Lecture 6 - Argument Principle, Rouch´E’Stheorem and Consequences

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Lecture 6 - Argument Principle, Rouch´E’Stheorem and Consequences Math 207 - Spring '17 - Fran¸coisMonard 1 Lecture 6 - Argument principle, Rouch´e'stheorem and consequences Material: [T, x4.4, 4.5], [G, xVIII.2]. [SS, Ch3, Sec. 4] Recall the Residue theorem, which allows to compute curve integrals of meromorphic functions in terms of their residues at the poles enclosed by that curve. Theorem 1 (Residue formula). Let f : U ! C meromorphic on U ⊂ C open with γ : I ! U a Jordan curve with Int (γ) ⊂ U, and such that f has no poles on γ(I). Then (i) Int (γ) encloses finitely many poles of f, call them z1; : : : ; zm. (ii) m Z X f(z) dz = 2πi Res (f; zj): γ j=1 We now show how this theorem can be used to compute the number of zeros and poles of f enclosed in a given region of the complex plane. When f is meromorphic, we have the following local representation of f: • near a zero or pole z0: there exists an integer k 6= 0, ρ > 0 and g analytic on Dρ(z0) (with k g nonvanishing near z0) such that f(z) = (z − z0) g(z) for z 2 Dρ(z0). Differentiating this equality, we obtain 0 k−1 k 0 f (z) = k(z − z0) g(z) + (z − z0) g (z); jz − z0j < ρ, so that 0 f k 0 (z) = g(z) + g (z); jz − z0j < ρ. f z − z0 f 0 • at any other point, f is analytic. f 0 As a conclusion, f is meromorphic wherever f is, and it has simple poles exactly located at the zeroes and poles of f, with residue the multiplicity of that zero/pole (with a negative sign if it is a pole). Combining this with the Residue theorem, we arrive at the next theorem. Theorem 2 (Argument principle). Let f : U ! C meromorphic on U ⊂ C open. Let γ : I ! U a Jordan curve with Int(γ) ⊂ U with no zeros or poles of f on γ(I). Then Z f 0(z) X f 0 dz = 2πi Res ; z = (2πi)(N − N ); f(z) f j 0 1 γ f0 zj poles of f where N0=N1 denote the numbers of zeros/poles of f inside γ, counted with multiplicity. (z−1)(z−i)3 R f 0(z) Example 1. Let f(z) = (z−2)5 . Compute γ f(z) dz for the following contours: (a) γ = @D1(−1); (b) γ = @D1:5(0); (c) γ = @D1:5(2): Math 207 - Spring '17 - Fran¸coisMonard 2 Theorem2 allows us to prove Rouch´e'stheorem. Theorem 3 (Rouch´e'stheorem). Let f; g : U ! C analytic on U ⊂ C open, γ : I ! U a Jordan curve with Int (γ) ⊂ U. Assume f has no zero on γ(I) and jf(z) − g(z)j ≤ jg(z)j; 8 z 2 γ(I): (1) Then f and g have the same number of zeros inside γ, counting multiplicities. You may think of f = (f − g) + g = "small" + "BIG" on γ(I) in the sense of (1): if f − g is \small" enough on γ(I), it does not perturb the number of zeros of g inside γ. f Proof of Rouch´e'stheorem. Due to (1), g has no zeros on γ(I) either. Define h := g , meromorphic on U, with no poles or zeros on γ(I). By Theorem2, we have Z h0(z) dz = 2πi(N0(h) − N1(h)) = 2πi(N0(f) − N0(g)); γ h(z) where the N's refer to numbers of zeros or poles inside γ. Using the equality above, the theorem will be proved if we can show that the left-hand-side is zero, which we now prove. R h0 To prove that γ h dz = 0, a way to rewrite (1) is, upon dividing by g, f(z) − 1 ≤ 1 8 z 2 γ(I) , jh(γ(t)) − 1j ≤ 1; 8 t 2 I; g(z) 1 so the closed curve h(γ(t)) is included in D1(1) − f0g, a convex set where z 7! z is analytic (that h cannot be zero on γ(I) comes from the fact that neither f nor g is vanishes on γ(I), as we stated above). Then Cauchy's theorem implies Z dz Z h0(γ(t)) Z h0(z) 0 = = γ0(t) dt = dz: h◦γ z I h(γ(t)) γ h(z) Hence the result. Example 2. Let f(z) = 1 + 2z + 7z2 + 3z5. Show that f has exactly two roots inside the unit disc. Answer: Apply Rouch´e'stheorem to g(z) = 7z2 and (f − g)(z) = 1 + 2z + 3z5. Among other consequences, Rouch´e'stheorem provides a short proof of the fundamental the- orem of algebra, with explicit bound on how large the roots are. In addition, we prove below a couple more