamieson Edited by Christopher Falzon, Timothy O’Leary, 20. A Companion to Analytic Philosophy and Jana Sawicki Edited by A. P. Martinich and David Sosa 52. A Companion to the Philosophy of Time 21. A Companion to Genethics Edited by Heather Dyke and Adrian Bardon Edited by Justine Burley and John Harris 53. A Companion to Donald Davidson 22. A Companion to Philosophical Logic Edited by Ernest Lepore and Kirk Ludwig Edited by Dale Jacquette 54. A Companion to Rawls 23. A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy Edited by A. P. Martinich and David Sosa Edited by Steven Nadler 55. A Companion to W.V.O Quine 24. A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages Edited by Gilbert Harman and Ernest Lepore Edited by Jorge J. E. Gracia and Timothy B. Noone 56. A Companion to Derrida 25. A Companion to African‐American Philosophy Edited by Zeynep Direk and Leonard Lawlor Edited by Tommy L. Lott and John P. Pittman 57. A Companion to David Lewis 26. A Companion to Applied Ethics Edited by Barry Loewer and Jonathan Schaffer Edited by R. G. Frey and Christopher Heath Wellman 58. A Companion to Kierkegaard 27. A Companion to the Philosophy of Education Edited by Jon Stewart Edited by Randall Curren 59. A Companion to Locke 28. A Companion to African Philosophy Edited by Matthew Stuart Edited by Kwasi Wiredu 60. The Blackwell Companion to Hermeneutics 29. A Companion to Heidegger Edited by Niall Keane and Chris Lawn Edited by Hubert L. Dreyfus and Mark A. Wrathall 61. A Companion to Ayn Rand 30. A Companion to Rationalism Edited by Allan Gotthelf and Gregory Salmieri Edited by Alan Nelson 62. The Blackwell Companion to Naturalism 31. A Companion to Pragmatism Edited by Kelly James Clark Edited by John R. Shook and Joseph Margolis 63. A Companion to Applied Philosophy 32. A Companion to Ancient Philosophy Edited by Kasper Lippert‐Rasmussen, Kimberley Edited by Mary Louise Gill and Pierre Pellegrin Brownlee, and David Coady A Companion to Applied Philosophy

Edited by Kasper Lippert‐Rasmussen, Kimberley Brownlee, and David Coady This edition first published 2017 © 2017 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

Registered Office John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK

Editorial Offices 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148‐5020, USA 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK

For details of our global editorial offices, for customer services, and for information about how to apply for permission to reuse the copyright material in this book please see our website at www.wiley.com/wiley‐blackwell.

The rights of Kasper Lippert‐Rasmussen, Kimberley Brownlee, and David Coady to be identified as the authors of of the editorial material in this work has been asserted in accordance with the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, without the prior permission of the publisher.

Wiley also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats. Some content that appears in print may not be available in electronic books.

Designations used by companies to distinguish their products are often claimed as trademarks. All brand names and product names used in this book are trade names, service marks, trademarks or registered trademarks of their respective owners. The publisher is not associated with any product or vendor mentioned in this book.

Limit of Liability/Disclaimer of Warranty: While the publisher and authors have used their best efforts in preparing this book, they make no representations or warranties with respect to the accuracy or completeness of the contents of this book and specifically disclaim any implied warranties of merchantability or fitness for a particular purpose. It is sold on the understanding that the publisher is not engaged in rendering professional services and neither the publisher nor the author shall be liable for damages arising herefrom. If professional advice or other expert assistance is required, the services of a competent professional should be sought.

Library of Congress Cataloging‐in‐Publication Data Names: Lippert-Rasmussen, Kasper, 1964– editor. | Brownlee, Kimberley, editor. | Coady, David, 1965– editor. Title: A companion to applied philosophy / edited by Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Kimberley Brownlee, and David Coady. Description: Chichester, UK ; Hoboken, NJ : John Wiley & Sons, 2016. | Includes bibliographical references and index. Identifiers: LCCN 2016023733| ISBN 9781118869130 (cloth) | ISBN 9781118869116 (Adobe PDF) | ISBN 9781118869123 (epub) Subjects: LCSH: Applied philosophy. Classification: LCC B831.3 .C66 2016 | DDC 100–dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016023733

A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

Cover image: Vermeer, Jan (1632–1675): Young Woman with a Water Pitcher, c. 1662. New York, Metropolitan Museum of Art. Oil on canvas, 18 × 16 in. (45.7 × 40.6 cm). Marquand Collection, Gift of Henry G. Marquand, 1889. Acc.n.: 89.15.21 © 2016. Image copyright: The Metropolitan Museum of Art/Art Resource/Scala, Florence

Set in 10/12.5pt Photina by SPi Global, Pondicherry, India

10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Contents

Notes on Contributors ix Foreword xvi Acknowledgments xix

Part I Introductory Articles 1 1 The Nature of Applied Philosophy 3 Kasper Lippert‐Rasmussen 2 The Methodology of Applied Philosophy 18 David Archard 3 The Value of Applied Philosophy 34 Suzanne Uniacke

Part II Epistemology 49 4 Applied Epistemology 51 David Coady 5 Gender and Feminist Epistemology 61 Nancy Daukas 6 The Epistemology of Deliberative Democracy 76 Fabienne Peter 7 Information Markets 89 Kristoffer Ahlstrom‐Vij 8 Epistemology for (Real) People 103 Michael Bishop and J.D. Trout 9 Are Conspiracy Theorists Epistemically Vicious? 120 Charles R. Pigden

v contents 10 Experts in the Climate Change Debate 133 Ben Almassi 11 Freedom of Expression, Diversity, and Truth 147 Klemens Kappel, Bjørn Hallsson, and Emil F.L. Møller

Part III Metaphysics and Philosophy of Language 163 12 Applied Metaphysics 165 Katherine Hawley 13 Applied Philosophy of Language 180 Emma Borg 14 Social Ontology and War 196 Seumas Miller 15 The Metaphysics of Gender 211 Natalie Stoljar 16 The Existence of the Dead 224 Steven Luper 17 Freedom of Expression and Derogatory Words 236 Caroline West

Part IV Ethics 253 18 Applied Moral Philosophy 255 Richard Arneson 19 Neuroethics and Responsibility 270 Neil Levy 20 Non‐ideal Theory 284 Zofia Stemplowska 21 Death: Badness and Prudential Reasons 297 Jens Johansson

Part V Political Philosophy and Philosophy of Law 311 22 Applied Political and Legal Philosophy 313 Michelle Madden Dempsey and Matthew Lister 23 Legal Human Rights Theory 328 Samantha Besson 24 Collectivism and Reductivism in the Ethics of War 342 Helen Frowe 25 Freedom of Association 356 Kimberley Brownlee vi Contents 26 Neuroethics and Criminal Justice 370 Jesper Ryberg and Thomas Søbirk Petersen 27 Deliberative Democracy 383 Thomas Christiano and Sameer Bajaj 28 Tax Ethics: Political and Individual 397 Geoffrey Brennan and George Tsai 29 Benefiting from Wrongdoing 411 Avia Pasternak 30 Freedom of Religion and Expression 424 Larry Alexander

Part VI Philosophy of Science 439 31 Applied Philosophy of Social Science: The Case of the Social Construction of Race 441 Isaac Wiegman and Ron Mallon 32 Social Constructivism in Social Science and Science Wars 455 Finn Collin 33 Did Climate Change Cause That? 469 Richard Corry

Part VII Aesthetics 485 34 Applied Aesthetics 487 David Davies 35 Thought Experiments in Aesthetics 501 Paisley Livingston and Mikael Pettersson 36 Aesthetic Value, Artistic Value, and Morality 514 Andrea Sauchelli 37 The Applied Philosophy of Humor 527 Noël Carroll

Part VIII Philosophy of Religion 539 38 Applied Philosophy of Religion 541 C.A.J. Coady 39 Thinking about Reported Miracles 555 Timothy Mcgrew 40 Religion and Neuroscience 567 Monima Chadha

vii contents Part IX History of Applied Philosophy 583 41 Ancient Applied Philosophy 585 Chris Megone 42 Modern Applied Philosophy: Kant on Theory and Practice 599 Allen Wood

