Coercion, Responsibility and the Scope of Justice: a Critique Of

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Coercion, Responsibility and the Scope of Justice: a Critique Of Coercion, Responsibility and the Scope of Justice: A critique of Nagel’s anti-cosmopolitan account By Attila Gergely Mráz Submitted to Central European University Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Supervisor: Professor Zoltán Miklósi CEU eTD Collection Budapest, Hungary 2010 Abstract This thesis offers a critique of the influential anti-cosmopolitan position put forward by Thomas Nagel. This position holds that duties of egalitarian justice exist if and only if there is a coercive political authority these duties can apply to, and the effects coercively imposed by this authority can be attributed to those coerced by it. As there is no global authority fulfilling these conditions, the scope of justice is not global on this account. After a brief contextualization of the scope-debate, I offer a twofold criticism of Nagel’s account. First, I argue that the existence of the required kind of political institutions cannot be a sufficient condition for the existence of robust egalitarian duties. Second, I show that even if egalitarian duties arose as Nagel suggests, the account given for their generation would not entail that their scope is restricted. Finally, I argue that even if the account of the generation and anti- cosmopolitan scope of these duties were right, the reasons Nagel accepts for leaving the state of nature also serve as reasons for establishing a global coercive authority to which egalitarian principles would apply on his account. Thus, it is shown that Nagel’s central normative premises are false, but their truth would not yield his desired conclusion either; and due to his assumptions concerning the state of nature, a consistent interpretation of his account should conclude that there is a duty to realize egalitarian justice globally. CEU eTD Collection Acknowledgements First and foremost, I would like to thank my supervisor, Professor Zoltán Miklósi, for his helpful comments, suggestions, objections and all the inspiring conversations we had on the topics discussed here. I would also like to take the opportunity to thank Orsi Reich and Anna Réz, in alphabetical order, for the support they gave me in matters professional and otherwise while I was working on my thesis. My gratitude to them can hardly be overstated for all they did to help me become a student of philosophy, and much more importantly, for their friendship. I hope I will grow up to be their colleague one day. I dedicate this thesis to A. K., who did not exactly make it easier for me to write it, nor anything else eventually, but who made life during the period of writing definitely much more worth living. (In the end, it was all the fault of Global Justice—but that’s no complaint.) CEU eTD Collection i Table of Contents Introduction............................................................................................................................1 1. The Scope of Justice: Contextualizing the Debate...............................................................5 1.0. Introduction .................................................................................................................5 1.1. Social cooperation, interaction and the scope of justice ................................................6 1.2. Pervasive impact and the scope of justice.....................................................................8 1.3. Coercion and the scope of justice ...............................................................................11 1.4. Conclusion.................................................................................................................15 2. Legitimacy, Responsibility and the Scope of Justice .........................................................17 2.0. Introduction ...............................................................................................................17 2.1. Reconstructing the argument, preliminary remarks on Nagel’s dualism......................17 2.2. Justice, responsibility and legitimacy .........................................................................20 2.3. Conclusion.................................................................................................................33 3. Nagel’s States of Nature and the Scope of Justice .............................................................34 3.0. Introduction ...............................................................................................................34 3.1. Nagel’s conception of the state of nature....................................................................34 3.2. The second-order state of nature.................................................................................37 3.3. Conclusion.................................................................................................................48 Conclusion ...........................................................................................................................49 References............................................................................................................................52 CEU eTD Collection ii Coercion, Responsibility and the Scope of Justice Attila Gergely Mráz Introduction The aim of this thesis is to provide a critique of Thomas Nagel’s (2005) anti-cosmopolitan account of the scope of egalitarian distributive justice: I argue that it fails to