The Intersection of Natural Rights and Positive Constitutional Law

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Intersection of Natural Rights and Positive Constitutional Law Georgetown University Law Center Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW 1993 The Intersection of Natural Rights and Positive Constitutional Law Randy E. Barnett Georgetown University Law Center, [email protected] This paper can be downloaded free of charge from: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/1253 25 Conn. L. Rev. 853-868 (1993) This open-access article is brought to you by the Georgetown Law Library. Posted with permission of the author. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, Human Rights Law Commons, and the Legislation Commons THE INTERSECTION OF NATURAL RIGHTS AND POSITIVE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW Randy E. Barnett* N his article, Constitutional PositivisiJl/ Fred Schauer makes a I number of intriguing observations about the possible relevance of natural law to constitutional adjudication. He identifies the natural law position as holding that law itself, just like the content of many laws, is derived from fundamental conceptions of morality. As a result, legal sys­ tems (and perhaps even particular laws) unfaithful to those moral conceptions are exemplars of erroneous derivations from first moral principles and are therefore not genuinely legal at all.2 Against this view stands legal positivism which holds that laws and legal systems satisfying certain sociological criteria count as laws and legal systems, regardless of their moral con­ tent. Hence the central positivist claim [is] ... that the exis­ tence of law is conceptually distinct from its moral worth.3 As a conceptual description of law, Professor Schauer endorses consti­ tutional positivism," although he in no manner denies that moral rea­ soning might be relevant to adjudication in some legal system or even every existing legal system. In this brief essay, I wish to describe what I see to be the unavoid­ able connection between natural law--or, more accurately, natural rights-and the positive law that is the subject of constitutional adjudi- * Norman & Edna Freehling Scholar and Professor of Law, Illinois Institute of Technology, Chicago-Kent College of Law. 1. Frederick Schauer, Constitutional Positivism, 25 CONN. L REV 797 (1993). 2. ld. at 799. 3. ld. at 800-01. 4. Elsewhere he identifies his position as "presumptive posith·ism." See Frederick Schauer, Rules and the Rule of Law, 14 HARV. J.L. & Pus. PoL'Y 645, 674-79 (1991). 853 854 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 25:853 cation. This connection would exist whether or not there is a conceptual distinction between natural and positive law of the sort that Schauer maintains. Because of this connection, judges in a world in which legal positivism is "true" should act, on occasion, as though the natural rights approach is' correct. And if this is true then, I maintain, the nat· ural rights position, in some important sense, is correct. Finally, I will take issue with Professor Schauer's intimation that the appropriate do· main of moral reasoning is limited largely to constitutional adjudica· tion and to the Supreme Court of the United States.5 I. THE MORAL IMPLICATION OF A PERCEIVED DUTY TO OBEY THE LAW My thesis is really quite simple. While it may be true-as Profes· sor Schauer argues-that we can distinguish conceptually between what the law "is" and what it "ought to be," between "law," on the one hand, and "justice," on the other,6 this distinction establishes less 5. Because Professor Schauer offers so much of his analysis as suggestive and concludes that "[t]here are no answers here," my thesis may not actually be inconsistent with his claims. But I think it is inconsistent with at least some of the impressions his presentation evokes. 6. Dworkin's criticism of this central claim of positivism is considered by Schauer. He rc· sponds that: If Dworkin is right ... the only hope for those who would be morally disturbed by the results that Justice Thomas would reach is to try to get better judges, for the task of trying to get Justice Thomas to lower his moral sights by focusing only on some pula· tively narrower range of materials is, as a descriptive matter, a complete nonstarter. Schauer, supra note I, at 824. In his later writings, however, Dworkin has made clear that he limits the range of interpretation to that which is "internal" to the particular legal system in question. That is, Hercules does not attempt to enforce only just laws, but to lind interpretations of the law that would make it the best law it can be in light of all other decisions, statutes and other authoritative legal pronouncements. In sum, Hercules' task is to rationalize the authoritative legal directives from within his legal universe. Having accomplished this Hercules has stated what the law "is." Nonetheless, this law-even so interpreted-may still be unjust. So while I may agree with Schauer that "the constitutional positivist can study