Index 612

viii Notes on Contributors

Kristoffer Ahlstrom‐Vij is a former Fulbright and Templeton Foundation Fellow, and currently senior lecturer in philosophy at the University of Kent, Canterbury. His research focuses on social epistemology and epistemic normativity, and has been published in, among other places, Noûs, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Episteme, Philosophical Quarterly, and Philosophical Studies. Larry Alexander is the Warren Distinguished Professor of Law at the University of San Diego. He is the author or co‐author of several books, the editor of several anthologies, and the author or co‐author of over 220 published articles, essays, and book chapters on legal and moral philosophy, criminal law theory, and constitutional theory. Ben Almassi is an assistant professor in the Division of Humanities and Social Sciences at Governors State University, Illinois, where he teaches practical and professional ethics, philosophy of science, and political philosophy. His recent publications in applied philosophy include “Medical Ghostwriting and Informed Consent” (2014) and “Climate Change, Epistemic Trust, and Expert Trustworthiness” (2012). He thanks the organizers of the 2011 Workshop on Climate Justice at the University of Alaska‐Anchorage and 2012 Summer Symposium on Science Communication at Iowa State University, where several aspects of his contribution to this volume were first developed. David Archard is professor of philosophy at Queen’s University Belfast, having previ- ously taught at the Universities of Ulster, St Andrews, and Lancaster. He is a past Honorary Chair of the Society for Applied Philosophy. His publications have addressed the philosophical issues of the child, family, and state, sexual consent, education, moral expertise, and the application of philosophy to public policy. Richard Arneson has been a professor in the Department of Philosophy at the University of California, San Diego since 1973. He has published extensively on a wide number of topics in ethics, political philosophy, and applied ethics. His current research interests include the relation between distributive justice and responsibility and forms of consequentialist morality that are responsive to standard objections.

ix Notes on Contributors Sameer Bajaj is a doctoral candidate in philosophy at the University of Arizona. He works primarily in political philosophy, metaethics, and the philosophy of law. His current research develops an account of democratic justice that gives a central role to both the ideal of public reason – which requires that political activity is mutually acceptable – and epistemic considerations – which concern democracy’s ability to produce decisions that correspond to or track the procedure‐independent truth about justice.

Samantha Besson is professor of public international law and European law at the University of Fribourg (Switzerland). Her research focus and publications interests lie in the philosophy of international law and human rights. She is the co‐editor of The Philosophy of International Law (2010) and The Oxford Handbook on the Sources of International Law (forthcoming). She is currently completing a monograph entitled Human Rights as Law.

Michael Bishop is professor of philosophy at Florida State University. He has authored or co-authored articles on a wide range of issues in philosophy of science, ethics and epistemology. He is co-author, with J.D. Trout, of Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment (2005). His most recent book, The Good Life: Unifying the Philosophy and Psychology of Well-Being (2015), builds an empirically grounded and philosophically reflective theory of wellbeing.

Emma Borg is a professor of philosophy at the University of Reading, UK. Her main research interests lie in philosophy of language (where she defends a position known as “minimal semantics”) and philosophy of mind (where she is interested in issues around modularity, embodied/enactive cognition, mirror neurons, and animal cognition). She has published widely in these areas, including two monographs, Minimal Semantics (2004) and Pursuing Meaning (2012), and has held numerous research grants, including a Philip Leverhulme Prize award. Emma is currently Director of the Reading Centre for Cognition Research and an Associate Investigator at the Australian Research Council Centre of Excellence in Cognition and Its Disorders.

Geoffrey Brennan is an economist by training who works increasingly at the interface between economics and political and moral philosophy. He is author of six books and over 250 articles and book chapters. He was a collaborator on two books, The Power to Tax and The Reason of Rules, with Nobel Laureate James Buchanan. His most recent book is co‐authored with Nicholas Southwood, Lina Eriksson, and Bob Goodin, entitled Explaining Norms.

Kimberley Brownlee is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Warwick. Her research focuses on the ethics of sociability, social rights, social , and freedom of association. She is the author of and Conviction: The Case for Civil Disobedience (2012) and co-editor of Disability and Disadvantage (2009).

Noël Carroll is distinguished professor of philosophy at City University of New York. He specializes in philosophy of art and aesthetics in the United States. x Notes on Contributors Monima Chadha is senior lecturer in philosophy at Monash University Australia. Her main research interests are in Buddhist philosophy of mind and Indian philosophy more generally. She has published extensively in journals such as Philosophy East and West, Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences, and Asian Philosophy. Thomas Christiano is professor of philosophy and law at the University of Arizona. He has written The Rule of the Many (1996) and The Constitution of Equality: Democratic Authority and Its Limits (2008). He has edited a number of books on political philosophy and written articles on the theory of democratic deliberation in large societies and on distributive justice and international institutions. He is co‐editor of Politics, Philosophy and Economics. C.A.J. (Tony) Coady is a prominent Australian philosopher well known for his writings on epistemology and on issues concerning political morality. He is Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, and was Boyce Gibson Professor of Philosophy at the University of Melbourne. His publications include Testimony: A Philosophical Study (1992), Morality and Political Violence (2008), and Messy Morality: The Challenge of Politics (2008). A current research project concerns the role of religion in politics. David Coady is a senior lecturer in philosophy at the University of Tasmania, Australia. He has published on many topics in applied epistemology, including expertise, conspiracy theory, rumor, and the blogosphere. He is the editor of Conspiracy Theories: The Philosophical Debate (2006), the author of What To Believe Now: Applying Epistemology to Contemporary Issues (2012), and the co‐author of The Climate Change Debate: An Epistemic and Ethical Enquiry (2013). He has also published on metaphysics, philos- ophy of law, police ethics, the ethics of horror films, and the ethics of cricket. Finn Collin holds a PhD degree from University of California Berkeley (1978) and a DPhil degree from the University of Copenhagen (1985), where he is currently a pro- fessor of philosophy. His writings are mainly in the philosophy of science, focusing upon the social sciences and the humanities. Chief titles in English are Theory and Understanding (1985), Social Reality (1993), and Science Studies as Naturalized Philosophy (2011). Richard Corry is a lecturer in philosophy at the University of Tasmania, Australia. He has published on numerous topics in the metaphysics of science and causation. He is author, with David Coady, of The Climate Change Debate: An Epistemic and Ethical Enquiry (2013), and editor, with Huw Price, of Causation, Physics, and the Constitution of Reality (2007). He has also published on ethics and on the philosophy of ESP. Nancy Daukas is a professor of philosophy and contributing faculty in Women’s, Gender, and Sexuality Studies at Guilford College in Greensboro, North Carolina, USA. Publications include Epistemic Trust and Social Location (2006) and Altogether Now: A ‐Theoretic Approach to Pluralism in Feminist Epistemology (2011). David Davies is professor of philosophy at McGill University. He is the author of Art as Performance (2004), Aesthetics and Literature (2007), and Philosophy of the Performing Arts (2011); editor of The Thin Red Line (2008); and co‐editor of Blade Runner (2015). He has published widely on philosophical issues relating to film, photography,

xi Notes on Contributors performance, music, literature, and visual art, and on issues in metaphysics, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language. Michelle Madden Dempsey (JD, LLM, DPhil) is a professor of law at Villanova University School of Law in Pennsylvania, USA, and was tutorial fellow and CUF l­ecturer in law at the University of Oxford (2006–2009). She is an associate editor of Criminal Law and Philosophy, member of the American Law Institute, former Chair of the American Association of Law Schools’ Scholarship and Jurisprudence Sections, and member of the American Philosophical Association’s Committee on Law and Philosophy. Helen Frowe is professor of practical philosophy and Wallenberg Academy research fellow at Stockholm University, where she directs the Stockholm Centre for the Ethics of War and Peace. She is the author of Defensive Killing (2014), The Ethics of War and Peace: An Introduction (2011), and co‐editor of The Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War (2015) and How We Fight: Ethics in War (2014). Bjørn Hallsson is a PhD student at the University of Copenhagen. He has a background in psychology and is doing research on the epistemology of disagreement. Katherine Hawley is professor of philosophy at the University of St Andrews. She is the author of How Things Persist (2001), Trust: A Very Short Introduction (2012), and articles on parts and wholes, identity, natural kinds, and practical knowledge. Jens Johansson is associate professor of practical philosophy at Uppsala University. He is the author of a number of essays on the philosophy of death and related issues (including personal identity and wellbeing), and co‐edited the Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death (2013, with Ben Bradley and Fred Feldman). Klemens Kappel is associate professor in philosophy at the University of Copenhagen. His research interests include social epistemology, political philosophy, and bioethics.

Neil Levy is professor of philosophy at Macquarie University, Sydney and Director of Research at the Oxford Centre for Neuroethics. He has published widely in neuroethics, philosophy of mind, and applied ethics. His most recent book is Consciousness and Moral Responsibility (2014).

Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen is Professor of Political Theory at the University of Aarhus and Professor II in Philosophy at the University of Tromsø. Recent publications include Born Free and Equal? (2013) and Luck Egalitarianism (2015). He is an associate editor of Ethics and was Chair of the Society for Applied Philosophy from 2012 to 2014. Matthew Lister (JD, PhD) is a visiting assistant professor of legal studies at the Wharton School of Business in the University of Pennsylvania. He has previously taught at the University of Pennsylvania Law School, Villanova Law School, and the University of Denver, Sturm College of Law. He is the current chair of the American Philosophical Association’s Committee on Law and Philosophy. Paisley Livingston is chair professor of philosophy at Lingnan University, Hong Kong. He has published books and papers on various topics in aesthetics. xii Notes on Contributors Steven Luper is Murchison term professor and chair of the Philosophy Department at Trinity University, Texas. Among his publications are The Philosophy of Death (2009) and The Cambridge Companion to Life and Death (2014). Ron Mallon is an associate professor of philosophy at Washington University in St. Louis and Director of the Philosophy‐Neuroscience‐Psychology Program. His research interests are at the intersection of culture and the mind. He is currently working on a book on the social and psychological construction of human categories. Timothy McGrew is professor and chairman of the Department of Philosophy at Western Michigan University. He specializes in the theory of knowledge, probability theory, the history and philosophy of science, and the philosophy of religion. He has published in numerous journals including Mind, The Monist, Analysis, Erkenntnis, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, and Philosophia Christi. His recent publi­ cations include the article “Evidence” in The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, co‐authorship of The Philosophy of Science: An Historical Anthology, co‐authorship (with Lydia McGrew) of the article “The Argument from Miracles” in The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology, and the article “Miracles” for The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Chris Megone is professor of inter‐disciplinary applied ethics, and director of Inter‐ Disciplinary Ethics Applied, a national Centre of Excellence (the IDEA CETL) at the University of Leeds. He has wide‐ranging publications – in Aristotelian ethics, in applied ethics, especially in medical ethics and business and professional ethics, and in the area of moral psychology and rationality. He was awarded a National Teaching Fellowship in 2006. Seumas Miller is a professorial fellow at the Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics at Charles Sturt University (Canberra) and the 3TU Centre for Ethics and Technology at Delft University of Technology (The Hague). He is the author or co‐author of over 200 academic articles and 15 books, including Terrorism and Counter‐ terrorism (2009) and Moral Foundations of Social Institutions (2010). Emil F.L. Møller is a former postdoctoral student in philosophy at the University of Copenhagen. Avia Pasternak is a senior lecturer in global ethics at the School of Public Policy, University College London. She is interested in questions of collective responsibility and political obligations in the face of unjust state policies. She co-edited a special issue in the Journal of Applied Philosophy (2014, 31(4)) on benefiting from injustice. Fabienne Peter is professor of philosophy at the University of Warwick. She specializes in social epistemology and moral and political philosophy. Currently, she is editor of Economics and Philosophy. Mikael Pettersson is assistant professor of philosophy at Lingnan University, Hong Kong. He has published papers on depiction and the philosophy of photography. Charles R. Pigden has taught at the University of Otago since 1988. He has published on a wide range of topics from the analytic/synthetic distinction through truthmaker

xiii Notes on Contributors theory to Jane Austen’s Mr Elliot. He has edited Russell on Ethics (1999), Hume on Motivation and Virtue (2009), and Hume on Is and Ought (2010). Jesper Ryberg is professor of ethics and philosophy of law at Roskilde University, Denmark. He is the head of the Research Group for Criminal Justice Ethics and is ­currently the head of a research project on neuroscience and criminal justice. Recent publications include Punishment and Ethics (ed. with A. Corlett) Palgrave Macmillan 2010 and Popular Punishment (ed. with J. Roberts) Oxford University Press 2014. Andrea Sauchelli is an assistant professor in the Department of Philosophy at Lingnan University, Hong Kong. His areas of current interest include personal identity and applied ethics; and aesthetics and philosophy of art (art and ethics). Thomas Søbirk Petersen is professor (MSO) of practical philosophy, Roskilde University, Denmark. Zofia Stemplowska is associate professor of political theory and Asa Briggs fellow of Worcester College, University of Oxford. She writes on domestic, global, and historical injustice and is the co‐editor (with Carl Knight) of Responsibility and Distributive Justice (2011). Natalie Stoljar is associate professor in the Department of Philosophy and the Institute for Health and Social Policy at McGill University, Canada. She is co‐editor (with Catriona Mackenzie) of Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self (2000) and author of many articles on autonomy, feminist metaphysics, and legal philosophy. J.D. Trout is professor of philosophy and psychology at Loyola University in Chicago. He has authored or co-authored articles on a wide range of issues in philosophy of ­science, epistemology, psychology, and policy. He is co-author, with Michal Bishop, of Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment (2005). His most recent book, Wondrous Truths: The Improbable Triumph of Modern Science, argues that scientific realism is supported by contingencies in history and by good explanations whose truth is independent of their audience. George Tsai is an assistant professor of philosophy at the University of Hawaii. He works primarily in moral and political philosophy. He has published or forthcoming work in venues including Philosophy and Public Affairs, Journal of Political Philosophy, Social Theory and Practice, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, and Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility. Suzanne Uniacke is director of the Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics (CAPPE) at Charles Sturt University, Australia. Her publications address philosophical issues of biomedicine, interpersonal and political conflict, and criminal law, and aspects of normative moral theory. Caroline West is senior lecturer in philosophy at the University of Sydney. Her research spans topics in metaphysics, philosophy of language, ethics, political philosophy, and feminism, including personal identity, free speech, and happiness. Relevant publica- tions include “Scorekeeping in a Pornographic Language Game” (with Rae Langton), xiv Notes on Contributors Australasian Journal of Philosophy, “The Free Speech Argument Against Pornography,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, and “What is Free Speech?” (with David Braddon‐ Mitchell), Journal of Political Philosophy. Isaac Wiegman is a lecturer at Texas State University. His research interests are in the philosophy of psychology and moral psychology. One of his papers, “The Evolution of Retribution,” is forthcoming in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. Allen Wood is Ruth Norman Halls Professor at Indiana University and Ward W. and Priscilla B. Woods professor emeritus at Stanford University. He has also held professor- ships at Cornell and Yale University and was Isaiah Berlin Visiting Professor at Oxford University in 2005. He is author of 10 books, editor or translator of a dozen more, mainly in the areas of eighteenth‐ and nineteenth‐century German philosophy, ethics, and political philosophy. His most recent book is The Free Development of Each: Studies on Freedom, Right and Ethics in Classical German Philosophy (2014). His forthcoming book is Fichte’s Ethical Thought (2016).

xv Foreword

I am delighted to have this opportunity, as the current Chief Editor of the Journal of Applied Philosophy, to contribute a foreword celebrating the publication of the Blackwell Companion to Applied Philosophy. The editors and contributors are to be warmly congrat- ulated for their achievement and thanked for their efforts. This is a milestone collection. The chapters collected here capture the breadth and vibrancy of the many ways in which philosophers bring their distinctive skills and outlook to bear on applied issues. Judging by this Companion – as well as by the articles being published by the Journal of Applied Philosophy and other journals like it – applied philosophy has a bright future ahead of it. The Society of Applied Philosophy was founded in 1982 with the aim of “promoting philosophical study and research that has a direct bearing on areas of practical con- cern.” The first issues of the Journal of Applied Philosophy appeared in 1984. Of course, applied philosophy did not begin with the founding of a society or journal with “applied philosophy” in the title. But these innovations, as with the founding of Philosophy and Public Affairs a decade earlier, testified to the appetite of philosophers to engage qua phi- losophers with the political and personal issues being raised by the rapidly changing societies around them. They helped to crystallize and provide a conduit for two lines of thought: first, that many actually existing social, political, and personal controversies had a basis in claims, counter‐claims, and confusions of a philosophical nature, and hence that clear, incisive philosophical reasoning could bring some benefit to those who wrestle with such controversies (among whom, often, are philosophers themselves in their life outside the seminar room); and second, that the skills in which philosophers become highly adept represent a great reservoir of intellectual power, and that these tools should sometimes be placed in the service not just of the intrinsic goods of philosophical understanding itself – important though that is – but of ends connected with the development of the individual and society. Given the opportunity, many p­hilosophers have chosen to turn their minds to applied issues in some way or other, and their work is increasingly influential within academia and beyond. If that tells us something about the “why” of applied philosophy, we can also ask what it is or how we would go about it. The first thing to say is – to echo a thought expressed by a number of authors in the Companion – that applied philosophy is far xvi Foreword broader than applied ethics. Applied epistemology, applied philosophy of language, applied metaphysics, as well as simply applied conceptual analysis, can bring illumina- tion to practical issues. Take the question of life after death: What would it mean to live on after death? One cannot come to an answer without stepping on philosophical issues regarding identity and persistence through time. Is pure evil intelligible? Is the type of freedom of the will that we can realistically ascribe to ourselves sufficient for moral or legal responsibility? What goes on when we forgive? What kind of speech act is pornog- raphy? These are applied philosophical questions, but their answers take us beyond applied ethics. Furthermore, important questions regarding the nature of knowledge arise when we start to reflect on the extent to which we depend on the opinion of experts in our increasingly complex, technology‐reliant societies, facing as we do major chal- lenges as a result on ongoing specialization and industrialization. What should we believe about climate change? What is the proper role of experts and expert knowledge in democratic society? What is the role of trust in knowledge? What is the role of expert consensus in providing warrant for the beliefs of non‐experts? Are there non‐epistemic marks of epistemic authority? Are our existing epistemic practices in line with our best models of knowledge creation and transmission? The term “applied philosophy” can suggest one‐way traffic, where the philosophy is largely done prior to the application, and the concern with practice involves showing what the theory suggests regarding this particular issue. This would still be important, of course, as long as it is true that philosophical theorizing can illuminate practical issues. However, one might draw the conclusion from this suggestion that the serious philosophical work is being done elsewhere. This impression might be compounded if we assume philosophy ideally to be of the “hedgehog” rather than the “fox” variety – to use the contrast made popular in our profession by Isaiah Berlin and, more recently, by Ronald Dworkin (where the fox knows many small things, the hedgehog one big thing). That is, if we assume philosophy ideally to be highly systematic and in some way “pure,” then the worry might emerge that its application can only be – from a purely philosophical point of view, at least – a second‐tier and in some way grubbier, inferior product (though – to be clear – this is not a worry that a reading of Dworkin’s hedgehog‐ ism would encourage). In which case, although there might be plenty of interest among practitioners – so the picture goes – in what philosophers have to tell them, there would be little for philosophers to learn from reading applied philosophy rather than its purer versions. However, in my experience as a writer and reader of applied philosophy, the process is beneficial in both directions: the philosophically informed engagement with practical issues is a fertile source of philosophical understanding as well as of practical illumina- tion. Applied philosophy, in other words, can and should be philosophically interesting in its own right. In part, this is because of the importance of the method of reflective equilibrium to philosophical theorizing: the mutual adjustment of intuitions and principles, or of practical and theoretical understanding. Even with the increasing popularity and influence of naturalistic and “experimental” philosophy, it is often hard to see how philosophical reasoning can avoid resting at some level on “how things strike us.” However, in addition, paying attention to practice can aid philosophical understanding because, as Wittgenstein has it, sometimes making philosophical progress requires us to vary our diet of examples. Philosophy works with models and metaphors,

