Continuations and Derivational Ambiguity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Continuations and Derivational Ambiguity Continuations and derivational ambiguity Michael Moortgat LACL 2014, Toulouse Abstract In categorial grammar, compositional interpretation is implemented along the lines of Montague's `Universal Grammar' program, taking the form of a structure-preserving mapping (a homomorphism) relating a source logic to a target logic. The homomorphism requirement implies that for an expression to be associated with multiple `readings', there must be derivational ambiguity at the source end of the compositional mapping. In this talk, I study the kind of derivational ambiguity that arises in some recent continuation-based categorial approaches. In Bastenhof (2013) and Moortgat and Moot (2013), the source derivations for compo- sitional interpretation are focused proofs of a polarized sequent calculus or its graphical alternative; different notions of derivational ambiguity result from the choices one can make in fixing the polarity of atomic formulas. I compare this approach to the handling of continuations in terms of the combinatory and multimodal sequent calculi one finds in Barker and Shan (2014). Continuation semantics Turn of the century shift from direct interpretation to continuation-based semantic analysis. I importing ideas from computer science / functional programming . de Groote 2001, Barker 2002; Barker and Shan (. , 2014) . dynamic semantics: de Groote 2006, Asher&Pogodalla 2011, Lebe- deva PhD 2012 I importing ideas from classical linear logic . Lambek-Grishin: equal treatment of hypotheses / conclusions . 2007{. : MM, Bernardi, Kurtonina, Moot, Bransen, Melissen, Bas- tenhof PhD 2013 Some key ideas I direct interpretation: a function A ! B, presented with an argument of type A, returns a value of type B I continuation semantics: makes explicit the context where that value will be used, creating opportunities for exerting control I continuation: the future of the computation, with respect to overall result I target for interpretation: distinguished response type ? (maybe identified with t for NL semantics); for every source type A, distinguish .V A: values .K A: continuations, VA !? .C A: computations, KA !?, i.e. (VA !?) !? A ! B interpretation becomes VA ! (VB !?) !? Outline of the talk I Compositionality, derivational ambiguity I Type shifting and evaluation order (Barker & Shan 2014) I Type shifting and focusing Compositional interpretation Source Target h h (As)s2S;F i h (Bt)t2T ;G i I source algebra, sorts S, operations F I target algebra, sorts T , operations G I interpretation h: homomorphism, mapping respecting sorts/operations Antecedents cf Janssen, Foundations and applications of MG, 1983 I Montague, Universal Grammar, 1970 I ADJ, Initial algebra semantics and continuous algebras, 1977 (Goguen, Thatcher, Wagner, Wright) Compositionality, categorially Source and target: type logics with similar structure. Simplest example: Source Target h np;s;n AB LPe;t =;n ( I h on types: atoms h(np) = e; h(s) = t; h(n) = e ( t, and h(AnB) = h(B=A) = h(A) ( h(B) I h on proofs/terms: h(x) = xe, h(N.M) = h(M/N) = ( h(M) h(N)) source: directional left/right application (Buszkowski, Wansing); target: regular LP/MILL application. Derivational vs lexical interpretation The above abstracts from the contribution of lexical items: one interprets source derivations x1 : A1; : : : ; xn : An ` M : B FV (M): parameters, where lexical constants can be substituted. Adding the lexicon: Source Targetder Targetlex hder hlex np;s;n AB LPe;t ILe;t =;n ( ! I Source signature: type assignments to lexical constants c0; c1;::: I Targetlex signature I hlex ◦ hder translations for ci: terms of Targetlex , possibly non-linear