and identify constitutional law as such without approving of it morally, and without feeling any part of the enterprise," id. at 806, I agree with Dworkin that to do constitutional law even a positivist must learn how to think as though he believed in the constitutional enterprise. Schauer himself attributes something like this internal point of view to constitutional scholars and particularly natural law scholars when he asserts that "the typical American constitutionalist thinks that the American constitutional tradition is generally worthy," id, at 805, and that "there is a tendency from a natural constitutional law perspective to think that a good deal of the Ameri· can constitutional tradition has been morally tested and found worthy." /d. To the contrary, natu­ ral law-and especially natural rights-thinking has always been primarily a radical philosophy and for that reason opposed. See, e.g., 2 JEREMY BENTHAM, Anarchical Fallacies, In THE WORKS OF JEREMY BENTHAM 489, 49 I -94 (John Bowring ed., 1962) ( 1838). The basic conservatism of the American judiciary has led it to reject, not embrace, natural law as positing a "brooding omni· presence in the sky." Southern Pac. Co. v. Jensen, 244 U.S. 205, 222 {1917) (Holmes, J., 1993] ON CONSTITUTIONAL POSITIVISM 855 than meets the eye. To understand why, we must consider an interpre­ tation of the natural law-positivist debate that nowadays is dismissed as mundane: "that the natural law position is merely a claim about lan­ guage and about the criteria for proper use of the word 'law' ... ." 1 Though this semantic interpretation of the natural law-positivist debate may be well known and boring, it has a significant moral implication that is widely overlooked. This implication derives from the widespread belief tha_t there is at least a prima facie moral duty to obey the law. While modern legal positivists may deny-as they must if they wish to preserve the value-neutral use of the term "law"-that there is such a duty of obedience, this denial is simply beside the point. For, so long as speaker and listeners both believe that law carries with it at least a prima facie duty of obedience-that law qua law binds in con­ science-then how we use or define the term law is not an arbitrary or value-free matter. The conclusion that a particular course of action is required by law will carry with it the perception that this action is, in a real sense, morally obligatory-at least prima facie. Schauer himself professes neutrality about the issue. He asserts that "nothing about legal positivism entails any attitude whatsoever about obedience to law."8 This claim holds, however, only if law is a strictly value-neutral concept. Only then would the mere fact that something is a valid law carry with it no duty of obedience. When, however, the popular perception that law does carry with it a duty of obedience is taken into account, then asking what counts as law, and thus as binding law (as opposed to positivist law simpliciter), is no longer a value-neutral inquiry. Consider this example: A duly enacted statute requires that people own, possess, and are proficient with handguns.9 If the fact that this statute was duly enacted says nothing about whether a citizen is bound in conscience to obey it, as Schauer maintains, then the positivists are correct in asserting both the conceptual and operational separation of law and justice. If, on the other hand, the fact that this statute was duly enacted means in the relevant community of discourse that people "ought" to obey it, then, at least prima facie, a person would be dissenting). 7. Schauer, supra note 1, at 799 (emphasis added). 8. /d. at 806 n.18. 9. Cf. Alaska Votes to Bar Towns from Regulating Guns, NY TIMES, June 6, 1982, § I, at 27 (describing Kennesaw, Georgia's ordinance requiring a head of household to own and maintain a firearm). 856 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 25:853 thought to be acting wrongly not to do so and, significantly, it may then be considered justified to coerce this person to so act. Thus, in a particular community of discourse, the positive meaning of a statute is not limited to what actions it directs (e.g., "own, possess, and be proficient with a handgun"), but implicitly includes the further proposition that "one has a moral obligation (at least prima facie) to own, possess, and be proficient with a handgun and can be sanctioned justly for disobedience." Consequently, as an operational matter, we-meaning both participants in and those observing the legal system in question-must ask whether this further proposition is true. If some person-say a sheriff-files a complaint and seeks legal sanctions10 against a person who has failed to possess a handgun, is this complaint valid? More specifically, is it valid merely because the al­ leged conduct violates a legally enacted statute? Or must considera­ tions of justice or rights be brought to bear so as to decide whether it is in fact justified to coerce a person to perform these actions? Positivists cannot use the term "law" both ways.
