Lecture 8 (Notes) 1 Introduction 2 the Class IP: Interactive Proofs with a Probabilistic Verifier
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
NP-Completeness: Reductions Tue, Nov 21, 2017
CMSC 451 Dave Mount CMSC 451: Lecture 19 NP-Completeness: Reductions Tue, Nov 21, 2017 Reading: Chapt. 8 in KT and Chapt. 8 in DPV. Some of the reductions discussed here are not in either text. Recap: We have introduced a number of concepts on the way to defining NP-completeness: Decision Problems/Language recognition: are problems for which the answer is either yes or no. These can also be thought of as language recognition problems, assuming that the input has been encoded as a string. For example: HC = fG j G has a Hamiltonian cycleg MST = f(G; c) j G has a MST of cost at most cg: P: is the class of all decision problems which can be solved in polynomial time. While MST 2 P, we do not know whether HC 2 P (but we suspect not). Certificate: is a piece of evidence that allows us to verify in polynomial time that a string is in a given language. For example, the language HC above, a certificate could be a sequence of vertices along the cycle. (If the string is not in the language, the certificate can be anything.) NP: is defined to be the class of all languages that can be verified in polynomial time. (Formally, it stands for Nondeterministic Polynomial time.) Clearly, P ⊆ NP. It is widely believed that P 6= NP. To define NP-completeness, we need to introduce the concept of a reduction. Reductions: The class of NP-complete problems consists of a set of decision problems (languages) (a subset of the class NP) that no one knows how to solve efficiently, but if there were a polynomial time solution for even a single NP-complete problem, then every problem in NP would be solvable in polynomial time. -
Computational Complexity: a Modern Approach
i Computational Complexity: A Modern Approach Draft of a book: Dated January 2007 Comments welcome! Sanjeev Arora and Boaz Barak Princeton University [email protected] Not to be reproduced or distributed without the authors’ permission This is an Internet draft. Some chapters are more finished than others. References and attributions are very preliminary and we apologize in advance for any omissions (but hope you will nevertheless point them out to us). Please send us bugs, typos, missing references or general comments to [email protected] — Thank You!! DRAFT ii DRAFT Chapter 9 Complexity of counting “It is an empirical fact that for many combinatorial problems the detection of the existence of a solution is easy, yet no computationally efficient method is known for counting their number.... for a variety of problems this phenomenon can be explained.” L. Valiant 1979 The class NP captures the difficulty of finding certificates. However, in many contexts, one is interested not just in a single certificate, but actually counting the number of certificates. This chapter studies #P, (pronounced “sharp p”), a complexity class that captures this notion. Counting problems arise in diverse fields, often in situations having to do with estimations of probability. Examples include statistical estimation, statistical physics, network design, and more. Counting problems are also studied in a field of mathematics called enumerative combinatorics, which tries to obtain closed-form mathematical expressions for counting problems. To give an example, in the 19th century Kirchoff showed how to count the number of spanning trees in a graph using a simple determinant computation. Results in this chapter will show that for many natural counting problems, such efficiently computable expressions are unlikely to exist. -
Notes on Space Complexity of Integration of Computable Real
Notes on space complexity of integration of computable real functions in Ko–Friedman model Sergey V. Yakhontov Abstract x In the present paper it is shown that real function g(x)= 0 f(t)dt is a linear-space computable real function on interval [0, 1] if f is a linear-space computable C2[0, 1] real function on interval R [0, 1], and this result does not depend on any open question in the computational complexity theory. The time complexity of computable real functions and integration of computable real functions is considered in the context of Ko–Friedman model which is based on the notion of Cauchy functions computable by Turing machines. 1 2 In addition, a real computable function f is given such that 0 f ∈ FDSPACE(n )C[a,b] but 1 f∈ / FP if FP 6= #P. 0 C[a,b] R RKeywords: Computable real functions, Cauchy function representation, polynomial-time com- putable real functions, linear-space computable real functions, C2[0, 1] real functions, integration of computable real functions. Contents 1 Introduction 1 1.1 CF computablerealnumbersandfunctions . ...... 2 1.2 Integration of FP computablerealfunctions. 2 2 Upper bound of the time complexity of integration 3 2 3 Function from FDSPACE(n )C[a,b] that not in FPC[a,b] if FP 6= #P 4 4 Conclusion 4 arXiv:1408.2364v3 [cs.CC] 17 Nov 2014 1 Introduction In the present paper, we consider computable real numbers and functions that are represented by Cauchy functions computable by Turing machines [1]. Main results regarding computable real numbers and functions can be found in [1–4]; main results regarding computational complexity of computations on Turing machines can be found in [5]. -