Claim non-linearity encapsuled in interpretation of lexical constants. Compositional variations Source Pick your favourite typelogical framework: I Lambek (N)L, multimodal/hybrid TLG, Displacement Calculus, . I LP/MILL: ACG, Lambda Grammars; MILL1 (Moot 2014) Target Alternatives for Montagovian modeltheoretic interpretation: I PTS, prooftheoretic semantics, Francez c.s. I distributional models (Coecke, Sadrzadeh c.s.): h: `quantisation functor' from monoidal bi-closed category (L) to FVect Derivational ambiguity Input for compositional interpretation: source derivations / proof terms. ; h can `forget' derivational structure (e.g. linear order) but not create struc- ture at the target end. Genuine ambiguity distinct source derivations correspond to distinct target terms. I e.g. s=(npns); (s=(npns))ns `NL s (`something is missing') I two source derivations, su > vp versus vp > su scope construal Spurious ambiguity distinct source derivations mapped to same target term I typical example: multiple sequent derivations for one N.D. proof I proof nets, normalized sequent proofs: eliminate spurious ambiguity Prehistoric remains H. Hendriks & M. Moortgat, Theory of flexible interpretation. Specification and grammar fragment. DYANA Deliverable R1.2.A, 1990. Hendriks: Flexible MG Objective optimal (=minimal) type assignment in syntax / semantics Source (viewed categorially) a pure application AB syntax Mapping source ; target derivations: weakened to a relation I types: source type is associated with (infinite) set of sem types . basic type map + closure under type-shifting combinators I terms: for primitive and composite terms . basic translation + derived translations for type-shifts ; the FMG architecture moves the origin of derivational ambiguity to the semantic target language. FMG semantic type shifting The following are valid LP/MILL type transitions: ~ VR, value raising from f : A ( B derive ~ λ~xλw:(w (f ~x)) : A ( (B ( D) ( D ~ ~ AL, argument lowering from f : A ( ((B ( D) ( D) ( C ( E derive ~ ~ λ~xλwλ~y:(f ~x (λz:(z w)) ~y): A ( B ( C ( E ~ ~ AR, argument raising from f : A ( B ( C ( D derive ~ ~ λ~xλwλ~y:(w λz:(f ~xz ~y)) : A ( ((B ( D) ( D) ( C ( D (Generalized from Hendriks '90, who imposes the restriction D = E = t.) Back to the source Challenge Can one restore compositionality in its strong form by relocating the origin of derivational ambiguity to the source calculus? Observation VR, AL and a restricted form of AR are obtainable as the image of valid NL type transitions. MM'90, commenting on HH'90. I VR, AL: lifting, recursively generalized under monotonicity I AR: obtain its sem effect via source inference of the form ∆[ y : A] ) N : B Γ[ z : C] ) M : D (qL) Γ[ ∆[ x : q(A; B; C)]] ) M 0 : D 0 where M = M[ z=(x λy:N)], h( q(A; B; C) ) = (h(A)(h(B))(h(C) Logical decomposition: q(A; B; C) = (B " A) # C, Morrill TLG. Type shifting and continuations Barker 2002/2004: rational reconstruction of FMG in terms of continuations. Target recast the ubiquitous lifted types of FMG as computations functions KA (?, i.e. (A (?) (?, wrt response type ? Source to Target extend the interpretation function with continuation level: 0 I types: h lifts h(A) to Ch(A), functions acting on their own continuation: 0 h (A) = (h(A) (?) (? I terms: we need translations for . atomic terms / lexical constants . derivations: left/right application Translation: constants, proof terms Constants at the Targetlex level, the response type is identified with t Default translation: cA ; λk:(k ceh(A)) but `logically interesting' lexical items actually exploit their continuation: (et)t someonenp ; λk:(9 λx.(k x)) Compound terms compositional interpretation of source operations /; . h0(N A .M AnB) = h0(.) h0(M) h0(N) 0 0 0 0 h (.) :: h (AnB) ( h (A) ( h (B) Two possible solutions respecting the interpretation of types: 0 (y) h (/) = λM λN λk:(M λx.