Recommended publications
  • The Fundamentals of Constitutional Courts
    Constitution Brief April 2017 Summary The Fundamentals of This Constitution Brief provides a basic guide to constitutional courts and the issues that they raise in constitution-building processes, and is Constitutional Courts intended for use by constitution-makers and other democratic actors and stakeholders in Myanmar. Andrew Harding About MyConstitution 1. What are constitutional courts? The MyConstitution project works towards a home-grown and well-informed constitutional A written constitution is generally intended to have specific and legally binding culture as an integral part of democratic transition effects on citizens’ rights and on political processes such as elections and legislative and sustainable peace in Myanmar. Based on procedure. This is not always true: in the People’s Republic of China, for example, demand, expert advisory services are provided it is clear that constitutional rights may not be enforced in courts of law and the to those involved in constitution-building efforts. constitution has only aspirational, not juridical, effects. This series of Constitution Briefs is produced as If a constitution is intended to be binding there must be some means of part of this effort. enforcing it by deciding when an act or decision is contrary to the constitution The MyConstitution project also provides and providing some remedy where this occurs. We call this process ‘constitutional opportunities for learning and dialogue on review’. Constitutions across the world have devised broadly two types of relevant constitutional issues based on the constitutional review, carried out either by a specialized constitutional court or history of Myanmar and comparative experience. by courts of general legal jurisdiction.
    [Show full text]
  • Nondelegation and the Unitary Executive
    NONDELEGATION AND THE UNITARY EXECUTIVE Douglas H. Ginsburg∗ Steven Menashi∗∗ Americans have always mistrusted executive power, but only re- cently has “the unitary executive” emerged as the bogeyman of Amer- ican politics. According to popular accounts, the idea of the unitary executive is one of “presidential dictatorship”1 that promises not only “a dramatic expansion of the chief executive’s powers”2 but also “a minimum of legislative or judicial oversight”3 for an American Presi- dent to exercise “essentially limitless power”4 and thereby to “destroy the balance of power shared by our three co-equal branches of gov- ernment.”5 Readers of the daily press are led to conclude the very notion of a unitary executive is a demonic modern invention of po- litical conservatives,6 “a marginal constitutional theory” invented by Professor John Yoo at UC Berkeley,7 or a bald-faced power grab con- jured up by the administration of George W. Bush,8 including, most ∗ Circuit Judge, U.S. Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit. ∗∗ Olin/Searle Fellow, Georgetown University Law Center. The authors thank Richard Ep- stein and Jeremy Rabkin for helpful comments on an earlier draft. 1 John E. Finn, Opinion, Enumerating Absolute Power? Who Needs the Rest of the Constitution?, HARTFORD COURANT, Apr. 6, 2008, at C1. 2 Tim Rutten, Book Review, Lincoln, As Defined by War, L.A. TIMES, Oct. 29, 2008, at E1. 3 Editorial, Executive Excess, GLOBE & MAIL (Toronto), Nov. 12, 2008, at A22. 4 Robyn Blumner, Once Again We’ll Be a Nation of Laws, ST.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Positivism: an Analysis of Austin and Bentham
    INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW AND LEGAL JURISPRUDENCE STUDIES, VOLUME 1, ISSUE 6 LEGAL POSITIVISM: AN ANALYSIS OF AUSTIN AND BENTHAM Authors PRAGALBH BHARDWAJ National Law University, Odisha BH-1, National Law University, Odisha, Sector 13, CDA, Cuttack, Odisha. Country-India [email protected] RISHI RAJ National Law University, Odisha BH-1, National Law University, Odisha, Sector 13, CDA, Cuttack, Odisha. Country-India [email protected] 1 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW AND LEGAL JURISPRUDENCE STUDIES, VOLUME 1, ISSUE 6 Abstract Key words- Austin, Bentham, Criticism of Positivist School, Indian Perspective of Positivist School, Legal Positivist School. The school of Legal Positivism developed over the period of 18th and 19th century through the works of influential jurists such as John Austin and Jeremey Bentham. The works of these two great jurists was mainly responsible for the Legal Positivist School to acquire such importance in the field of legal jurisprudence. Their work was taken forward by jurists such as H.L.A.Hart. Although not free from shortcomings, the Legal Positivist School is regarded as the most influential school of thought in jurisprudence. Judges have based their decisions on this school of thought across various countries, including India. Indian Judges have been greatly influenced by the thinking of legal positivists and have applied their jurisprudence while giving landmark judgements such as A.K.Gopalan v. State of Madras to name one of them. The basic idea behind legal positivists was that they considered law as it is and not what it ought to be. They separated moral principles from legal principles.