establish that the right scope of egalitarian justice is national. My critique addresses two specific aspects of Nagel’s theory. First, I investigate into the implicit theory of citizens’ responsibility for state action and that of political legitimacy, as conceived by Nagel, and the role they play in his argument for a restricted scope; I argue that these considerations cannot provide sufficient support for Nagel’s account of the generation and scope of duties of egalitarian justice. Second, by means of a detailed scrutiny of Nagel’s conception of the state of nature, I show that Nagel’s rejection of a duty to establish a global political community where duties of egalitarian justice would emerge on his account is unfounded, given his own assumptions concerning moral reasons to stay out of the state of nature. Nagel’s account has recently received ample criticism in two major respects. On the one hand, it has been argued that his account, even if normatively correct, does not yield empirically as restricted a scope as he intended (see e.g., Ypi, Goodin & Barry [2009], or even Cohen & Sabel [2006] who leave substantial parts of Nagel’s theoretical argumentation largely untouched). This line of criticism mainly concerns the correctness of Nagel’s empirical presuppositions. On the other hand, a strand of criticism more theoretical in focus has questioned or denied the normative relevance of coercion, an important but not specific element in Nagel’s theory, in triggering or generating duties of justice (this line of criticism siding Nagel simply with, e.g., Blake’s [2001] account). CEU eTD Collection My aim is to further the debate about the right scope of justice in favor of a global scope by criticizing Nagel’s account on two grounds not tackled by either line of extant criticism. First, I criticize the normative premises specific to his account of the generation and scope of egalitarian duties. In particular, I question the relevance of citizens’ responsibility for state 1 Coercion, Responsibility and the Scope of Justice Attila Gergely Mráz action to the generation and scope of these duties. Second, I reject Nagel’s account by showing that Nagel’s conclusions do not follow under coherent interpretations of his normative premises, regardless of the truth-value of his empirical premises. To the best of my knowledge, criticism on these grounds has been relatively sparsely, and not systematically, presented to date. The structure of my thesis is as follows. In Chapter 1, I will contextualize the Nagelian account by a brief, selective critical presentation of the debate on the scope of justice. Providing an avowedly biased overview, I will analyze and criticize some of the prevalent anti-cosmopolitan arguments for determining the scope of justice on grounds of social cooperation or interaction, pervasive impact, and coercion, so as to highlight the normatively interesting differences between these theories and Nagel’s account. My aim in this chapter is not to provide an exhaustive inventory of all the possible anti-cosmopolitan positions, but rather to emphasize the differences between Nagel’s theory and those theories which share at least some of its important fundamental assumptions. In Chapter 2, I will focus in on Nagel’s theory, analyzing his concept of political legitimacy and the concept of responsibility figuring in his implicit account of citizens’ responsibility for state action. The aim of this chapter is, first, to provide a charitable interpretation of Nagel’s argument for the national scope of justice, with special emphasis on the analysis of his responsibility-condition, a necessary condition of the emergence of egalitarian duties on his account. This condition requires citizens’ authorship of, or responsibility for, coercively enforced policies. Second, my aim is to show that the existence CEU eTD Collection of a legitimate coercive political authority which fulfills Nagel’s responsibility-condition is insufficient both for the generation of egalitarian duties of justice, and for the restriction of their scope. My argumentation, as declared above, will concern exclusively
Recommended publications
  • Churchland Source: the Journal of Philosophy, Vol
    Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Reduction, Qualia, and the Direct Introspection of Brain States Author(s): Paul M. Churchland Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 82, No. 1 (Jan., 1985), pp. 8-28 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2026509 Accessed: 07-08-2015 19:14 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 142.58.129.109 on Fri, 07 Aug 2015 19:14:45 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 8 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY structureof this idiom, moreover-its embeddingof a subordinate sentence-would have been clearly dictatedby its primitiveuse in assessing children's acquisition of observationsentences. Analogi- cal extension of the idiom to other than observation sentences would follow inevitably,and the developmentof parallel idioms for other propositional attitudeswould then come naturally too, notwithstanding their opacity from a logical point of view. Naturalness is one thing, transparencyanother; familiarityone, clarityanother. W. V. QtJINE Harvard University REDUCTION, QUALIA, AND THE DIRECT INTROSPECTION OF BRAIN STATES* DO the phenomenological or qualitative featuresof our sen- sations constitutea permanentbarrier to thereductive aspi- rations of any materialisticneuroscience? I here argue that theydo not.