(N λy:(k (x y)))) 0 (z) h (/) = λM λN λk:(N λy:(M λx.(k (x y)))) Towers Ambiguity the interpretation of everyone . (tv / someone) depends on the choice between translations (y) and (z)(exercise). But having them both, the Source ; Target correspondence is again a relation. B&S 2014 Source: multimodal type system: I AB logic for regular phrasal composition: operations =; n I separate level for composition of continuations: operations ; C B Tower notation for C (A B) formulas: A Compare binder schema q(A; B; C), infixation/extraction (B " A) # C Interaction slash / fat slash composition The type logic of B&S 2014 (Part I) is a CCG-style combinator system. The combination schema for interaction between the =; n and ; levels realizes default left-to-right surface scope construal: F D D C F C ; ` A AnB B The underlying sequent calculus (Part II) also validates right-to-left construal: D C F D F C ; ` A AnB B CompareLP derivations (thanks to Grail) for the two options. Left to right [y : a]1 [x : anb]2 [nE] (x y): b [k : bnc]3 [nE] (k (x y)): c [P 3] (k (x y)): c [P 2] (k (x y)): c [nI]2 λx:(k (x y)):( anb)nc right : ((anb)nc)nd [nE] (right λx:(k (x y))): d [P 2] (right λx:(k (x y))): d [nI]1 λy:(right λx:(k (x y))): and left :(and)nf [nE] (left λy:(right λx:(k (x y)))): f [P 2] (left λy:(right λx:(k (x y)))): f [nI]3 λk:(left λy:(right λx:(k (x y)))):( bnc)nf [P 3] λk:(left λy:(right λx:(k (x y)))):( bnc)nf λk:(left λy:(right λx:(k (x y)))) Right to left [y : a]1 [x : anb]2 [nE] (x y): b [k : bnc]3 [nE] (k (x y)): c [P 2] (k (x y)): c [nI]1 λy:(k (x y)): anc left :(anc)nd [nE] (left λy:(k (x y))): d [P 2] (left λy:(k (x y))): d [nI]2 λx:(left λy:(k (x y))):( anb)nd right : ((anb)nd)nf [nE] (right λx:(left λy:(k (x y)))): f [P 2] (right λx:(left λy:(k (x y)))): f [nI]3 λk:(right λx:(left λy:(k (x y)))):( bnc)nf λk:(right λx:(left λy:(k (x y)))) Inverse scope To obtain inverse scope, an alternative version of lifting is needed, targeting internal levels (. ?. not generally valid) B (A B) ` B (( C (A C )) B) plus a generalization of the
Recommended publications
  • Continuation-Passing Style
    Continuation-Passing Style CS 6520, Spring 2002 1 Continuations and Accumulators In our exploration of machines for ISWIM, we saw how to explicitly track the current continuation for a computation (Chapter 8 of the notes). Roughly, the continuation reflects the control stack in a real machine, including virtual machines such as the JVM. However, accurately reflecting the \memory" use of textual ISWIM requires an implementation different that from that of languages like Java. The ISWIM machine must extend the continuation when evaluating an argument sub-expression, instead of when calling a function. In particular, function calls in tail position require no extension of the continuation. One result is that we can write \loops" using λ and application, instead of a special for form. In considering the implications of tail calls, we saw that some non-loop expressions can be converted to loops. For example, the Scheme program (define (sum n) (if (zero? n) 0 (+ n (sum (sub1 n))))) (sum 1000) requires a control stack of depth 1000 to handle the build-up of additions surrounding the recursive call to sum, but (define (sum2 n r) (if (zero? n) r (sum2 (sub1 n) (+ r n)))) (sum2 1000 0) computes the same result with a control stack of depth 1, because the result of a recursive call to sum2 produces the final result for the enclosing call to sum2 . Is this magic, or is sum somehow special? The sum function is slightly special: sum2 can keep an accumulated total, instead of waiting for all numbers before starting to add them, because addition is commutative.