xvii Foreword the appropriateness of which are often derived from taking certain practical examples as paradigmatic. Looking at the rich resources of human life, and the varied ways in which people have reflected on its philosophical basis in forms other than academic phi- losophy, can sometimes help us to see the limited presuppositions of philosophical debate and suggest new paradigms and models. Furthermore, one does not have to be a Wittgensteinian quietist about the ambitions of philosophy to be humbled by the wisdom of highly skilled practitioners in government, law, medicine, and so forth in dealing with urgent and complex issues on a day‐to‐day basis. In the face of the efforts of such practitioners to make sense of challenges and to act for the best, it is not an abandonment of the critical potential of our discipline to conclude that sometimes all philosophy can do is to seek to give a theoretical articulation to such wisdom, putting it into a wider philosophical context rather than attempting to second guess or even to refine it. Applied philosophy, then, can – and should – involve many different approaches to the relation between philosophy and practice. As the contents of this Companion indicate, philosophers have always been inter- ested in the application of their theories and their skills to issues of practical concern. Plato, Aquinas, and Hegel represent some of the systematizers; Aristotle perhaps stands at the head of the opposing tradition of placing the appearances first. Indeed, one might argue that the idea that there is a distinction between pure and applied philosophy is itself a historical development, one that requires a certain degree of academic speciali- zation, but which is not at all universal in the history of philosophy. This is not itself to cast doubt on the validity of the distinction. But thinkers like Plato and Aristotle argu- ably did not think of themselves as developing their philosophy first and applying it after. Rather they thought of themselves as answering questions, constructing theories, developing a method for thinking through problems, that would apply to what we might now call applied and pure topics as a whole rather than differently. Another way of thinking about applied philosophy, we might say, is as the application of a set of skills in which philosophers are highly trained, rather than the application of pre‐formed t­heories or doctrines. Whatever applied philosophy amounts to – and largely we should let a thousand flowers bloom, judging the worth of a method by its results – this collection shows that it is in fine fettle. Nevertheless, the practice of applied philosophy is to some extent fragile, at the mercy of political context and trends in academic specialization. Within living memory it has not always been a sure route to credibility in philosophy to devote oneself to real‐world issues. Philosophers in the Anglo‐American tradition have some- times taken pride in their isolation from what other – particularly Continental – thinkers have taken to be “relevance” (even while the claim that philosophy concerns itself with timeless truths rather than transient matters has had fewer and fewer defenders). This Companion is testament to the fact that this is rapidly changing, and we should cele- brate that fact. There really is a lot for philosophers to turn their attention to.

Christopher Bennett Chief Editor, Journal of Applied Philosophy

xviii Acknowledgments

We wish to express our gratitude to Fay Niker for her assistance in preparing the manuscript and to Clare Hymer for assistance with the index. We thank the editors at Wiley with whom we have worked: Natarajan Bhargavi, Liam Cooper, Sally Cooper, Jeff Dean, Allison Kostka, Manish Luthra, and Roshna Mohan. We are grateful to Christopher Bennett for his excellent Foreword and to the 51 authors for their sterling contributions to this Companion. We also wish to thank the many reviewers who provided prompt and valuable feedback on Companion chapters including: Kristoffer Ahlmstrom‐Vij, Ben Almassi, David Archard, Christian Barry, Helen Beebee, Corine Besson, David Birks, David Braddon‐Mitchell, Noel Carroll, Finn Collin, Richard Corry, Roger Crisp, Rowan Cruft, Jake Davis, Tom Douglas, James Edwards, Patrick Emerton, Sarah Fine, Helen Frowe, Heidi Grasswick, Alan Hamlin, Lisa Herzog, Nils Holtug, Jens Johansson, Klemens Kappel, Matthew Kramer, Bruce Langtry, Seth Lazar, Paisley Livingston, Steven Luper, Ron Mallon, Neil Manson, Graham Oppy, Fabienne Peter, Lucy Tatman, Jens Timmermann, Graham Twelftree, Suzanne Uniacke, Alison Wylie, and Lea Ypi.

xix

Part I

Introductory Articles

1 The Nature of Applied Philosophy KASPER LIPPERT‐RASMUSSEN

Introduction

Applied philosophy is a form of philosophy, albeit one that differs from non‐applied or, as some put it, “pure philosophy.” Presumably, the distinction between applied and pure philosophy is exhaustive and mutually exclusive, though there might be borderline cases. What distinguishes the two? Here is one way to approach the question: When we apply philosophy, we apply it to something. If I say that I am working on a piece of applied philosophy and if, in response to the question what I apply philosophy to, I say “Oh, nothing. I am just writing a piece in applied philosophy,” I show myself to be conceptually and/or grammatically confused. “To apply” is a verb that takes an object. On the assumption that applied and non‐applied philosophy are mutually exclusive, this suggests that pure philosophy has no object. But, non‐grammatically speaking, this is not so. Work in a field of philosophy outside applied philosophy, such as general meta­ physics, has an object – for example, the nature of properties. Hence, applied philosophy does not distinguish itself from pure philosophy in that the former is philosophy applied to an object, whereas pure philosophy is not. Pure philosophy being applied philosophy in this sense is not marked by the use of the term “applied.” This is because the problems it addresses are ones that are normally considered philosophical problems in a narrow sense. Metaphorically, pure philosophy is philosophy applied to itself – that is, to philosophical problems such as the fundamental nature of reality, knowledge, morality, and so on – whereas applied philosophy is philosophy applied to non‐philosophical problems broadly construed. There are many views on which problems belong to the narrow set of philosophical problems. These differences we can set aside and instead focus on the fact there are also a number of different conceptions of applied philosophy. One reason for this multiplicity

A Companion to Applied Philosophy, First Edition. Edited by Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Kimberley Brownlee, and David Coady. © 2017 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Published 2017 by John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

3 Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen is that there are different views regarding what philosophy is. For example, is it a special approach to addressing problems, or is it a set of substantive principles that one can apply outside philosophy itself (or both)? On the former view, at its core applying phi­ losophy is a matter of, say, approaching a particular question through meticulous conceptual analysis, making explicit how one’s conclusions follow from one’s premises, and so forth. On the latter view, applying philosophy is a matter of applying substantive philosophical principles. Often, doing so will consist in carefully identifying the relevant empirical facts of the matter and then feeding them into the relevant principles. For ­instance, applied ethicists who discuss capital punishment and believe that deterrence effects may justify punishment will look into whether capital punishment, as a matter of empirical fact, reduces overall crime rates. Another reason why there are different conceptions of applied philosophy is that there are different views regarding what it is to apply something. For instance, some think that the notion of application differs across different philosophical disciplines; for example, it differs across ethics and aesthetics because the latter embodies “only in a limited manner a tacit imperative toward the kind of hierarchical taxonomy that we find expressed in ethics as traditionally conceived” (see Chapter 34, Applied Aesthetics). In this chapter, I introduce seven conceptions of applied philosophy and clarify the differences between them. Along the way I will draw on examples from the contribu­ tions to this Companion. One core claim in this chapter – one that underpins the entire Companion – is that while applied ethics forms an important part of applied philosophy, applied philosophy is much more than applied ethics. This might seem odd, since applied ethics is a more established, self‐conscious applied philosophy discipline than others. However, there are historical reasons why this is so, which are compatible with the fact that any philosophical discipline – for example, epistemology or metaphysics – has an applied sub‐ or co‐discipline. This non‐applied ethics‐centered conception of applied phi­ losophy is a consequence of all of the seven conceptions of applied philosophy discussed below. The editors of this Companion hope that the Companion in its entirety consti­ tutes an even more effective argument for this broad construal of applied philosophy.