Interactive Proofs 1 1 Pspace ⊆ IP
CS294: Probabilistically Checkable and Interactive Proofs January 24, 2017 Interactive Proofs 1 Instructor: Alessandro Chiesa & Igor Shinkar Scribe: Mariel Supina 1 Pspace ⊆ IP The first proof that Pspace ⊆ IP is due to Shamir, and a simplified proof was given by Shen. These notes discuss the simplified version in [She92], though most of the ideas are the same as those in [Sha92]. Notes by Katz also served as a reference [Kat11]. Theorem 1 ([Sha92]) Pspace ⊆ IP. To show the inclusion of Pspace in IP, we need to begin with a Pspace-complete language. 1.1 True Quantified Boolean Formulas (tqbf) Definition 2 A quantified boolean formula (QBF) is an expression of the form 8x19x28x3 ::: 9xnφ(x1; : : : ; xn); (1) where φ is a boolean formula on n variables. Note that since each variable in a QBF is quantified, a QBF is either true or false. Definition 3 tqbf is the language of all boolean formulas φ such that if φ is a formula on n variables, then the corresponding QBF (1) is true. Fact 4 tqbf is Pspace-complete (see section 2 for a proof). Hence to show that Pspace ⊆ IP, it suffices to show that tqbf 2 IP. Claim 5 tqbf 2 IP. In order prove claim 5, we will need to present a complete and sound interactive protocol that decides whether a given QBF is true. In the sum-check protocol we used an arithmetization of a 3-CNF boolean formula. Likewise, here we will need a way to arithmetize a QBF. 1.2 Arithmetization of a QBF We begin with a boolean formula φ, and we let n be the number of variables and m the number of clauses of φ. -
Interactive Proofs for Quantum Computations
Innovations in Computer Science 2010 Interactive Proofs For Quantum Computations Dorit Aharonov Michael Ben-Or Elad Eban School of Computer Science, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Israel [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Abstract: The widely held belief that BQP strictly contains BPP raises fundamental questions: Upcoming generations of quantum computers might already be too large to be simulated classically. Is it possible to experimentally test that these systems perform as they should, if we cannot efficiently compute predictions for their behavior? Vazirani has asked [21]: If computing predictions for Quantum Mechanics requires exponential resources, is Quantum Mechanics a falsifiable theory? In cryptographic settings, an untrusted future company wants to sell a quantum computer or perform a delegated quantum computation. Can the customer be convinced of correctness without the ability to compare results to predictions? To provide answers to these questions, we define Quantum Prover Interactive Proofs (QPIP). Whereas in standard Interactive Proofs [13] the prover is computationally unbounded, here our prover is in BQP, representing a quantum computer. The verifier models our current computational capabilities: it is a BPP machine, with access to few qubits. Our main theorem can be roughly stated as: ”Any language in BQP has a QPIP, and moreover, a fault tolerant one” (providing a partial answer to a challenge posted in [1]). We provide two proofs. The simpler one uses a new (possibly of independent interest) quantum authentication scheme (QAS) based on random Clifford elements. This QPIP however, is not fault tolerant. Our second protocol uses polynomial codes QAS due to Ben-Or, Cr´epeau, Gottesman, Hassidim, and Smith [8], combined with quantum fault tolerance and secure multiparty quantum computation techniques. -
Distribution of Units of Real Quadratic Number Fields
Y.-M. J. Chen, Y. Kitaoka and J. Yu Nagoya Math. J. Vol. 158 (2000), 167{184 DISTRIBUTION OF UNITS OF REAL QUADRATIC NUMBER FIELDS YEN-MEI J. CHEN, YOSHIYUKI KITAOKA and JING YU1 Dedicated to the seventieth birthday of Professor Tomio Kubota Abstract. Let k be a real quadratic field and k, E the ring of integers and the group of units in k. Denoting by E( ¡ ) the subgroup represented by E of × ¡ ¡ ( k= ¡ ) for a prime ideal , we show that prime ideals for which the order of E( ¡ ) is theoretically maximal have a positive density under the Generalized Riemann Hypothesis. 1. Statement of the result x Let k be a real quadratic number field with discriminant D0 and fun- damental unit (> 1), and let ok and E be the ring of integers in k and the set of units in k, respectively. For a prime ideal p of k we denote by E(p) the subgroup of the unit group (ok=p)× of the residue class group modulo p con- sisting of classes represented by elements of E and set Ip := [(ok=p)× : E(p)], where p is the rational prime lying below p. It is obvious that Ip is inde- pendent of the choice of prime ideals lying above p. Set 1; if p is decomposable or ramified in k, ` := 8p 1; if p remains prime in k and N () = 1, p − k=Q <(p 1)=2; if p remains prime in k and N () = 1, − k=Q − : where Nk=Q stands for the norm from k to the rational number field Q. -