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Natural Law
    4YFPMWLIHMR-RWXMXYXI W.SYVREP7IT PHILOSOPHY OF NATURAL LAW Justice K. N. Saikia Former Judge Supreme Court of India. Director General National Judicial Academy By philosophy of law, for the purpose of this article, is meant the pursuit of wisdom, truth and knowledge of law by use of reason. In other words, philosophy of law means the ratlonal investigation and study of the basic ideal and principles of law. The philosophy of natural law is the subject of this article. Longing for a Higher Law - In the human bosom there has always been a longing for a higher law than those made by the community itself. The divine theory of law, the theory of natural law, and the principles of natural justice are some theories or notions found in fulfilment of this longing. Divine laws are those ascribed to God. Divine rights of kings were supposed to have been derived from God. Laws which are claimed to be God-made, may not be amendable by man; and their reasoning and provisions also not to be ques- tioned by man. Greek thinkers from Homer to the Stoics, and reflections of Plato and Aristotle mainly provide the beginning of systematic legal thinking. In Homer, law is embodied in the themistes which the kings receive from Zeus as the divine source of all earthly justice which is still identical with order and authority. Solon the great Athenian lawgiver appeals to Dike, the daughter of Zeus, as a guarantor of justice against earthly tyranny, violation of rights and social injustice. The Code of Hamurapi was handed over by the Sun god.
    [Show full text]
  • Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (In a Constitutional Democracy)
    Georgetown University Law Center Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW 2013 Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (in a Constitutional Democracy) Imer Flores Georgetown Law Center, [email protected] Georgetown Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper No. 12-161 This paper can be downloaded free of charge from: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/1115 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2156455 Imer Flores, Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (in a Constitutional Democracy), in LAW, LIBERTY, AND THE RULE OF LAW 77-101 (Imer B. Flores & Kenneth E. Himma eds., Springer Netherlands 2013) This open-access article is brought to you by the Georgetown Law Library. Posted with permission of the author. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Legislation Commons, and the Rule of Law Commons Chapter6 Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (in a Constitutional Democracy) lmer B. Flores Tse-Kung asked, saying "Is there one word which may serve as a rule of practice for all one's life?" K'ung1u-tzu said: "Is not reciprocity (i.e. 'shu') such a word? What you do not want done to yourself, do not ckJ to others." Confucius (2002, XV, 23, 225-226). 6.1 Introduction Taking the "rule of law" seriously implies readdressing and reassessing the claims that relate it to law and liberty, in general, and to a constitutional democracy, in particular. My argument is five-fold and has an addendum which intends to bridge the gap between Eastern and Western civilizations,
    [Show full text]
  • Public Choice, Constitutional Political Economy and Law and Economics