The Relevance Conception

In an article from 1970, Leslie Stevenson made a plea for applied philosophy. In his view, most of what went on in philosophy departments reflected “legitimately specialized con­ cerns” with little or no “wider relevance” outside the various subdisciplines of “pure philosophy” such as “mathematical and philosophical logic, metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of mind, philosophy of science, and most of the questions now discussed by professional philosophers about ethics, politics, and aesthetics (e.g., the validity of the fact‐value distinction)” (Stevenson 1970: 259). By “applied philosophy” he meant phi­ losophy that is “relevant to ‘the important questions of everyday life’” (Stevenson 1970: 258). These are a mix of quite different questions ranging from existential ones such as why death is bad to political questions such as what we should do about global warming. On what I shall refer to as the relevance conception of applied philosophy,

(1) Philosophy is applied if, and only if, it is relevant to important questions of everyday life.

4 The Nature of Applied Philosophy As examples of questions in applied philosophy so construed, Stevenson mentions:

rational discussion of particular controversial moral questions, such as sexual morality, the Catholic ban on contraception, the use of hallucinogenic drugs, abortion, euthanasia, eugenics, the definition of death, and many other medico‐ethical‐legal problems raised or soon to be raised by the coming “biological revolution”; also certain aspects of various difficult and social political problems, such as educational policy (comprehensive schools? religious education?), the need for public participation in planning (Do people know what they want twenty years from now, and is it identical with what they need? How can many and different pressures result in a sensible and just decision?), world economic development (Do the richer countries have a duty to help the poorer? Should the Indian peasant be forced to change his agricultural methods?); also the critical examination of various political and religious ideologies in the forms they take now (e.g., Marxism, and the various denomina­ tions of Christianity); scientific or supposedly scientific theories (e.g., Freudian psycho‐ analysis, and various sociological theories). (1970: 259)

Four thoughts spring to mind. First, this list reflects the time at which Stevenson wrote his article as well as the particular audience he addressed (cf. Singer 1993: 1). This is as it should be, if applied philosophy is “relevant to ‘the important questions of everyday life,’” and such questions, to some extent at least, vary across time and audi­ ence. Indeed, if we attend not just to actual variation but take into account possible variation, the present subdisciplines of pure philosophy would qualify as applied philos­ ophy if, say, people in their everyday lives were pure‐philosophically more inclined than almost all of us are, and were pained by unresolved questions about the nature of entail­ ment and reference. This reflects the fact that the relevance‐based distinction between pure and applied philosophy has nothing to do with the intrinsic nature of the two fields of philosophy, but turns on which questions are raised in “everyday life.” Hence, on the relevance conception there is no reason to expect that applied philosophy is any differ­ ent in terms of its methods from non‐applied philosophy. Or, at least, there is no such reason unless we have some independent grasp of which questions are the important questions of everyday life and have reason to believe that the way in which these can be answered is different from the way in which questions that are not in this way ­important can be. One aspect of the audience relativity of the notion of “important questions of everyday life” is worth emphasizing. Many subdisciplines within applied philosophy address “questions of everyday life” for members of particular professions – for example, ethics of war. Here philosophy addresses important questions bearing on the everyday professional life of members of armed forced (see Chapter 24, Collectivism and Reductivism in the Ethics of War). However, as the example shows, some questions that are important questions of everyday professional life are also important questions outside the professions, such as the rights of combatants fighting an unjust war to kill enemy combatants. Second, while most of the questions Stevenson mentions fall within the scope of applied ethics, construed broadly enough to include applied political philosophy (see Kagan 1998: 3), there are exceptions. For instance, the critical examination that Stevenson had in mind in relation to various “scientific or supposedly scientific theories” is not an ethical one, but, at least in good part, an epistemic one. Also,

5 Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen a conceptual exploration of the relation between wants and needs does not itself tell us anything about what weight should be given to people’s wants regarding their future. Third, Stevenson ties part of his plea for applied philosophy to the “coming biological revolution” that forces us to rethink a number of moral issues. Some argue that something similar can be said about other disciplines in applied philos­ ophy. For instance, David Coady contends that the “rise of new technologies, such as mobile phones and the Internet, along with the decline of older sources of information, such as newspapers and traditional reference books, have signifi­ cantly changed the way in which we acquire knowledge and justify our beliefs,” and that this motivates a similar wave of applied epistemology (see Chapter 4, Applied Epistemology). This connects with a fourth point – namely, that applied philosophy is “relevant to ‘the important questions of everyday life.’” Thus, to qualify as applied philosophy on the relevance conception, philosophy does not have to answer “the important questions of everyday life.” This is a stronger requirement. By way of illustration, accounts of what makes someone an expert on climate change do not in themselves answer the question that, currently, is an important question of everyday life: what should we do about ­climate change? But they are relevant to how we should do so – for example, because they are relevant to who can make any claim to climate expertise and, thus, to whose predictions and opinions should be trusted (see Chapter 10, Experts in the Climate Change Debate). Similarly, determining whether freedom of expression promotes truth (or other epistemic desiderata) does not answer the question of the degree to which people should enjoy freedom of expression (see Chapter 11, Freedom of Expression, Diversity, and Truth; Chapter 30, Freedom of Religion and Expression). However, to the extent that we (ought to) care about truth, it is relevant to how we should answer this question. Hence, even on the relevance conception applied ethics is not co‐extensive with applied philosophy even though, due to the nature of the important questions of everyday life, it takes up a large part of it. The relevance conception is a respectable notion of applied philosophy. Nevertheless, it involves two ways of delimiting the topic that, from a certain perspective, appear odd. First, by “important question,” Stevenson had in mind questions that were actually on people’s minds. But suppose that while a certain question is not on people’s minds, it ought to be. Suppose, for instance, that no one bothers to raise questions about discrimination against disabled people – as was the case not so long ago – and yet they ought to do so, because it disadvantages disabled people a lot and people have the facts available to them that are needed to see this as an important question. A philosophical analysis of what makes discrimination against disabled people wrong would not on Stevenson’s construal count as work in applied philosophy, though, intuitively, we would classify it as such. Second, some important questions in everyday life are answered by philosophical accounts that are not normally thought to fall under the scope of applied philosophy. Take, for instance, arguments for the unconditional wrongness of lying (e.g., Kant 1785/2002). These are normally thought to belong to moral philosophy in general. Yet, suppose the President lies to his people in the interest of their nation, or, at least, this is how he sees it, and the public is preoccupied with whether the President did wrong in

6 The Nature of Applied Philosophy lying to them. In that case such arguments are relevant to an important question of everyday life and, thus, in the present sense, one that, somewhat revisionistically, falls under the scope of applied philosophy.

The Specificity Conception

The relevance conception distinguishes applied from non‐applied philosophy on the basis of how its object relates to a particular set of concerns. However, the distinction can also be drawn in terms of how the object of applied philosophy relates to the object of non‐applied philosophy. On what I shall call the specificity conception (see Stevenson 1970: 259),

(2) Philosophy is applied if, and only if, it addresses a comparatively specific question within the branch of philosophy, e.g., metaphysics, epistemology or moral philosophy, to which it belongs.

On this conception, “What is a speech act?” is a question for pure philosophy of lan­ guage, whereas “What is a derogatory speech act?” is a question in applied philosophy (see Chapter 17, Freedom of Expression and Derogatory Words), since it is more specific than that of general speech act theory (see Chapter 13, Applied Philosophy of Language). Similarly, the question “When, if ever, is it morally permissible for unjust combatants to kill enemy soldiers?” is a question within applied philosophy, because within the branch of moral philosophy it is a comparatively specific question relative to the more general question “When, if ever, is it morally permissible to kill?” and the even more general “When are actions morally permissible?” The last question is one in pure moral philosophy on the specificity conception. In moral philosophy, it hard to think of a more general question than that one. The previous question perhaps is a borderline case and the ­definition above does not in itself tell us whether it is a question in applied philosophy. That there are borderline cases is not surprising. Generality and specificity are mat­ ters of degree (Hare 1981: 41) and for that reason, on the specificity conception, one should not expect any sharp and non‐arbitrary borders, where one leaves applied phi­ losophy and enters pure philosophy. Indeed, some philosophers have distinguished bet­ ween ethics (“Which acts are morally permissible?”), applied ethics (“When is it morally permissible to kill in war?”), and applying applied ethics (“Was the bombing of Hiroshima morally permissible?”) (Kamm 2013: 568–576). It is interesting to compare the relevance and the specificity conceptions. Generally, most of the questions, which are seen as “important questions of everyday life,” are quite specific such that the two conceptions overlap considerably, extensionally speaking. However, the two conceptions are different, and perhaps some very general questions are seen as important questions of everyday life and some very specific ques­ tions are not important questions of everyday life. By way of illustration of the latter possibility, consider the following: for Aquinas, as for his medieval contemporaries, whether charging an interest on loans could be justified at all was an important, quite specific moral question, yet for most Westerners it is no longer important, at least not in this general form.