consequences: the Open Mapping theorem and Hurwitz' theorem. Theorem 4 (Open Mapping Theorem). If f is holomorphic and non-constant in a region Ω, then it is open (i.e., f maps open sets to open sets). Proof. Suppose f non-constant. It is enough to show that if w0 2 f(z0) for some z0 2 Ω then there exists ρ > 0 such that Dρ(w0) ⊂ f(Ω). Indeed, consider the function g(z) = f(z) − w0. g is holomorphic, non-constant and has a zero at z0. By the local representation, there exists r > 0 such that g does not vanish on D_ (z ). In particular inf jg(z)j = C > 0. For w such that r 0 z2Cr=2(z0) jw − w0j < C, the function h(z) = f(z) − w satisfies jh(z) − g(z)j = jw − w0j < C ≤ jg(z)j; z 2 Cr=2(z0); so by Rouch´e'stheorem, h must have a zero inside Dr=2(z0), which means there exists z 2 Dr=2(z0) such that f(z) = w. That is, for every w 2 DC (w0), w belongs to f(Ω). Hence the proof. Math 207 - Spring '17 - Fran¸coisMonard 3 Hurwitz's theorem. Recall that a sequence fn of analytic functions fn : U ! C converges uniformly to f on K ⊂ U if and only if 8" > 0; 9n0; 8n ≥ n0; jfn(z) − f(z)j < "; 8 z 2 K: Recall that a uniform limit of analytic functions on K is itself analytic on K. For U ⊂ C an open domain, a sequence fn : U ! C of analytic functions converges normally to f on U if it converges uniformly to f on every compact subset of U. For the reason mentioned before this definition, the normal limit f as above is then analytic on U. Beware that normal convergence on U certainly does NOT imply uniform convergence on U. Examples: P n 1. The geometric series n≥0 z converges normally on the unit disk D1(0). (it's enough to show uniform convergence on every closed disk Dr(0) with r < 1). 2. The local power series of an analytic function converges normally to that function on its open disk of convergence. 3. The Laurent series of a function analytic on an annulus A(z0; r; R) converges normally to that function on the annulus. Theorem 5 (Hurwitz's theorem). Let U ⊂ C open and fn : U ! C a sequence of analytic functions on U, converging normally to a limit f on U. If z0 2 U is a zero of order m of f, there exists ρ > 0 and n0 2 N such that for every n ≥ n0, fn has exactly m zeros inside Dρ(z0), counting multiplicity. Moreover these zeros converge to z0 as n ! 1. m Proof. By local representation, there exists ρ > 0 such that f(z) = (z − z0) g(z) for every z 2 Dρ(z0), with g analytic on Dρ(z0) and g(z0) 6= 0. Upon shrinking ρ a bit, since g is continuous, we jg(z0)j can assume that jg(z)j ≥ 2 for every z 2 @Dρ(z0), so that, for jz − z0j = ρ, ρmjg(z )j jf(z)j = jz − z jmjg(z)j = ρmjg(z)j ≥ 0 ≡ c > 0: 0 2 Upon shrinking ρ again, we can assume that Dρ ⊂ U so that by normal convergence applied to the compact set K = Dρ(z0), there exists an integer n0 such that for n ≥ n0, maxz2K jfn(z)−f(z)j ≤ c. In particular, for every n ≥ n0 and jz − z0j = ρ, we have the estimate jfn(z) − f(z)j ≤ c ≤ jf(z)j: By Rouch´e'stheorem, this implies that fn has the same number of zeros as f inside Dρ(z0), counting multiplicity, i.e., m zeros. That these zeros converge to z0 is clear because we can shrink ρ as much we want, f will still have m zeros inside Dρ(z0), and following the proof above, for n large enough, fn much have its zeros inside Dρ(z0). Pn zk z Example: As a consequence, because the sequence fn(z) = k=0 k! converges normally to e on C, we can show that for every R > 0 there exists n0 such that for every n ≥ n0, fn has no zero inside DR(0). This is striking since fn has exactly n roots. This tells us that somehow, all the roots we add at every step should all escape at 1 ! Math 207 - Spring '17 - Fran¸coisMonard 4 References [G] Complex Analysis, Theodore W. Gamelin. Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics, Springer.1 [SS] Complex Analysis, Elias M. Stein and Rami Shakarchi, Princeton Lectures in Analysis II.1 [T] Complex Variables, Joseph L.