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Research Papers in Economics 0610 PUBLIC CHOICE, CONSTITUTIONAL POLITICAL ECONOMY AND LAW AND ECONOMICS Ludwig Van den Hauwe Brussels, Belgium © Copyright 1999 Ludwig Van den Hauwe Abstract The various subdisciplines within the emerging ‘new institutionalism’ in economics all draw special attention to the legal-political constraints within which economic and political agents choose and therefore represent a return of economics to its appropriate legal foundations. By changing the name of his research programme to constitutional political economy Buchanan distanced himself from those parts of the public choice literature that remained too close to the traditional welfare economics approach. This chapter draws lessons for law and economics from recent developments in the re-emerging field of constitutional political economy. CPE compares alternative sets of institutional arrangements, in markets and the polity, and their outcomes, using ‘democratic consent’ as an internal standard of comparison. The chapter discusses the methodological foundation of the CPE approach, presents Buchanan’s reconstruction of the Coase theorem along subjectivist-contractarian lines and gives an overview of recent contributions to the literature. JEL classification: B41, D70, H10 Keywords: Constitutional Economics, Constitutional Political Economy, Public Choice, James M. Buchanan, Methodological Foundation A. The Manifold Legacy of Adam Smith 1. Introduction As the title of this chapter suggests, the new law and economics movement on the one hand and the now rapidly emerging field of constitutional political economy - as well as the somewhat older public choice branch of economics from which it emerged - on the other hand, are research traditi- ons that are in some respects genuinely related.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 1994 Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics Nelson T. Potter Jr. University of Nebraska - Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Legal Ethics and Professional Responsibility Commons, and the Legal History Commons Potter, Nelson T. Jr., "Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics" (1994). Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy. 15. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub/15 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Potter in Jarbuch für Recht und Ethik (1994) 2. Copyright 1994, Friedrich-Alexander-Universität Erlangen-Nürnberg. Used by permission. Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics Nelson Potter I. There is a passage in Immanuel Kant's general introduction to both parts of Die Metaphysik der Sitten that deserves more attention than it has received. I plan to build the present paper around the implil:ations of this passage: In all lawgiving (Gesetzgebung) (whether it prescribes for internal or external actions, and whether it prescribes them a priori by reason alone or by the choice of another) there are two elements: first, a law, which represents an action that is to be done as objectively necessary, that is, which makes the action a duty; and second, an incentive, which connects a ground for determining choice to this action subjectively with the representation of the law.
    [Show full text]
  • Keep Reading Contracts, Constitutions, and Getting The
    PAPERS Contracts, Constitutions, and Getting the Interpretation-Construction Distinction Right GREGORY KLASS* ABSTRACT Interpretation determines the meaning of a legal actor's words or other sig- ni®cant acts, construction their legal effect. Using contract law and two nine- teenth century theories of constitutional interpretation as examples, this Article advances four claims about interpretation, construction, and the relationship between the two. First, many theorists, following Francis Lieber, assume that rules of construction apply only when interpretation runs out, such as when a text's meaning is ambiguous or does not address an issue. In fact, a rule of con- struction is always necessary to determine a legal speech act's effect, including when its meaning is clear and de®nite. Construction does not supplement inter- pretation, but compliments it. Second, there exists more than one form of inter- pretation, and correspondingly more than one type of meaning. The meaning a text or other speech act has depends on the questions one asks of it. Third, which type of meaning is legally relevant depends on the applicable rule of con- struction. Rules of construction are in this sense conceptually prior to legal interpretation. This priority has important consequences for how legal rules of interpretation are justi®ed. Finally, because there exist multiple types of mean- ing, when one form of interpretation runs out, another form might step in. Whether that is so again depends on the applicable rule of construction. These four claims apply to legal interpretation and construction generally. This Article supports them with a close examination of the interpretation and construction of contractual agreements.