7 Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen If we adopt the specificity conception, every philosophical discipline that contains general principles, controversial or not, has an applied subdiscipline. For instance, if there are general principles regarding the justification of beliefs these can be applied to concrete evidential situations in the same way that general principles for the moral jus­ tification of action can be applied to concrete contexts of action. Hence, recently some non‐ethicists have come to see themselves as doing a kind of applied philosophy, for example, social epistemology and social ontology. The specificity conception is naturally associated with the so‐called top‐down model of applied philosophy. On this view, we first establish various basic, non‐contingent philosophical principles. Once they have been secured, we explore their implications given certain additional and non‐philosophical, empirical assumptions. Doing so enables us to say something about concrete and very specific issues. Few, if any applied philosophers, work in a top‐down fashion (Beauchamp 2003: 8; Haldane 2009: 11; Hansson 2008: 480–481), though some think that non‐applied philosophy has a certain priority over applied philosophy. For instance, Peter Singer, in his book Practical Ethics, writes: “In order to have a useful discussion within ethics, it is necessary to say a little about ethics, so that we have a clear understanding of what we are doing when we discuss ethical questions” (Singer 1993: 1). Presumably, Singer would not say that the reverse is the case. Against such views, many would point to the fact that basic principles are revised, or accepted in part on the basis of their implications given certain additional empirical assumptions. Indeed, more general principles are often under‐described, and paying close attention to the complexities of concrete cases is a way of becoming clearer about the general principles, which, on reflection, one is committed to (see Archard 2009: 240). This is as it should be, given that we endorse a coherentist model of justification where to be justified in endorsing more general principles these must cohere with our considered beliefs about specific cases. This may not show that we should reject the specificity conception of applied philosophy – after all, unlike coherentism it is not explicitly formulated as a doctrine about justification – but, in the light of reflective equilibrium, the top‐down model looks peculiar (see Chapter 18, Applied Moral Philosophy). To determine which non‐specific principles are justified, we must address very specific questions in philosophy also.

The Practical Conception

The specificity conception is not the only conception of applied philosophy that locates its distinctive features in its object. On what I shall refer to as the practical conception,

(3) Philosophy is applied if, and only if, it justifies an answer to comparatively specific ­questions within its relevant branch of philosophy about what we ought to do.

The practical questions to be answered must be relatively specific because otherwise applied philosophy becomes indistinguishable from practical philosophy in general and, thus, is to be contrasted with theoretical philosophy – for example, metaphysics and logic – not non‐applied philosophy. Even so restricted, the specificity and the practical

8 The Nature of Applied Philosophy conceptions differ, since some specific questions are not questions about what we ought to do. For instance, the question about whether we have any reason to think that Jesus performed the miracle of feeding the multitude with five loaves of bread and two fish is much more specific than the question of whether we have reason to accept the existence of miracles and is not a question about what we ought to do (see Chapter 39, Thinking about Reported Miracles). The practical conception is also different from the relevance conception because some practical questions in the present sense are relatively unimportant and some non‐practical questions – for example. “What is bad about dying?” – are highly ­relevant, specific questions in everyday life. Also, on the practical conception applied philosophy seeks not just to be relevant to practical questions, but, more ambitiously, to answer them. The practical conception of applied philosophy is the one that comes closest to mak­ ing applied philosophy roughly equivalent to applied ethics. Given such overlap, and given skepticism about the truth or justifiability of moral judgments – or normative judgments in general – a skeptical stance toward the rational credentials of applied ­philosophy follows. For this reason among others, it is worthwhile pointing out that even on the practical conception there are noticeable differences between applied philosophy and applied ethics. First, some questions in applied ethics are not questions about what we ought to do. For instance, this is true of axiological questions in population ethics. Similarly, many applied ethics issues are resolved on the basis of applying other philosophical dis­ ciplines to the concrete issues at hand. For instance, in the applied ethics literature on abortion much of the discussion concerns when human beings or persons begin to exist. To answer such questions, philosophers turn to metaphysics and apply meta­ physical principles about division and persistence over time to facts about human ­procreation – as, for example, when they appeal to the empirical phenomenon of mono­ zygotic twinning to argue that even if you accept the idea that persons have Cartesian souls, we do not start to exist at the time of conception rather than at the onset of con­ sciousness (see McMahan 2003: 18–19). Second, some normative questions are not ethical ­questions. Questions about which strategies we can adopt to form less biased beliefs in the interest of having more true beliefs and fewer false ones are not questions for applied ethics. What gave applied philosophy its big boost in the 1970s was an attempt to make ­philosophy practical in order to answer many of the pressing moral questions of those days (Beauchamp 2003: 1–2; Lafollette 2003: 2) – some of which, for example, global justice, are still with us and, regrettably, no less in need of an answer – and this is prob­ ably what partly explains that, despite the two observations just made, some identify applied philosophy with applied ethics.

The Activist Conception

Many philosophers who work in applied philosophy are not satisfied with simply answering the question of what we ought to do. Rather, they want, through their engagement with philosophy, to causally affect the world in a certain way (see Archard

9 Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen 2009: 238; Gaus 2005: 65; Singer 1975). Nancy Daukas, in her chapter on feminist epistemology (Chapter 5), writes: “The many, diverse areas of feminist philosophy are united by a commitment to use philosophical reflection to improve the conditions of our lives insofar as they are shaped by social power. That is, feminist philosophy is defined by its liberatory goals, and it is primarily for that reason that it may be considered ‘applied philosophy.” She continues: “The expression ‘feminist epistemology’ refers not to a particular epistemological doctrine or theory, but to doing epistemology as a feminist, that is, to pursuing epistemological work in the service of liberatory socio‐political objectives.” On what I shall call the activist conception,

(4) Philosophy is applied if, and only if, it is motivated by an ambition of having a certain causal effect on the world.

Here “certain effect” does a lot of work. Presumably, most philosophers – even those working within pure philosophy – want to bring about some causal effect on the world through their work. For instance, they want to change the views of other philosophers’ beliefs about the topic on which they work or, in less admirable cases, to promote their careers. However, these are not the concerns I have in mind. Rather, the motivation is of a kind that characterizes someone who is politically engaged, broadly construed, or who is an educator (Brownlee 2009; Kitcher 2011: 259; Stevenson 1970: 265) and wants to affect the world through his or her philosophical engagement. While many philosophers who work in non‐applied philosophy have an ambition to change the world for the better, the distinction between philosophers who have and phi­ losophers who do not have this ambition does not align well with the distinction bet­ ween applied and non‐applied philosophy. First, there are examples of philosophers who have done work that is thought of by most as pure philosophy and yet might have been motivated by a concern to change the world. For instance, it is reasonable to conjecture that Karl Popper’s work on falsifiability (Popper 1963/2007: 45) and on the impossi­ bility of making large‐scale predictions about the course of history (Popper 1957/2002) in part was motivated by a desire to combat totalitarian ideologies in general and Marxism in particular. And, speaking of which, in his eleventh thesis on Feuerbach, Marx – not seen by many as someone doing applied philosophy whether rightly so or not – famously complained that so far philosophers had only interpreted the world, whereas the point was to change it (Marx 1998). Second, some academic work in applied philosophy is done in a bread‐and‐butter‐, 9‐to‐5 way, reflecting something that comes close to an indifference to what happens in (most of) the world. There probably is an established use of the term “applied philosophy” where the term is tied to having an activist motivation. However, as we have seen, it misclassifies certain cases as applied and others as non‐applied – at least, when these cases are classified by the nature of their topics. Still, this is as it should be and being clear about what we mean by “applied philosophy” steers us clear of any problems. Should we expect activist applied philosophy to be different from pure philosophy in terms of its methods? Undoubtedly, activism often leads applied philosophers to emphasize different things: for example, as Daukas points out, the fact that feminist epistemology focuses on various mechanisms of social power and oppression means that feminist epistemologies have a “methodological commitment to bring multiple

10 The Nature of Applied Philosophy ­perspectives into critical yet collaborative conversation, to promote pluralism, to develop methods for productive ‘listening across differences’, and to create opportunities for the perspectives of the marginalized to be developed and heard.” Similarly, feminist episte­ mologists might be more alert to identifying mechanisms of social power that underlies the social production of beliefs than other epistemologists might be. Still others might think that there is no necessity about non‐applied philosophy not being open to multiple perspectives, and indeed that such openness, while needed, does not reflect any novel methodological stance. More radically, some caution that when philosophers are concerned, as they should be, “with the policy consequences of what they do” – a concern that will sometimes favor unsound arguments – their primary commitment will no longer be “knowledge and truth” (Brock 1987: 787). Also, philosophy that “is really practical” and has as a goal “to improve behavior or at least to reduce the incidence of very bad behavior” will tend to focus on issues other than those that non‐practical philosophy attends to: for example, rather than focusing on intellectually challenging cases, it will explore how, through the inculcation of a critical ethics of belief, we can avoid the subversion of morality through false beliefs (Buchanan 2009).