Glossary of Complexity Classes
App endix A Glossary of Complexity Classes Summary This glossary includes selfcontained denitions of most complexity classes mentioned in the b o ok Needless to say the glossary oers a very minimal discussion of these classes and the reader is re ferred to the main text for further discussion The items are organized by topics rather than by alphab etic order Sp ecically the glossary is partitioned into two parts dealing separately with complexity classes that are dened in terms of algorithms and their resources ie time and space complexity of Turing machines and complexity classes de ned in terms of nonuniform circuits and referring to their size and depth The algorithmic classes include timecomplexity based classes such as P NP coNP BPP RP coRP PH E EXP and NEXP and the space complexity classes L NL RL and P S P AC E The non k uniform classes include the circuit classes P p oly as well as NC and k AC Denitions and basic results regarding many other complexity classes are available at the constantly evolving Complexity Zoo A Preliminaries Complexity classes are sets of computational problems where each class contains problems that can b e solved with sp ecic computational resources To dene a complexity class one sp ecies a mo del of computation a complexity measure like time or space which is always measured as a function of the input length and a b ound on the complexity of problems in the class We follow the tradition of fo cusing on decision problems but refer to these problems using the terminology of promise problems -
User's Guide for Complexity: a LATEX Package, Version 0.80
User’s Guide for complexity: a LATEX package, Version 0.80 Chris Bourke April 12, 2007 Contents 1 Introduction 2 1.1 What is complexity? ......................... 2 1.2 Why a complexity package? ..................... 2 2 Installation 2 3 Package Options 3 3.1 Mode Options .............................. 3 3.2 Font Options .............................. 4 3.2.1 The small Option ....................... 4 4 Using the Package 6 4.1 Overridden Commands ......................... 6 4.2 Special Commands ........................... 6 4.3 Function Commands .......................... 6 4.4 Language Commands .......................... 7 4.5 Complete List of Class Commands .................. 8 5 Customization 15 5.1 Class Commands ............................ 15 1 5.2 Language Commands .......................... 16 5.3 Function Commands .......................... 17 6 Extended Example 17 7 Feedback 18 7.1 Acknowledgements ........................... 19 1 Introduction 1.1 What is complexity? complexity is a LATEX package that typesets computational complexity classes such as P (deterministic polynomial time) and NP (nondeterministic polynomial time) as well as sets (languages) such as SAT (satisfiability). In all, over 350 commands are defined for helping you to typeset Computational Complexity con- structs. 1.2 Why a complexity package? A better question is why not? Complexity theory is a more recent, though mature area of Theoretical Computer Science. Each researcher seems to have his or her own preferences as to how to typeset Complexity Classes and has built up their own personal LATEX commands file. This can be frustrating, to say the least, when it comes to collaborations or when one has to go through an entire series of files changing commands for compatibility or to get exactly the look they want (or what may be required). -
A Short History of Computational Complexity
The Computational Complexity Column by Lance FORTNOW NEC Laboratories America 4 Independence Way, Princeton, NJ 08540, USA [email protected] http://www.neci.nj.nec.com/homepages/fortnow/beatcs Every third year the Conference on Computational Complexity is held in Europe and this summer the University of Aarhus (Denmark) will host the meeting July 7-10. More details at the conference web page http://www.computationalcomplexity.org This month we present a historical view of computational complexity written by Steve Homer and myself. This is a preliminary version of a chapter to be included in an upcoming North-Holland Handbook of the History of Mathematical Logic edited by Dirk van Dalen, John Dawson and Aki Kanamori. A Short History of Computational Complexity Lance Fortnow1 Steve Homer2 NEC Research Institute Computer Science Department 4 Independence Way Boston University Princeton, NJ 08540 111 Cummington Street Boston, MA 02215 1 Introduction It all started with a machine. In 1936, Turing developed his theoretical com- putational model. He based his model on how he perceived mathematicians think. As digital computers were developed in the 40's and 50's, the Turing machine proved itself as the right theoretical model for computation. Quickly though we discovered that the basic Turing machine model fails to account for the amount of time or memory needed by a computer, a critical issue today but even more so in those early days of computing. The key idea to measure time and space as a function of the length of the input came in the early 1960's by Hartmanis and Stearns. -