Recommended publications
  • Poles and Zeros of Generalized Carathéodory Class Functions
    W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 5-2011 Poles and Zeros of Generalized Carathéodory Class Functions Yael Gilboa College of William and Mary Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses Part of the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Gilboa, Yael, "Poles and Zeros of Generalized Carathéodory Class Functions" (2011). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 375. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses/375 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects at W&M ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of W&M ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Poles and Zeros of Generalized Carathéodory Class Functions A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Bachelor of Science with Honors in Mathematics from The College of William and Mary by Yael Gilboa Accepted for (Honors) Vladimir Bolotnikov, Committee Chair Ilya Spiktovsky Leiba Rodman Julie Agnew Williamsburg, VA May 2, 2011 POLES AND ZEROS OF GENERALIZED CARATHEODORY´ CLASS FUNCTIONS YAEL GILBOA Date: May 2, 2011. 1 2 YAEL GILBOA Contents 1. Introduction 3 2. Schur Class Functions 5 3. Generalized Schur Class Functions 13 4. Classical and Generalized Carath´eodory Class Functions 15 5. PolesandZerosofGeneralizedCarath´eodoryFunctions 18 6. Future Research and Acknowledgments 28 References 29 POLES AND ZEROS OF GENERALIZED CARATHEODORY´ CLASS FUNCTIONS 3 1. Introduction The goal of this thesis is to establish certain representations for generalized Carath´eodory functions in terms of related classical Carath´eodory functions. Let denote the Carath´eodory class of functions f that are analytic and that have a nonnegativeC real part in the open unit disk D = z : z < 1 .
    [Show full text]
  • 6.5 the Recursion Theorem
    6.5. THE RECURSION THEOREM 417 6.5 The Recursion Theorem The recursion Theorem, due to Kleene, is a fundamental result in recursion theory. Theorem 6.5.1 (Recursion Theorem, Version 1 )Letϕ0,ϕ1,... be any ac- ceptable indexing of the partial recursive functions. For every total recursive function f, there is some n such that ϕn = ϕf(n). The recursion Theorem can be strengthened as follows. Theorem 6.5.2 (Recursion Theorem, Version 2 )Letϕ0,ϕ1,... be any ac- ceptable indexing of the partial recursive functions. There is a total recursive function h such that for all x ∈ N,ifϕx is total, then ϕϕx(h(x)) = ϕh(x). 418 CHAPTER 6. ELEMENTARY RECURSIVE FUNCTION THEORY A third version of the recursion Theorem is given below. Theorem 6.5.3 (Recursion Theorem, Version 3 ) For all n ≥ 1, there is a total recursive function h of n +1 arguments, such that for all x ∈ N,ifϕx is a total recursive function of n +1arguments, then ϕϕx(h(x,x1,...,xn),x1,...,xn) = ϕh(x,x1,...,xn), for all x1,...,xn ∈ N. As a first application of the recursion theorem, we can show that there is an index n such that ϕn is the constant function with output n. Loosely speaking, ϕn prints its own name. Let f be the recursive function such that f(x, y)=x for all x, y ∈ N. 6.5. THE RECURSION THEOREM 419 By the s-m-n Theorem, there is a recursive function g such that ϕg(x)(y)=f(x, y)=x for all x, y ∈ N.