    [Show full text]
  • Denotational Semantics
    Denotational Semantics CS 6520, Spring 2006 1 Denotations So far in class, we have studied operational semantics in depth. In operational semantics, we define a language by describing the way that it behaves. In a sense, no attempt is made to attach a “meaning” to terms, outside the way that they are evaluated. For example, the symbol ’elephant doesn’t mean anything in particular within the language; it’s up to a programmer to mentally associate meaning to the symbol while defining a program useful for zookeeppers. Similarly, the definition of a sort function has no inherent meaning in the operational view outside of a particular program. Nevertheless, the programmer knows that sort manipulates lists in a useful way: it makes animals in a list easier for a zookeeper to find. In denotational semantics, we define a language by assigning a mathematical meaning to functions; i.e., we say that each expression denotes a particular mathematical object. We might say, for example, that a sort implementation denotes the mathematical sort function, which has certain properties independent of the programming language used to implement it. In other words, operational semantics defines evaluation by sourceExpression1 −→ sourceExpression2 whereas denotational semantics defines evaluation by means means sourceExpression1 → mathematicalEntity1 = mathematicalEntity2 ← sourceExpression2 One advantage of the denotational approach is that we can exploit existing theories by mapping source expressions to mathematical objects in the theory. The denotation of expressions in a language is typically defined using a structurally-recursive definition over expressions. By convention, if e is a source expression, then [[e]] means “the denotation of e”, or “the mathematical object represented by e”.
    [Show full text]
  • A Descriptive Study of California Continuation High Schools
    Issue Brief April 2008 Alternative Education Options: A Descriptive Study of California Continuation High Schools Jorge Ruiz de Velasco, Greg Austin, Don Dixon, Joseph Johnson, Milbrey McLaughlin, & Lynne Perez Continuation high schools and the students they serve are largely invisible to most Californians. Yet, state school authorities estimate This issue brief summarizes that over 115,000 California high school students will pass through one initial findings from a year- of the state’s 519 continuation high schools each year, either on their long descriptive study of way to a diploma, or to dropping out of school altogether (Austin & continuation high schools in 1 California. It is the first in a Dixon, 2008). Since 1965, state law has mandated that most school series of reports from the on- districts enrolling over 100 12th grade students make available a going California Alternative continuation program or school that provides an alternative route to Education Research Project the high school diploma for youth vulnerable to academic or conducted jointly by the John behavioral failure. The law provides for the creation of continuation W. Gardner Center at Stanford University, the schools ‚designed to meet the educational needs of each pupil, National Center for Urban including, but not limited to, independent study, regional occupation School Transformation at San programs, work study, career counseling, and job placement services.‛ Diego State University, and It contemplates more intensive services and accelerated credit accrual WestEd. strategies so that students whose achievement in comprehensive schools has lagged might have a renewed opportunity to ‚complete the This project was made required academic courses of instruction to graduate from high school.‛ 2 possible by a generous grant from the James Irvine Taken together, the size, scope and legislative design of the Foundation.
    [Show full text]
  • RELATIONAL PARAMETRICITY and CONTROL 1. Introduction the Λ
    Logical Methods in Computer Science Vol. 2 (3:3) 2006, pp. 1–22 Submitted Dec. 16, 2005 www.lmcs-online.org Published Jul. 27, 2006 RELATIONAL PARAMETRICITY AND CONTROL MASAHITO HASEGAWA Research Institute for Mathematical Sciences, Kyoto University, Kyoto 606-8502 Japan, and PRESTO, Japan Science and Technology Agency e-mail address: [email protected] Abstract. We study the equational theory of Parigot’s second-order λµ-calculus in con- nection with a call-by-name continuation-passing style (CPS) translation into a fragment of the second-order λ-calculus. It is observed that the relational parametricity on the tar- get calculus induces a natural notion of equivalence on the λµ-terms. On the other hand, the unconstrained relational parametricity on the λµ-calculus turns out to be inconsis- tent. Following these facts, we propose to formulate the relational parametricity on the λµ-calculus in a constrained way, which might be called “focal parametricity”. Dedicated to Prof. Gordon Plotkin on the occasion of his sixtieth birthday 1. Introduction The λµ-calculus, introduced by Parigot [26], has been one of the representative term calculi for classical natural deduction, and widely studied from various aspects. Although it still is an active research subject, it can be said that we have some reasonable un- derstanding of the first-order propositional λµ-calculus: we have good reduction theories, well-established CPS semantics and the corresponding operational semantics, and also some canonical equational theories enjoying semantic completeness [16, 24, 25, 36, 39]. The last point cannot be overlooked, as such complete axiomatizations provide deep understand- ing of equivalences between proofs and also of the semantic structure behind the syntactic presentation.