    [Show full text]
  • The Absurd Author(S): Thomas Nagel Reviewed Work(S): Source: the Journal of Philosophy, Vol
    Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Absurd Author(s): Thomas Nagel Reviewed work(s): Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 68, No. 20, Sixty-Eighth Annual Meeting of the American Philosophical Association Eastern Division (Oct. 21, 1971), pp. 716-727 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2024942 . Accessed: 19/08/2012 01:08 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org 7i6 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY The formerstands as valid only if we can findcriteria for assigning a differentlogical formto 'allegedly' than to 'compulsively'.In this case, the criteriaexist: 'compulsively'is a predicate, 'allegedly' a sentenceadverb. But in countless other cases, counterexamplesare not so easily dismissed.Such an example, bearing on the inference in question, is Otto closed the door partway ThereforeOtto closed the door It seems clear to me that betterdata are needed beforeprogress can be made in this area; we need much more refinedlinguistic classificationsof adverbial constructionsthan are presentlyavail- able, ifour evidenceconcerning validity is to be good enough to per- mit a richerlogical theory.In the meantime,Montague's account stands: thereis no reason to thinka morerefined theory, if it can be produced, should not be obtainable within the frameworkhe has given us.
    [Show full text]
  • Distinguishing Science from Philosophy: a Critical Assessment of Thomas Nagel's Recommendation for Public Education Melissa Lammey
    Florida State University Libraries Electronic Theses, Treatises and Dissertations The Graduate School 2012 Distinguishing Science from Philosophy: A Critical Assessment of Thomas Nagel's Recommendation for Public Education Melissa Lammey Follow this and additional works at the FSU Digital Library. For more information, please contact [email protected] THE FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF ARTS & SCIENCES DISTINGUISHING SCIENCE FROM PHILOSOPHY: A CRITICAL ASSESSMENT OF THOMAS NAGEL’S RECOMMENDATION FOR PUBLIC EDUCATION By MELISSA LAMMEY A Dissertation submitted to the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Degree Awarded: Spring Semester, 2012 Melissa Lammey defended this dissertation on February 10, 2012. The members of the supervisory committee were: Michael Ruse Professor Directing Dissertation Sherry Southerland University Representative Justin Leiber Committee Member Piers Rawling Committee Member The Graduate School has verified and approved the above-named committee members, and certifies that the dissertation has been approved in accordance with university requirements. ii For Warren & Irene Wilson iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS It is my pleasure to acknowledge the contributions of Michael Ruse to my academic development. Without his direction, this dissertation would not have been possible and I am indebted to him for his patience, persistence, and guidance. I would also like to acknowledge the efforts of Sherry Southerland in helping me to learn more about science and science education and for her guidance throughout this project. In addition, I am grateful to Piers Rawling and Justin Leiber for their service on my committee. I would like to thank Stephen Konscol for his vital and continuing support.
    [Show full text]
  • The Pragmatic Turn in Philosophy
    Introduction n recent years the classical authors of Anglo-Saxon pragmatism have gar- Inered a renewed importance in international philosophical circles. In the aftermath of the linguistic turn, philosophers such as Charles S. Peirce, William James, George H. Mead, Ferdinand C. S. Schiller, and John Dewey are being reread alongside, for example, recent postmodern and deconstructivist thought as alternatives to a traditional orientation toward the concerns of a represen- tationalist epistemology. In the context of contemporary continental thought, the work of Jacques Derrida, Jean-Francois Lyotard, and Gilles Deleuze comprises just a few examples of a culturewide assault on a metaphysical worldview premised on what Michel Foucault called the empirico-transcendental doublet, and presents a wealth of potential exchange with the pragmatist critique of representationalism. In both cases, aspects of pragmatist thought are being used to add flexibility to the conceptual tools of modern philoso- phy, in order to promote a style of philosophizing more apt to dealing with