    [Show full text]
  • April 22 7.1 Recursion Theorem
    CSE 431 Theory of Computation Spring 2014 Lecture 7: April 22 Lecturer: James R. Lee Scribe: Eric Lei Disclaimer: These notes have not been subjected to the usual scrutiny reserved for formal publications. They may be distributed outside this class only with the permission of the Instructor. An interesting question about Turing machines is whether they can reproduce themselves. A Turing machine cannot be be defined in terms of itself, but can it still somehow print its own source code? The answer to this question is yes, as we will see in the recursion theorem. Afterward we will see some applications of this result. 7.1 Recursion Theorem Our end goal is to have a Turing machine that prints its own source code and operates on it. Last lecture we proved the existence of a Turing machine called SELF that ignores its input and prints its source code. We construct a similar proof for the recursion theorem. We will also need the following lemma proved last lecture. ∗ ∗ Lemma 7.1 There exists a computable function q :Σ ! Σ such that q(w) = hPwi, where Pw is a Turing machine that prints w and hats. Theorem 7.2 (Recursion theorem) Let T be a Turing machine that computes a function t :Σ∗ × Σ∗ ! Σ∗. There exists a Turing machine R that computes a function r :Σ∗ ! Σ∗, where for every w, r(w) = t(hRi; w): The theorem says that for an arbitrary computable function t, there is a Turing machine R that computes t on hRi and some input. Proof: We construct a Turing Machine R in three parts, A, B, and T , where T is given by the statement of the theorem.
    [Show full text]
  • Intuitionism on Gödel's First Incompleteness Theorem
    The Yale Undergraduate Research Journal Volume 2 Issue 1 Spring 2021 Article 31 2021 Incomplete? Or Indefinite? Intuitionism on Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem Quinn Crawford Yale University Follow this and additional works at: https://elischolar.library.yale.edu/yurj Part of the Mathematics Commons, and the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Crawford, Quinn (2021) "Incomplete? Or Indefinite? Intuitionism on Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem," The Yale Undergraduate Research Journal: Vol. 2 : Iss. 1 , Article 31. Available at: https://elischolar.library.yale.edu/yurj/vol2/iss1/31 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by EliScholar – A Digital Platform for Scholarly Publishing at Yale. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Yale Undergraduate Research Journal by an authorized editor of EliScholar – A Digital Platform for Scholarly Publishing at Yale. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Incomplete? Or Indefinite? Intuitionism on Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem Cover Page Footnote Written for Professor Sun-Joo Shin’s course PHIL 437: Philosophy of Mathematics. This article is available in The Yale Undergraduate Research Journal: https://elischolar.library.yale.edu/yurj/vol2/iss1/ 31 Crawford: Intuitionism on Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem Crawford | Philosophy Incomplete? Or Indefinite? Intuitionism on Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem By Quinn Crawford1 1Department of Philosophy, Yale University ABSTRACT This paper analyzes two natural-looking arguments that seek to leverage Gödel’s first incompleteness theo- rem for and against intuitionism, concluding in both cases that the argument is unsound because it equivo- cates on the meaning of “proof,” which differs between formalism and intuitionism.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory
    Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory To criticize mathematics for its abstraction is to miss the point entirely. Abstraction is what makes mathematics work. If you concentrate too closely on too limited an application of a mathematical idea, you rob the mathematician of his most important tools: analogy, generality, and simplicity. – Ian Stewart Does God play dice? The mathematics of chaos In mathematics, a proof is a demonstration that, assuming certain axioms, some statement is necessarily true. That is, a proof is a logical argument, not an empir- ical one. One must demonstrate that a proposition is true in all cases before it is considered a theorem of mathematics. An unproven proposition for which there is some sort of empirical evidence is known as a