Lecture 16 1 Interactive Proofs
Notes on Complexity Theory Last updated: October, 2011 Lecture 16 Jonathan Katz 1 Interactive Proofs Let us begin by re-examining our intuitive notion of what it means to \prove" a statement. Tra- ditional mathematical proofs are static and are veri¯ed deterministically: the veri¯er checks the claimed proof of a given statement and is either convinced that the statement is true (if the proof is correct) or remains unconvinced (if the proof is flawed | note that the statement may possibly still be true in this case, it just means there was something wrong with the proof). A statement is true (in this traditional setting) i® there exists a valid proof that convinces a legitimate veri¯er. Abstracting this process a bit, we may imagine a prover P and a veri¯er V such that the prover is trying to convince the veri¯er of the truth of some particular statement x; more concretely, let us say that P is trying to convince V that x 2 L for some ¯xed language L. We will require the veri¯er to run in polynomial time (in jxj), since we would like whatever proofs we come up with to be e±ciently veri¯able. A traditional mathematical proof can be cast in this framework by simply having P send a proof ¼ to V, who then deterministically checks whether ¼ is a valid proof of x and outputs V(x; ¼) (with 1 denoting acceptance and 0 rejection). (Note that since V runs in polynomial time, we may assume that the length of the proof ¼ is also polynomial.) The traditional mathematical notion of a proof is captured by requiring: ² If x 2 L, then there exists a proof ¼ such that V(x; ¼) = 1. -
The Complexity Class NP
Quantum Many-Body Systems Boulder School Ashwin Nayak (U. Waterloo & Perimeter) July 22, 2010 Quantum Complexity Theory II In the last lecture, we saw what it means to compute a function efficiently, and saw subproblems of ISING GROUND STATE and k-SAT for which we know efficient algorithms. We also saw that the best known algorithms or these problems in their full generality are not efficient, and in fact are not qualitatively better than taking a brute-force search approach. Today, we’ll develop a theory that explains to some extent the difficulty in designing efficient algorithms for these problems. The complexity class NP Let us revisit the language ISING GROUND STATE. If someone gave us a state σ claiming that it had en- ergy H(σ) at most the required threshold k, we would be able to efficiently check whether that is true. In fact, whenever an instance (G,c,b,k) is in the language, there is such a state—the ground state would be one such. When the instance is not in the language, there is no such state, and any claimed state can efficiently be checked and rejected. The problem k-SAT enjoys the same property. If we are presented with an assignment, and we can check efficiently whether it satisfies the given formula or not. By definition, whenever the formula is satisfiable, there is evidence supporting this (e.g., a satisfying assignment), and when the formula is not satisfiable any claimed evidence (like a putative satisfying assignment) can be checked and rejected efficiently. This property is common to a wide array of problems, including the travelling salesman problem, graph isomorphism, scheduling with constraints, etc., and is the defining characteristic of the complexity class NP. -
IP=PSPACE. Arthur-Merlin Games
Computational Complexity Theory, Fall 2010 10 November Lecture 18: IP=PSPACE. Arthur-Merlin Games Lecturer: Kristoffer Arnsfelt Hansen Scribe: Andreas Hummelshøj J Update: Ω(n) Last time, we were looking at MOD3◦MOD2. We mentioned that AND required size 2 MOD3◦ MOD2 circuits. We also mentioned, as being open, whether NEXP ⊆ (nonuniform)MOD2 ◦ MOD3 ◦ MOD2. Since 9/11-2010, this is no longer open. Definition 1 ACC0 = class of languages: 0 0 ACC = [m>2ACC [m]; where AC0[m] = class of languages computed by depth O(1) size nO(1) circuits with AND-, OR- and MODm-gates. This is in fact in many ways a natural class of languages, like AC0 and NC1. 0 Theorem 2 NEXP * (nonuniform)ACC . New open problem: Is EXP ⊆ (nonuniform)MOD2 ◦ MOD3 ◦ MOD2? Recap: We defined arithmetization A(φ) of a 3-SAT formula φ: A(xi) = xi; A(xi) = 1 − xi; 3 Y A(l1 _ l2 _ l3) = 1 − (1 − A(li)); i=1 m Y A(c1 ^ · · · ^ cm) = A(cj): j=1 1 1 X X ]φ = ··· P (x1; : : : ; xn);P = A(φ): x1=0 xn=0 1 Sumcheck: Given g(x1; : : : ; xn), K and prime number p, decide if 1 1 X X ··· g(x1; : : : ; xn) ≡ K (mod p): x1=0 xn=0 True Quantified Boolean Formulae: 0 0 Given φ ≡ 9x18x2 ::: 8xnφ (x1; : : : ; xn), where φ is a 3SAT formula, decide if φ is true. Observation: φ true , P1 Q1 P ··· Q1 P (x ; : : : ; x ) > 0, P = A(φ0). x1=0 x2=0 x3 x1=0 1 n Protocol: Can't we just do it analogous to Sumcheck? Id est: remove outermost P, P sends polynomial S, V checks if S(0) + S(1) ≡ K, asks P to prove Q1 P1 ··· Q1 P (a) ≡ S(a), where x2=0 x3=0 xn=0 a 2 f0; 1; : : : ; p − 1g is chosen uniformly at random.