the problems of everyday life. The hope for a pragmatic “renewing of phi- losophy” (Putnam) evidenced in these trends has led to an analytic reexami- nation of some of the fundamental positions in modern continental thought as well, and to a recognition of previously unacknowledged or underappreciated pragmatic elements in thinkers like Kant, Hegel, Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Wittgenstein. Within the current analytic discussions, a wide spectrum of differing and at times completely heterogeneous forms of neopragmatism can be distinguished, which for heuristic purposes can be grouped into two general categories according to the type of discursive strategy employed. The first of these consists in a conscious inflation of the concept of pragmatism in order to establish it as widely as possible within the disciplinary discourse of philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Consequences of Pragmatism University of Minnesota Press, 1982
    estratto dal volume: RICHARD RORTY Consequences of Pragmatism University of Minnesota Press, 1982 INTRODUCTION 1. Platonists, Positivists, and Pragmatists The essays in this book are attempts to draw consequences from a prag- matist theory about truth. This theory says that truth is not the sort of thing one should expect to have a philosophically interesting theory about. For pragmatists, “truth” is just the name of a property which all true statements share. It is what is common to “Bacon did not write Shakespeare,” “It rained yesterday,” “E equals mc²” “Love is better than hate,” “The Alle- gory of Painting was Vermeer’s best work,” “2 plus 2 is 4,” and “There are nondenumerable infinities.” Pragmatists doubt that there is much to be said about this common feature. They doubt this for the same reason they doubt that there is much to be said about the common feature shared by such morally praiseworthy actions as Susan leaving her husband, Ameri- ca joining the war against the Nazis, America pulling out of Vietnam, Socrates not escaping from jail, Roger picking up litter from the trail, and the suicide of the Jews at Masada. They see certain acts as good ones to perform, under the circumstances, but doubt that there is anything gen- eral and useful to say about what makes them all good. The assertion of a given sentence—or the adoption of a disposition to assert the sentence, the conscious acquisition of a belief—is a justifiable, praiseworthy act in certain circumstances. But, a fortiori, it is not likely that there is something general and useful to be said about what makes All such actions good-about the common feature of all the sentences which one should ac- quire a disposition to assert.
    [Show full text]
  • THE HORNSWOGGLE PROBLEM1 Patricia Smith Churchland, Department of Philosophy, University of California at San Diego, La Jolla, CA 92093, USA
    Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3, No. 5ñ6, 1996, pp. 402ñ8 THE HORNSWOGGLE PROBLEM1 Patricia Smith Churchland, Department of Philosophy, University of California at San Diego, La Jolla, CA 92093, USA. Abstract: Beginning with Thomas Nagel, various philosophers have propsed setting con- scious experience apart from all other problems of the mind as ëthe most difficult problemí. When critically examined, the basis for this proposal reveals itself to be unconvincing and counter-productive. Use of our current ignorance as a premise to determine what we can never discover is one common logical flaw. Use of ëI-cannot-imagineí arguments is a related flaw. When not much is known about a domain of phenomena, our inability to imagine a mechanism is a rather uninteresting psychological fact about us, not an interesting metaphysical fact about the world. Rather than worrying too much about the meta-problem of whether or not consciousness is uniquely hard, I propose we get on with the task of seeing how far we get when we address neurobiologically the problems of mental phenomena. I: Introduction Conceptualizing a problem so we can ask the right questions and design revealing experiments is crucial to discovering a satisfactory solution to the problem. Asking where animal spirits are concocted, for example, turns out not to be the right question to ask about the heart. When Harvey asked instead, ëHow much blood does the heart pump in an hour?í, he conceptualized the problem of heart function very differently. The recon- ceptualization was pivotal in coming to understand that the heart is really a pump for circulating blood; there are no animal spirits to concoct.