conjecture. Mathematical logic is the framework upon which rigorous proofs are built. It is the study of the principles and criteria of valid inference and demonstrations. Logicians have analyzed set theory in great details, formulating a collection of axioms that affords a broad enough and strong enough foundation to mathematical reasoning. The standard form of axiomatic set theory is denoted ZFC and it consists of the Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) axioms combined with the axiom of choice (C). Each of the axioms included in this theory expresses a property of sets that is widely accepted by mathematicians. It is unfortunately true that careless use of set theory can lead to contradictions. Avoiding such contradictions was one of the original motivations for the axiomatization of set theory. 1 2 CHAPTER 1. LOGIC AND SET THEORY A rigorous analysis of set theory belongs to the foundations of mathematics and mathematical logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Control Systems
    ECE 380: Control Systems Course Notes: Winter 2014 Prof. Shreyas Sundaram Department of Electrical and Computer Engineering University of Waterloo ii c Shreyas Sundaram Acknowledgments Parts of these course notes are loosely based on lecture notes by Professors Daniel Liberzon, Sean Meyn, and Mark Spong (University of Illinois), on notes by Professors Daniel Davison and Daniel Miller (University of Waterloo), and on parts of the textbook Feedback Control of Dynamic Systems (5th edition) by Franklin, Powell and Emami-Naeini. I claim credit for all typos and mistakes in the notes. The LATEX template for The Not So Short Introduction to LATEX 2" by T. Oetiker et al. was used to typeset portions of these notes. Shreyas Sundaram University of Waterloo c Shreyas Sundaram iv c Shreyas Sundaram Contents 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Dynamical Systems . .1 1.2 What is Control Theory? . .2 1.3 Outline of the Course . .4 2 Review of Complex Numbers 5 3 Review of Laplace Transforms 9 3.1 The Laplace Transform . .9 3.2 The Inverse Laplace Transform . 13 3.2.1 Partial Fraction Expansion . 13 3.3 The Final Value Theorem . 15 4 Linear Time-Invariant Systems 17 4.1 Linearity, Time-Invariance and Causality . 17 4.2 Transfer Functions . 18 4.2.1 Obtaining the transfer function of a differential equation model . 20 4.3 Frequency Response . 21 5 Bode Plots 25 5.1 Rules for Drawing Bode Plots . 26 5.1.1 Bode Plot for Ko ....................... 27 5.1.2 Bode Plot for sq ....................... 28 s −1 s 5.1.3 Bode Plot for ( p + 1) and ( z + 1) .
    [Show full text]
  • Theorem Proving in Classical Logic
    MEng Individual Project Imperial College London Department of Computing Theorem Proving in Classical Logic Supervisor: Dr. Steffen van Bakel Author: David Davies Second Marker: Dr. Nicolas Wu June 16, 2021 Abstract It is well known that functional programming and logic are deeply intertwined. This has led to many systems capable of expressing both propositional and first order logic, that also operate as well-typed programs. What currently ties popular theorem provers together is their basis in intuitionistic logic, where one cannot prove the law of the excluded middle, ‘A A’ – that any proposition is either true or false. In classical logic this notion is provable, and the_: corresponding programs turn out to be those with control operators. In this report, we explore and expand upon the research about calculi that correspond with classical logic; and the problems that occur for those relating to first order logic. To see how these calculi behave in practice, we develop and implement functional languages for propositional and first order logic, expressing classical calculi in the setting of a theorem prover, much like Agda and Coq. In the first order language, users are able to define inductive data and record types; importantly, they are able to write computable programs that have a correspondence with classical propositions. Acknowledgements I would like to thank Steffen van Bakel, my supervisor, for his support throughout this project and helping find a topic of study based on my interests, for which I am incredibly grateful. His insight and advice have been invaluable. I would also like to thank my second marker, Nicolas Wu, for introducing me to the world of dependent types, and suggesting useful resources that have aided me greatly during this report.