The Methodology Conception

On the specificity conception of applied philosophy the distinctive nature of applied ­philosophy lies in the questions it asks. However, there is a different way of conceiving applied philosophy, which ties it not to particular questions or substantive theories, but to certain methods – for example, the systematic use of thought experiments, making presuppositions explicit, conceptual analysis, and rigorous analysis of argumentation. On what I shall call the methodology conception,

(5) Philosophy is applied if, and only if, it involves the use of specifically philosophical methods to explore issues outside the narrow set of philosophical problems.

Unlike the specificity conception, the methodology conception allows that a piece of applied philosophy addresses a topic that, narrowly construed, does not form a philosophical question. Consider, for instance, the gatecrashers’ paradox (see Enoch, Spectre, and Fisher 2012). There is a baseball match and 10,000 people attend. In the first case, everyone except for 10 spectators gatecrashed. John is charged with gate­ crashing. There is no specific evidence that he did so, but since he certainly attended the match there is a very high probability that he gatecrashed. In the second case, John is under the same charge. This time there is no information about how many people gate­ crashed, but an eyewitness reports that he saw John gatecrash and the evidence conclu­ sively shows that the eyewitness is very reliable. If he reports that he saw someone gatecrash he will make an error only once every 100 times. The paradox is this: courts are unlikely to convict John on the basis of the statistical evidence in the former case, but likely to do so in the latter, despite the fact that the evidence in the former case is more accurate than in the latter and despite the fact that, ultimately, evidence based on eyewitness reports rests on statistics too, to wit, about the reliability of the relevant

11 Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen eyewitness reports. Hence: is there any good reason for treating statistical and ­eyewitness reports‐based evidence differently? This question is not a typical philosophical question like “Do we have free will?” or “What is an explanation?” Yet, work that tries to answer this question intuitively belongs to applied philosophy, and at least part of the reason this is so is that, methodologically speaking, it is quite similar to work that addresses standard philosophical questions. The gatecrashers’ paradox also illustrates a difference between the methodology and the relevance conceptions of applied philosophy. For, independently of academic work on the gatecrashers’ paradox, few people think that it is an important question of everyday life, which sort of statistical evidence courts can rely on. However, it might become an important topic as a result of people writing on it in applied philosophy. An illustration of this is Singer’s (1975) work on animal ethics. This book is perhaps an actual example of how a question has become an important question in everyday life partly as a result of work in applied philosophy. As he writes in one of the first lines in the book: “‘Animal liberation’ may sound more like a parody of other liberation ­movements than a serious objective” (Singer 1975: 1). Not so much anymore! Note, finally, that, on the methodology conception, what we apply when we apply philosophy is something quite different from what it is naturally taken to be that we apply when, on the specificity conception, we apply philosophy to something outside philosophy. On the latter conception, it is natural to assume that what we apply are substantive principles – for example, general moral principles or principles of ­rationality – that have been shown to be justified within pure philosophy. However, on the methodology conception what we apply is philosophical methods of analysis. Such application might modestly aim at no more than clarifying concepts and presupposi­ tions behind a certain practice or set of beliefs without aiming to assess these aims or presuppositions or assess them only conditionally, that is, relative to assumptions that are not themselves posited, but might be accepted by the addressee of applied philosophy.

The Empirical Facts Conception

A sixth conception of applied philosophy comes out in Stevenson’s thought that applied philosophy has an “essentially interdisciplinary nature” (Stevenson 1970: 263; see Chapter 41, Ancient Applied Philosophy). On this conception pure philosophy is largely an a priori discipline that uncovers conceptual truths or truths discoverable through pure reason. However, applied philosophy draws on the results of a posteriori empirical sciences as well as empirical evidence in general. On this conception, which I coin the empirical facts conception,

(6) Philosophy is applied if, and only if, it is significantly informed by empirical evidence – in particular, that provided by empirical sciences.

While most philosophy that qualifies as applied on this conception will also do so on the methodological conception (if it did not use the methods of philosophy, how could it qualify as applied philosophy?), as the gatecrashers’ paradox indicates it is quite possible

12 The Nature of Applied Philosophy for philosophy to qualify as applied on the methodological conception, but not on the empirical facts conception. In this Companion, the empirical facts conception is illustrated by the contribution on neuroscience and criminal justice, which emphasizes that it is located at the “intersection between neuroscience and law” (see Chapter 26, Neuroethics and Criminal Justice; Chapter 40, Religion and Neuroscience). A more problematic instance of applied philosophy on the present conception is an influential argument for the falsity of moral realism. According to this argument – Mackie’s argument from relativity – the best explanation of empirical variation of moral codes across time and place is that there are no moral facts (Mackie 1977: 36). Unless “informed by empirical evidence” is understood in a narrow sense, this argument is an argument in applied philosophy, though, normally, it is not thought of as such. And if it is narrowly construed to avoid this taxonomical infelicity, to some extent the distinction between pure and applied philosophy becomes a matter of degree that should not be expected to signal any significant difference in method and so on. Some naturalistically minded philosophers will claim that all philosophy, or at least all worthwhile philosophy, is applied in this sense. For instance, some think that even the deepest questions about, say, the nature of our privileged access to the contents of our own minds, cannot be answered independently of the results of the empirical find­ ings of neuroscience among other things. As Neil Levy (Chapter 19, Neuroethics and Responsibility) puts it: “the sciences of the mind illuminate traditional philosophical questions, concerning, say, the nature of knowledge or the existence of free will.” Similarly, philosophers much attuned to the experimental turn in philosophy insist that good philosophy is applied philosophy in this sense. The empirical facts conception is likely to be associated with the specificity concep­ tion. However, the two are different – not simply because, as just mentioned, some nat­ uralistically minded philosophers think that even the most general questions in philosophy can only be fruitfully explored in empirically informed ways, but also because some (non‐naturalistically inclined) philosophers think that some specific questions (“Is capital punishment morally justified?”) can be answered without paying any attention to empirical facts of the matter. One particular way in which applied philosophy is significantly informed by the results of empirical sciences comes out in the contrast between ideal and non‐ideal theory. This distinction applies to normative disciplines and runs as follows: ideal theory explores how agents ought to act under ideal circumstances and what these circum­ stances are in the first place. Accounts of when circumstances are ideal differ, but only ideal circumstances are such that reasoning agents are not prone to reason badly in ways which normal reasoning agents do – for instance, in their assessment of probabil­ ities ideal reasoning agents do not disregard base rates (e.g., if a certain test for a med­ ical condition has a 10% likelihood of false positives and similarly so for false negatives and the medical condition is very rare, actual agents will overestimate the probability that they have the medical condition if their test is positive, ignoring that the great majority of positive tests are false positives) – and such that acting agents are assumed to be motivated to act as they ought to act and do so successfully. Non‐ideal theory notes that, realistically, certain reasoning strategies, given the psychology of actual agents, are intractable and, thus, propose reasoning strategies that will enable them to improve their reasoning, for instance, in the case at hand by reasoning in terms of frequencies

13 Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen rather than probabilities (Bishop and Trout 2005: 141). Similarly, non‐ideal moral theory asks how we should act in light of the deficiencies of agents, which are empiri­ cally well established. This is why non‐ideal theory (see Chapter 7, Information Markets; Chapter 8, Epistemology for (Real) People; Chapter 9, Are Conspiracy Theorists Epistemically Vicious?; Chapter 20, Non‐Ideal Theory; Chapter 29, Benefiting from Wrongdoing) is often seen as applied philosophy. It is worth noting, however, that non‐ideal theory could be discussed in a way that would make it less likely to be seen as applied. If instead of focusing on how we actually fall short of what is ideal, non‐ideal theory might focus on how we could fall short of what is ideal – for example, non‐ideal, moral theory was just as interested in how we ought to act given a tendency to give too little weight to our own interests as in how we ought to act given a tendency to give too much weight to our self‐interest – presumably, non‐ideal theory would be less applied than is actually the case. Another way in which philosophy is empirically informed is through its aim to uncover and possibly assess philosophical assumptions made in non‐philosophical ­contexts (see Boghossian 2006; Keeley 1999). To take an example by Richard Corry (Chapter 33, Did Climate Change Cause That?): philosophers might explore the debate on climate change and the causation of particular extreme weather conditions trying to establish “the concept of causation in play here: what concept of causation is being employed? Is the debate being confused by the use of more than one concept of causa­ tion? Which concept of causation is appropriate in this discussion?” In doing so, philos­ ophers may not seek to cast light on the philosophical discussion of causation on the basis of empirical sciences (or, more broadly, public and quasi‐public debates) but rather to cast light on these debates drawing on insights from pure philosophy. This can be ­beneficial, for example, by showing that what appears to participants to be a disagree­ ment really amounts to different uses of the term “cause.” To clarify non‐philosophical debates by making philosophical assumptions underpinning those debates explicit is to do empirically informed applied philosophy even if the aim is not so much to clarify philosophical questions as to oppose non‐philosophical ones. Still, it counts as a useful contribution of applied philosophy. On most of the conceptions of applied philosophy – the activist conception being a possible exception – that I have so far introduced, there is no reason that applied and non‐applied philosophy should differ in terms of their methods. However, on the empirical facts conception applied philosophy is empirically informed and empirical studies bring with them a methodology that is different from the one normally, ­justifiably or not, applied in pure philosophy, which on the present conception means philosophy that is not significantly informed by the results of the empirical sciences.