    [Show full text]
  • Continuation Calculus
    Eindhoven University of Technology MASTER Continuation calculus Geron, B. Award date: 2013 Link to publication Disclaimer This document contains a student thesis (bachelor's or master's), as authored by a student at Eindhoven University of Technology. Student theses are made available in the TU/e repository upon obtaining the required degree. The grade received is not published on the document as presented in the repository. The required complexity or quality of research of student theses may vary by program, and the required minimum study period may vary in duration. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain Continuation calculus Master’s thesis Bram Geron Supervised by Herman Geuvers Assessment committee: Herman Geuvers, Hans Zantema, Alexander Serebrenik Final version Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Foreword . 3 1.2 The virtues of continuation calculus . 4 1.2.1 Modeling programs . 4 1.2.2 Ease of implementation . 5 1.2.3 Simplicity . 5 1.3 Acknowledgements . 6 2 The calculus 7 2.1 Introduction . 7 2.2 Definition of continuation calculus . 9 2.3 Categorization of terms . 10 2.4 Reasoning with CC terms .
    [Show full text]
  • 6.5 a Continuation Machine
    6.5. A CONTINUATION MACHINE 185 6.5 A Continuation Machine The natural semantics for Mini-ML presented in Chapter 2 is called a big-step semantics, since its only judgment relates an expression to its final value—a “big step”. There are a variety of properties of a programming language which are difficult or impossible to express as properties of a big-step semantics. One of the central ones is that “well-typed programs do not go wrong”. Type preservation, as proved in Section 2.6, does not capture this property, since it presumes that we are already given a complete evaluation of an expression e to a final value v and then relates the types of e and v. This means that despite the type preservation theorem, it is possible that an attempt to find a value of an expression e leads to an intermediate expression such as fst z which is ill-typed and to which no evaluation rule applies. Furthermore, a big-step semantics does not easily permit an analysis of non-terminating computations. An alternative style of language description is a small-step semantics.Themain judgment in a small-step operational semantics relates the state of an abstract machine (which includes the expression to be evaluated) to an immediate successor state. These small steps are chained together until a value is reached. This level of description is usually more complicated than a natural semantics, since the current state must embody enough information to determine the next and all remaining computation steps up to the final answer.
    [Show full text]
  • Compositional Semantics for Composable Continuations from Abortive to Delimited Control
    Compositional Semantics for Composable Continuations From Abortive to Delimited Control Paul Downen Zena M. Ariola University of Oregon fpdownen,[email protected] Abstract must fulfill. Of note, Sabry’s [28] theory of callcc makes use of Parigot’s λµ-calculus, a system for computational reasoning about continuation variables that have special properties and can only be classical proofs, serves as a foundation for control operations em- instantiated by callcc. As we will see, this not only greatly aids in bodied by operators like Scheme’s callcc. We demonstrate that the reasoning about terms with free variables, but also helps in relating call-by-value theory of the λµ-calculus contains a latent theory of the equational and operational interpretations of callcc. delimited control, and that a known variant of λµ which unshack- In another line of work, Parigot’s [25] λµ-calculus gives a sys- les the syntax yields a calculus of composable continuations from tem for computing with classical proofs. As opposed to the pre- the existing constructs and rules for classical control. To relate to vious theories based on the λ-calculus with additional primitive the various formulations of control effects, and to continuation- constants, the λµ-calculus begins with continuation variables in- passing style, we use a form of compositional program transforma- tegrated into its core, so that control abstractions and applications tions which preserves the underlying structure of equational the- have the same status as ordinary function abstraction. In this sense, ories, contexts, and substitution. Finally, we generalize the call- the λµ-calculus presents a native language of control.