    [Show full text]
  • Real Rational Filters, Zeros and Poles
    Real Rational Filters, Zeros and Poles Jack Xin (Lecture) and J. Ernie Esser (Lab) ∗ Abstract Classnotes on real rational filters, causality, stability, frequency response, impulse response, zero/pole analysis, minimum phase and all pass filters. 1 Real Rational Filter and Frequency Response A real rational filter takes the form of difference equations in the time domain: a(1)y(n) = b(1)x(n)+ b(2)x(n 1) + + b(nb + 1)x(n nb) − ··· − a(2)y(n 1) a(na + 1)y(n na), (1) − − −···− − where na and nb are nonnegative integers (number of delays), x is input signal, y is filtered output signal. In the z-domain, the z-transforms X and Y are related by: Y (z)= H(z) X(z), (2) where X and Y are z-transforms of x and y respectively, and H is called the transfer function: b(1) + b(2)z−1 + + b(nb + 1)z−nb H(z)= ··· . (3) a(1) + a(2)z−1 + + a(na + 1)z−na ··· The filter is called real rational because H is a rational function of z with real coefficients in numerator and denominator. The frequency response of the filter is H(ejθ), where j = √ 1, θ [0, π]. The θ [π, 2π] − ∈ ∈ portion does not contain more information due to complex conjugacy. In Matlab, the frequency response is obtained by: [h, θ] = freqz(b, a, N), where b = [b(1), b(2), , b(nb + 1)], a = [a(1), a(2), , a(na + 1)], N refers to number of ··· ··· sampled points for θ on the upper unit semi-circle; h is a complex vector with components H(ejθ) at sampled points of θ.
    [Show full text]
  • Residue Theorem
    Topic 8 Notes Jeremy Orloff 8 Residue Theorem 8.1 Poles and zeros f z z We remind you of the following terminology: Suppose . / is analytic at 0 and f z a z z n a z z n+1 ; . / = n. * 0/ + n+1. * 0/ + § a ≠ f n z n z with n 0. Then we say has a zero of order at 0. If = 1 we say 0 is a simple zero. f z Suppose has an isolated singularity at 0 and Laurent series b b b n n*1 1 f .z/ = + + § + + a + a .z * z / + § z z n z z n*1 z z 0 1 0 . * 0/ . * 0/ * 0 < z z < R b ≠ f n z which converges on 0 * 0 and with n 0. Then we say has a pole of order at 0. n z If = 1 we say 0 is a simple pole. There are several examples in the Topic 7 notes. Here is one more Example 8.1. z + 1 f .z/ = z3.z2 + 1/ has isolated singularities at z = 0; ,i and a zero at z = *1. We will show that z = 0 is a pole of order 3, z = ,i are poles of order 1 and z = *1 is a zero of order 1. The style of argument is the same in each case. At z = 0: 1 z + 1 f .z/ = ⋅ : z3 z2 + 1 Call the second factor g.z/. Since g.z/ is analytic at z = 0 and g.0/ = 1, it has a Taylor series z + 1 g.z/ = = 1 + a z + a z2 + § z2 + 1 1 2 Therefore 1 a a f .z/ = + 1 +2 + § : z3 z2 z This shows z = 0 is a pole of order 3.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Mathematical Foundations of Learning
    BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 39, Number 1, Pages 1{49 S 0273-0979(01)00923-5 Article electronically published on October 5, 2001 ON THE MATHEMATICAL FOUNDATIONS OF LEARNING FELIPE CUCKER AND STEVE SMALE The problem of learning is arguably at the very core of the problem of intelligence, both biological and artificial. T. Poggio and C.R. Shelton Introduction (1) A main theme of this report is the relationship of approximation to learning and the primary role of sampling (inductive inference). We try to emphasize relations of the theory of learning to the mainstream of mathematics. In particular, there are large roles for probability theory, for algorithms such as least squares,andfor tools and ideas from linear algebra and linear analysis. An advantage of doing this is that communication is facilitated and the power of core mathematics is more easily brought to bear. We illustrate what we mean by learning theory by giving some instances. (a) The understanding of language acquisition by children or the emergence of languages in early human cultures. (b) In Manufacturing Engineering, the design of a new wave of machines is an- ticipated which uses sensors to sample properties of objects before, during, and after treatment. The information gathered from these samples is to be analyzed by the machine to decide how to better deal with new input objects (see [43]). (c) Pattern recognition of objects ranging from handwritten letters of the alpha- bet to pictures of animals, to the human voice. Understanding the laws of learning plays a large role in disciplines such as (Cog- nitive) Psychology, Animal Behavior, Economic Decision Making, all branches of Engineering, Computer Science, and especially the study of human thought pro- cesses (how the brain works).