The Audience Conception

A seventh conception of applied philosophy is that what distinguishes it from pure ­philosophy is that it addresses an audience of non‐philosophers. So, on the audience conception,

(7) Philosophy is applied if, and only if, its intended audience is non‐philosophers.

14 The Nature of Applied Philosophy Stevenson thought applied philosophy addressed an audience of non‐philosophers and, in part, that reflects the fact that, unlike now, in 1970 there were not that many applied philosophers around to address. However, I suspect that this conception, while some­ times used, is not very helpful. If a philosopher writes a book on general issues in philosophical logic for the benefit of an audience of non‐philosophers, whom she thinks would like to acquire some acquaintance with the topic, the book would qualify as applied philosophy on the present conception despite the fact that its topic is not usually seen as one that falls within applied philosophy and, in all likelihood, would not qualify as such on any of the other conceptions above. It is better to distinguish between ­popularized (whether applied or non‐applied) philosophy, on the one hand, and non‐ popularized philosophy, on the other hand. This being said, the fact that a piece of philosophy is written for non‐philosophers might be a reasonably good indicator of its being a piece of applied philosophy – for example, because one motivation for writing for a general audience is the ambition to have a “practical impact,” say, on the way in which animals are treated in agriculture or on the legality of assisted suicide. However, the fact that a piece of philosophy is written for philosophers is not a good indicator of being a piece of pure philosophy (in a pre‐ theoretical notion of that term), since in these golden days of applied philosophy most of it is written for an audience of philosophers.

Conclusion

I have specified all of the seven conceptions above in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions. This makes the different conceptions incompatible with one another. To avoid this, they could be stated in terms of sufficient conditions only. Or rather than all conditions being conditions of philosophy being applied, they could be stated as condi­ tions for philosophy being a certain sort of applied philosophy. Or the seven conditions could be thought to form a point score system such that the more conditions are satis­ fied the stronger the case is for classifying the relevance piece of philosophy as being applied. In any case, what I have written is compatible with a contribution in philos­ ophy being applied philosophy in more than one way. Indeed, often this is the case. Many chapters in this Companion qualify as pieces of applied philosophy in several ways. None of the chapters are not applied philosophy in any of the senses that I have identified. The fact that philosophy can count as “applied” in different senses has some ­implications for questions about its method, focus topic‐wise, and its value, since, as I have hinted, perhaps on some conceptions of applied philosophy it is unlikely to differ in principle in these respects from non‐applied philosophy, whereas on other concep­ tions they are likely to differ. To round off this discussion, it is worth repeating a core claim in this chapter – one that underpins the Companion as such – namely, that applied philosophy is much broader than applied ethics. Applied ethics might enjoy a more secure and established existence as a philosophical subdiscipline than, say, applied epistemology or applied metaphysics. But there is every reason why some or all other fields of philosophy should have applied parts (but see Chapter 34, Applied Aesthetics). Even on the conception that

15 Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen comes closest to making applied philosophy co‐extensional with applied ethics – the practical conception – there are parts of applied philosophy that are not subdisciplines in ethics – for example, applied epistemology – and ethical questions that are normally conceived as questions in applied ethics and yet are not questions about what we should do – for example, axiology in population ethics. Some might worry that applied ­philosophy is simply a very broad category that not much interesting can be said about. Still, presumably, it remains narrower than philosophy in general, so people who raise this worry should consider whether they have the same worry regarding philosophy as such.

Acknowledgments

My thanks are due to David Coady, Kimberley Brownlee, and to an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments.

References

Archard, D. 2009. “Applying Philosophy: A Reply to O’Neill.” Journal of Applied Philosophy 26(3): 238–244. Beauchamp, T.L. 2003. “The Nature of Applied Ethics.” In A Companion to Applied Ethics, edited by R.G. Frey and C.H. Wellman. Malden, MA: Blackwell. Bishop, M.A. and Trout, J.D. 2005. Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgement. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Boghossian, P. 2006. Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism. New York: Oxford University Press. Brock, D.W. 1987. “Truth or Consequences: The Role of Philosophers in Policy‐Making.” Ethics 97: 786–791. Brownlee, K. 2009. “Normative Principles and Practical Ethics: A Response to O’Neill.” Journal of Applied Philosophy 26(3): 231–237. Buchanan, A. 2009. “Philosophy and Public Policy: A Role for Social Moral Epistemology.” Journal of Applied Philosophy 26(3): 276–290. Enoch, D., Spectre, L., and Fisher, T. 2012. “Statistical Evidence, Sensitivity, and the Legal Value of Knowledge.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 40(3): 197–224. Gaus, G. 2005. “Should Philosophers Apply Ethics?” Think 3(9): 63–67. Haldane, J. 2009. Practical Philosophy. Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic. Hansson, S.O. 2008. “Philosophy and Other Disciplines.” Metaphilosophy 39(4–5): 472–483. Hare, R. 1981. Moral Thinking. Oxford: Clarendon. Kagan, S. 1998. Normative Ethics. Boulder, CO: Westview. Kamm, F.M. 2013. Bioethical Prescriptions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kant, I. 1785/2002. Ground for the Metaphysics of Morals. Edited and translated by A. Wood. New York: Yale University Press. Keeley, B.L. 1999. “Of Conspiracy Theories.” Journal of Philosophy 96: 109–126. Kitcher, P. 2011. “Philosophy Inside Out.” Metaphilosophy 42(3): 248–260. LaFollette, H. (ed.). 2003. The Oxford Handbook of Practical Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mackie, J.L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. New York: Penguin.

16 The Nature of Applied Philosophy Marx, K. 1998. The German Ideology: Including Theses on Feuerbach and an Introduction to the Critique of Political Economy. New York: Prometheus Books. McMahan, J. 2003. The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Popper, K. 1957/2002. The Poverty of Historicism. London: Routledge. Popper, K. 1963/2007. Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge. Singer, P. 1975. Animal Liberation. New York: HarperCollins. Singer, P. 1993. Practical Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Stevenson, L. 1970. “Applied Philosophy.” Metaphilosophy 1(3): 258–267.

Further Reading

Coady, D. 2006. Conspiracy Theories: The Philosophical Debate. Farnham, UK: Ashgate. Coady, D. 2012. What to Believe Now: Applying Epistemology to Contemporary Issues. Oxford: Wiley‐Blackwell. Fricker, M. 2007. Epistemic Injustice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Goldman, A.I. 1999. Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hume, D. 1739–1740/1999. An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, Part II, §10. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kamm, F.M. 2013. Bioethical Prescriptions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. McMahan, J. 2009. Killing in War. Oxford: Clarendon. Pogge, T. 2008. World Poverty and Human Rights, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Polity. Searle, J.R. 1995. The Construction of Social Reality. London: Penguin. Wood, A.W. 1999. Kant’s Ethical Thought, Part II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

17 2 The Methodology of Applied Philosophy DAVID ARCHARD

Introduction: What Is Applied Philosophy?

Applied philosophy is applied philosophy. To that extent we might assume that its ­methodology would share something at least with the subject as a whole. However, what exactly it is to do philosophy – by contradistinction from any other academic ­subject – is not entirely uncontroversial. We might argue that philosophy is different from the physical sciences in not having an experimental method or in not seeking to uncover facts about our world. Yet, that is true of some other humanities disciplines. Moreover, what are often celebrated as the virtues of philosophical method – conceptual clarity, the use of robust argumentation, and the careful evaluation of competing claims – need not successfully distinguish philosophy from many other academic subjects. We should immediately add that these are alleged to be the virtues of mainstream Anglo‐American philosophy. It is often further asserted that the contrary vices of some European, or Continental, philosophy are obfuscation and rhetoric. In consequence, it seems easier to define the various subdisciplines of philosophy, such as metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and logic; or at least to indicate their different scope and content. So what is it, in relation to these forms of philosophy, to do applied philosophy? An answer to this requires attention in the first instance to the prior question of definition: What exactly is applied philosophy? Kasper Lippert‐Rasmussen (Chapter 1, The Nature of Applied Philosophy) offers seven conceptions of applied philosophy, none of which, as he shows, seems satisfac- tory, at least when each is taken as providing a necessary and sufficient condition of the subject. Rather than enter into a discussion of the conceptions offered by Lippert‐ Rasmussen, it is more instructive to point to a general contrast and to identify a desideratum.

A Companion to Applied Philosophy, First Edition. Edited by Kasper Lippert‐Rasmussen, Kimberley Brownlee, and David Coady. © 2017 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Published 2017 by John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

18