    [Show full text]
  • Accumulating Bindings
    Accumulating bindings Sam Lindley The University of Edinburgh [email protected] Abstract but sums apparently require the full power of ap- plying a single continuation multiple times. We give a Haskell implementation of Filinski’s nor- malisation by evaluation algorithm for the computational In my PhD thesis I observed [14, Chapter 4] that by gen- lambda-calculus with sums. Taking advantage of extensions eralising the accumulation-based interpretation from a list to the GHC compiler, our implementation represents object to a tree that it is possible to use an accumulation-based language types as Haskell types and ensures that type errors interpretation for normalising sums. There I focused on are detected statically. an implementation using the state supported by the inter- Following Filinski, the implementation is parameterised nal monad of the metalanguage. The implementation uses over a residualising monad. The standard residualising Huet’s zipper [13] to navigate a mutable binding tree. Here monad for sums is a continuation monad. Defunctionalising we present a Haskell implementation of normalisation by the uses of the continuation monad we present the binding evaluation for the computational lambda calculus using a tree monad as an alternative. generalisation of Filinski’s binding list monad to incorpo- rate a tree rather than a list of bindings. (One motivation for using state instead of continuations 1 Introduction is performance. We might expect a state-based implementa- tion to be faster than an alternative delimited continuation- Filinski [12] introduced normalisation by evaluation for based implementation. For instance, Sumii and Kobay- the computational lambda calculus, using layered mon- ishi [17] claim a 3-4 times speed-up for state-based versus ads [11] for formalising name generation and for collecting continuation-based let-insertion.
    [Show full text]
  • C Programming Tutorial
    C Programming Tutorial C PROGRAMMING TUTORIAL Simply Easy Learning by tutorialspoint.com tutorialspoint.com i COPYRIGHT & DISCLAIMER NOTICE All the content and graphics on this tutorial are the property of tutorialspoint.com. Any content from tutorialspoint.com or this tutorial may not be redistributed or reproduced in any way, shape, or form without the written permission of tutorialspoint.com. Failure to do so is a violation of copyright laws. This tutorial may contain inaccuracies or errors and tutorialspoint provides no guarantee regarding the accuracy of the site or its contents including this tutorial. If you discover that the tutorialspoint.com site or this tutorial content contains some errors, please contact us at [email protected] ii Table of Contents C Language Overview .............................................................. 1 Facts about C ............................................................................................... 1 Why to use C ? ............................................................................................. 2 C Programs .................................................................................................. 2 C Environment Setup ............................................................... 3 Text Editor ................................................................................................... 3 The C Compiler ............................................................................................ 3 Installation on Unix/Linux ............................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Backpropagation with Continuation Callbacks: Foundations for Efficient
    Backpropagation with Continuation Callbacks: Foundations for Efficient and Expressive Differentiable Programming Fei Wang James Decker Purdue University Purdue University West Lafayette, IN 47906 West Lafayette, IN 47906 [email protected] [email protected] Xilun Wu Grégory Essertel Tiark Rompf Purdue University Purdue University Purdue University West Lafayette, IN 47906 West Lafayette, IN, 47906 West Lafayette, IN, 47906 [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Abstract Training of deep learning models depends on gradient descent and end-to-end differentiation. Under the slogan of differentiable programming, there is an increas- ing demand for efficient automatic gradient computation for emerging network architectures that incorporate dynamic control flow, especially in NLP. In this paper we propose an implementation of backpropagation using functions with callbacks, where the forward pass is executed as a sequence of function calls, and the backward pass as a corresponding sequence of function returns. A key realization is that this technique of chaining callbacks is well known in the programming languages community as continuation-passing style (CPS). Any program can be converted to this form using standard techniques, and hence, any program can be mechanically converted to compute gradients. Our approach achieves the same flexibility as other reverse-mode automatic differ- entiation (AD) techniques, but it can be implemented without any auxiliary data structures besides the function call stack, and it can easily be combined with graph construction and native code generation techniques through forms of multi-stage programming, leading to a highly efficient implementation that combines the per- formance benefits of define-then-run software frameworks such as TensorFlow with the expressiveness of define-by-run frameworks such as PyTorch.