    [Show full text]
  • JL Mackie – “The Subjectivity of Values” Thomas Nagel – “Ethics”
    Lecture 23: The Objectivity or Subjectivity of Morality J. L. Mackie – “The Subjectivity of Values” Thomas Nagel – “Ethics” 1 Agenda 1. J. L. Mackie 2. Thomas Nagel 3. Ethics versus Metaethics 4. What Does it Mean for Morality to be Objective? 5. Argument from Relativity 6. Argument from Queerness 2 J. L. Mackie • John Leslie Mackie (1917 – 1981) • Australian philosopher from Sydney. • Interested in metaphysics, philosophy of language, ethics, metaethics, and the philosophy of religion. • Professor of philosophy at the University of Otago in New Zealand from 1955 to 1959. The Challis Professor of Philosophy at the University of Sydney from 1959 to 1963. Chair of philosophy in the University of York from 1963-1967. 3 Thomas Nagel • 1931 – present • Professor of Philosophy and Law Emeritus at New York University. • Works in political philosophy, ethics, philosophy of mind, and epistemology. • PhD from Harvard. 4 Ethics versus Metaethics • First order moral questions concern how you ought to act. (Theoretical and Practical Ethics) • Second order moral questions concern the nature of morality. For example, is morality objective? (Metaethics) • Are first order and second order moral questions completely independent? 5 What Does it Mean for Morality to be Objective? • Mackie says that when he is denying the objectivity of morality, he is denying that any categorical imperative is objectively valid. “The objective values which I am denying would be action-directing absolutely, not contingently… upon the agent’s desires and inclinations” (2). • Mackie understands himself to be espousing an error theory, namely “a theory that although most people in making moral judgments implicitly claim… to be pointing to something objectively prescriptive, these claims are all false” (3).
    [Show full text]
  • The Limits of Objectivity: the Tanner Lecture on Human Values by Thomas Nagel
    The Limits of Objectivity THOMAS NAGEL THE TANNER LECTURE ON HUMAN VALUES Delivered at Brasenose College, Oxford University May 4,11, and 18, 1979 THOMAS NAGEL is Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University. He was educated at Cornell, Oxford, and Harvard, and taught from 1963 to 1966 at the University of California, Berkeley, before moving to Princeton. He has been a Fellow of the Guggenheim and National Sci- ence Foundations. Professor Nagel is the author of The Possibility of Altruism (1970) and Mortal Questions (1979), and associate editor of Philosophy and Public Affairs . I. THE MIND 1. These lectures are about objectivity and its limits. In the second and third lectures I shall be concerned with normative questions; I shall defend the objectivity of ethics, and try to explain what it means. But today I am going to say something about the problem of objectivity as it occurs in metaphysics, espe- cially in the philosophy of mind. I do this because the problem has a similar form in the two areas, and because ideas arising from metaphysics influence our views of what must be done to discover objectivity in ethics. I hope therefore not only to say something about subjectivity and objectivity in the philosophy of mind, but also to set the stage for an account of what it would be for ethics to be objective. 2. As an aid to comprehension, let me begin by asserting with- out argument what I hope to show by examination of particular cases. Objectivity is a method of understanding. It is beliefs and knowledge that are objective in the primary sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Absolutism, Utilitarianism, and Moral Military Decision Making. Kristine V
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Masters Theses 1911 - February 2014 1999 Absolutism, utilitarianism, and moral military decision making. Kristine V. Nakutis University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/theses Nakutis, Kristine V., "Absolutism, utilitarianism, and moral military decision making." (1999). Masters Theses 1911 - February 2014. 2554. Retrieved from https://scholarworks.umass.edu/theses/2554 This thesis is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Masters Theses 1911 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ABSOLUTISM, UTILITARIANISM, AND MORAL MILITARY DECISION MAKING A Thesis Presented by KRISTINE V. NAKUTIS Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS September 1999 Philosophy - ABSOLUTISM, UTILITARIANISM, AND MORAL MILITARY DECISION MAKING A Thesis Presented by KRISTINE VARNUM NAKUTIS Approved as to style and content by: ^7 (— Fred Feldman, Chair i/eth B. Matthews, Member olftn G. Robison, Department Head department of Philosophy TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER Page 1. UTILITARIANISM AND WAR ... 1 Introduction... .. 1 Utilitarianism War ..2 ..5 U.S. Catholic Bishop View of War Combatants versus Non-Combatants 2. NAGEL’S ABSOLUTISM AND UTILITARIANISM Means and Ends 18 Straightforward Utilitarianism 20 What is Absolutism? 22 Technical Matters 26 Absolutist Restriction on Warfare 28 Class of Persons 28 Manner of Attack on Specific Classes of Persons 33 Utilitarianism and Absolutist Conflict 38 3. BRANDT’S RULE-UTILITARIANISM Nagel’s “Absolutism” 43 Morally Justifiable Rules 47 Utilitarian Rules 49 Rules Restricting Military Operations 52 Rules of War and Morality 60 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Nagel and Bernard Lonergan