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 7: the Z-Transform
    Chapter 7: The z-Transform Chih-Wei Liu Outline Introduction The z-Transform Properties of the Region of Convergence Properties of the z-Transform Inversion of the z-Transform The Transfer Function Causality and Stability Determining Frequency Response from Poles & Zeros Computational Structures for DT-LTI Systems The Unilateral z-Transform 2 Introduction The z-transform provides a broader characterization of discrete-time LTI systems and their interaction with signals than is possible with DTFT Signal that is not absolutely summable z-transform DTFT Two varieties of z-transform: Unilateral or one-sided Bilateral or two-sided The unilateral z-transform is for solving difference equations with initial conditions. The bilateral z-transform offers insight into the nature of system characteristics such as stability, causality, and frequency response. 3 A General Complex Exponential zn Complex exponential z= rej with magnitude r and angle n zn rn cos(n) jrn sin(n) Re{z }: exponential damped cosine Im{zn}: exponential damped sine r: damping factor : sinusoidal frequency < 0 exponentially damped cosine exponentially damped sine zn is an eigenfunction of the LTI system 4 Eigenfunction Property of zn x[n] = zn y[n]= x[n] h[n] LTI system, h[n] y[n] h[n] x[n] h[k]x[n k] k k H z h k z Transfer function k h[k]znk k n H(z) is the eigenvalue of the eigenfunction z n k j (z) z h[k]z Polar form of H(z): H(z) = H(z)e k H(z)amplitude of H(z); (z) phase of H(z) zn H (z) Then yn H ze j z z n .
    [Show full text]
  • Augustin-Louis Cauchy - Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia 1/6/14 3:35 PM Augustin-Louis Cauchy from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    Augustin-Louis Cauchy - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia 1/6/14 3:35 PM Augustin-Louis Cauchy From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Baron Augustin-Louis Cauchy (French: [oɡystɛ̃ Augustin-Louis Cauchy lwi koʃi]; 21 August 1789 – 23 May 1857) was a French mathematician who was an early pioneer of analysis. He started the project of formulating and proving the theorems of infinitesimal calculus in a rigorous manner, rejecting the heuristic Cauchy around 1840. Lithography by Zéphirin principle of the Belliard after a painting by Jean Roller. generality of algebra exploited by earlier Born 21 August 1789 authors. He defined Paris, France continuity in terms of Died 23 May 1857 (aged 67) infinitesimals and gave Sceaux, France several important Nationality French theorems in complex Fields Mathematics analysis and initiated the Institutions École Centrale du Panthéon study of permutation École Nationale des Ponts et groups in abstract Chaussées algebra. A profound École polytechnique mathematician, Cauchy Alma mater École Nationale des Ponts et exercised a great Chaussées http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Augustin-Louis_Cauchy Page 1 of 24 Augustin-Louis Cauchy - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia 1/6/14 3:35 PM influence over his Doctoral Francesco Faà di Bruno contemporaries and students Viktor Bunyakovsky successors. His writings Known for See list cover the entire range of mathematics and mathematical physics. "More concepts and theorems have been named for Cauchy than for any other mathematician (in elasticity alone there are sixteen concepts and theorems named for Cauchy)."[1] Cauchy was a prolific writer; he wrote approximately eight hundred research articles and five complete textbooks. He was a devout Roman Catholic, strict Bourbon royalist, and a close associate of the Jesuit order.
    [Show full text]