    [Show full text]
  • Continuation-Passing Style Models Complete for Intuitionistic Logic Danko Ilik
    Continuation-passing Style Models Complete for Intuitionistic Logic Danko Ilik To cite this version: Danko Ilik. Continuation-passing Style Models Complete for Intuitionistic Logic. 2010. hal- 00647390v2 HAL Id: hal-00647390 https://hal.inria.fr/hal-00647390v2 Preprint submitted on 3 Dec 2011 (v2), last revised 9 May 2012 (v3) HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Continuation-passing Style Models Complete for Intuitionistic Logic Danko Ilik1 Ecole Polytechnique, INRIA, CNRS & Universit´eParis Diderot Address: INRIA PI-R2, 23 avenue d’Italie, CS 81321, 75214 Paris Cedex 13, France E-mail: [email protected] Abstract A class of models is presented, in the form of continuation monads polymorphic for first-order individuals, that is sound and complete for minimal intuitionistic predicate logic. The proofs of soundness and completeness are constructive and the computa- tional content of their composition is, in particular, a β-normalisation-by-evaluation program for simply typed lambda calculus with sum types. Although the inspiration comes from Danvy’s type-directed partial evaluator for the same lambda calculus, the there essential use of delimited control operators(i.e. computational effects) is avoided.
    [Show full text]
  • Continuation Passing Style
    Type Systems Lecture 10: Classical Logic and Continuation-Passing Style Neel Krishnaswami University of Cambridge Proof (and Refutation) Terms Propositions A ::= > j A ^ B j ? j A _ B j :A True contexts Γ ::= · j Γ; x : A False contexts ∆ ::= · j ∆; u : A Values e ::= hi j he; e0i j L e j R e j not(k) j µu : A: c Continuations k ::= [] j [k; k0] j fst k j snd k j not(e) j µx : A: c Contradictions c ::= he jA ki 1 Expressions — Proof Terms x : A 2 Γ Hyp Γ; ∆ ` x : A true >P (No rule for ?) Γ; ∆ ` hi : > true 0 Γ; ∆ ` e : A true Γ; ∆ ` e : B true ⟨ ⟩ ^ 0 P Γ; ∆ ` e; e : A ^ B true Γ; ∆ ` e : A true Γ; ∆ ` e : B true _P1 _P2 Γ; ∆ ` L e : A _ B true Γ; ∆ ` R e : A _ B true Γ; ∆ ` k : A false :P Γ; ∆ ` not(k): :A true 2 Continuations — Refutation Terms x : A 2 ∆ Hyp Γ; ∆ ` x : A false ?R (No rule for >) Γ; ∆ ` [] : ? false 0 Γ; ∆ ` k : A false Γ; ∆ ` k : B false [ ] _ 0 R Γ; ∆ ` k; k : A _ B false Γ; ∆ ` k : A false Γ; ∆ ` k : B false ^R1 ^R2 Γ; ∆ ` fst k : A ^ B false Γ; ∆ ` snd k : A ^ B false Γ; ∆ ` e : A true :R Γ; ∆ ` not(e): :A false 3 Contradictions Γ; ∆ ` e : A true Γ; ∆ ` k : A false Contr Γ; ∆ ` he jA ki contr Γ; ∆; u : A ` c contr Γ; x : A; ∆ ` c contr Γ; ∆ ` µu : A: c : A true Γ; ∆ ` µx : A: c : A false 4 Operational Semantics hhe1; e2i jA^B fst ki 7! he1 jA ki hhe1; e2i jA^B snd ki 7! he2 jB ki hL e jA_B [k1; k2]i 7! he jA k1i hR e jA_B [k1; k2]i 7! he jB k2i hnot(k) j:A not(e)i 7! he jA ki hµu : A: c jA ki 7! [k=u]c he jA µx : A: ci 7! [e=x]c 5 Type Safety? Preservation If ·; · ` c contr and c ; c0 then ·; · ` c0 contr.
    [Show full text]