    The University of Notre Dame Australia ResearchOnline@ND Theses 2018 A dialogue of traditions on the reality of mind: Thomas Nagel and Bernard Lonergan Robert van Gend Follow this and additional works at: https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses COMMONWEALTH OF AUSTRALIA Copyright Regulations 1969 WARNING The material in this communication may be subject to copyright under the Act. Any further copying or communication of this material by you may be the subject of copyright protection under the Act. Do not remove this notice. Publication Details van Gend, R. (2018). A dialogue of traditions on the reality of mind: Thomas Nagel and Bernard Lonergan (Master of Philosophy (School of Philosophy and Theology)). University of Notre Dame Australia. https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses/237 This dissertation/thesis is brought to you by ResearchOnline@ND. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of ResearchOnline@ND. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A DIALOGUE OF TRADITIONS ON THE REALITY OF MIND: THOMAS NAGEL AND BERNARD LONERGAN Robert van Gend A thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Philosophy School of Philosophy and Theology The University of Notre Dame Australia 2018 Abstract The scientific picture of the world is one of invisible particles and empty space, but this is not the world of our everyday experience. How can we reconcile the scientific view of the world with the view from our ordinary perspective? This thesis puts Thomas Nagel and Bernard Lonergan into dialogue on the question of the mind’s place in the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Wlodek Rabinowicz Derek Parfit's Contributions to Philosophy
    Wlodek Rabinowicz Derek Parfit's contributions to Philosophy Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Rabinowicz, Wlodek (2016) Derek Parfit's contributions to Philosophy. Theoria, 82 (2). pp. 104-109. ISSN 0040-5825 DOI: 10.1111/theo.12088 © 2016 Stiftelsen Theoria This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/66819/ Available in LSE Research Online: June 2016 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final accepted version of the journal article. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. Derek Parfit’s Contributions to Philosophy Wlodek Rabinowicz In 2014, The Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences awarded Derek Parfit the Rolf Schock Prize in Logic and Philosophy. In its motivation, the Academy stressed Parfit’s ground-breaking contributions to theory of personal identity, population ethics and analysis of the structure of moral theories. The list of philosophers and logicians who have received the Rolf Schock Prize is as yet relatively short.
    [Show full text]
  • Rhetoric, Pragmatism and the Interdisciplinary Turn in Legal Criticism -- a Study of Altruistic Judicial Argument
    Maurer School of Law: Indiana University Digital Repository @ Maurer Law Articles by Maurer Faculty Faculty Scholarship 1998 Rhetoric, Pragmatism and the Interdisciplinary Turn in Legal Criticism -- A Study of Altruistic Judicial Argument Gene R. Shreve Indiana University Maurer School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/facpub Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Legal History Commons Recommended Citation Shreve, Gene R., "Rhetoric, Pragmatism and the Interdisciplinary Turn in Legal Criticism -- A Study of Altruistic Judicial Argument" (1998). Articles by Maurer Faculty. 561. https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/facpub/561 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by Maurer Faculty by an authorized administrator of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. TOPIC I.B.2 GENE R. SHREVE Rhetoric, Pragmatism and the Interdisciplinary Turn in Legal Criticism-A Study of Altruistic Judicial Argument I. THE SETTING It is a pleasure to be the United States Reporter for a one-word topic as spacious and beguiling as "arguability." Since most academic writing in this country has become argument, the topic might be read locally to authorize a paper on any legal subject. The longer French version of the topic, however, seems to impose some discipline. With help, I translate it as: "What criteria would you use to determine the possibility of presenting a given legal argument?"1 A literal-minded (and no doubt acceptable) approach to this topic might discuss whether or why certain arguments are effective before judges of the writer's country.
    [Show full text]