    [Show full text]
  • Randy E. Barnett* Whether Or Not They Are Originalists, Most Constitutional
    THE MISCONCEIVED ASSUMPTION ABOUT CONSTITUTIONAL ASSUMPTIONS Randy E. Barnett* INTRODUCTION Whether or not they are originalists, most constitutional scholars and observers assume that the basic assumptions held at the time the Constitution was enacted or amended are relevant to ascertaining its original meaning. Some originalists use constitutional assumptions to constrain judges in their interpretations of the more abstract passages of the text. Others reject originalism precisely because they object to the outmoded assumptions that prevailed at the time of enactment, and they assume that these assumptions must shape the original meaning of the text. For example, some claim that because of widespread concern about the continued vitality of the militia, the original meaning of the Second Amendment’s right to keep and bear arms is limited to those who are in service to the militia. Others think that because many in the Thirty-Ninth Congress and elsewhere assumed the continued existence of segregated government schools or the inferiority of women, the original meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment must be consistent with segregated schools and the common law rules of coverture. Still others claim that because people assumed at the time the Fourteenth Amendment was adopted that laws regulating private morality were within the police power of the states, such laws must be consistent with its original meaning. In this article, I challenge this misconceived assumption about the constitutional status of basic assumptions, which derives from a mistaken conflation of constitutions and contracts. Because the shared background assumptions of the parties are relevant to the enforcement of written contracts, it seems natural to treat written constitutions the same way.
    [Show full text]
  • Constitutional Law of the United States, by Hugh Evander Willis
    Indiana Law Journal Volume 12 Issue 4 Article 15 4-1937 Constitutional Law of the United States, by Hugh Evander Willis Glenn D. Peters Member, Hammond Bar Follow this and additional works at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj Part of the Constitutional Law Commons Recommended Citation Peters, Glenn D. (1937) "Constitutional Law of the United States, by Hugh Evander Willis," Indiana Law Journal: Vol. 12 : Iss. 4 , Article 15. Available at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj/vol12/iss4/15 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School Journals at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Indiana Law Journal by an authorized editor of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INDIAN. LAW JOURNAL BOOK REVIEW CONSTITUTIONAL LAW OF THE UNITED STATES, by Hugh Evander Willis. 1936. The Principia Press, Bloomington, Indiana. This reviewer has just finished a most interesting task, the critical reading of Dr. Willis' new book on the Constitutional Law of the United States. When one reads this book he is immediately struck with the tremendous amount of intelligent labor that has been bestowed upon it. Not only does the book evince h careful and critical study of hundreds of authorities, both State and Federal, but it also indicates a most careful analysis of political science, philosophy and psychology. Dr. Willis' approach to the subject of the Constitution is most enlightening. Having due regard to Mr. Justice Hughes' holding that the Constitution is what the judges say it is, Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Federalism and Constitutional Criminal Law Brenner M
    Hofstra Law Review Volume 46 | Issue 2 Article 6 12-1-2017 Federalism and Constitutional Criminal Law Brenner M. Fissell Maurice A. Deane School of Law at Hofstra University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/hlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Fissell, Brenner M. (2017) "Federalism and Constitutional Criminal Law," Hofstra Law Review: Vol. 46 : Iss. 2 , Article 6. Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/hlr/vol46/iss2/6 This document is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hofstra Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Fissell: Federalism and Constitutional Criminal Law FEDERALISM AND CONSTITUTIONAL CRIMINAL LAW Brenner M. Fissell* I. INTRODUCTION Over the past fifty years, the Supreme Court has created an expansive and nearly comprehensive body of constitutional criminal procedure. These are the familiar rules about police investigation and fair trials. At the same time, though, the Court has repeatedly resisted doing the same for substantive criminal law and sentencing. It has generally avoided limiting what can be a crime, how it must be defined, and how much it can be punished. As William Stuntz concluded, while "policing and the trial process" have been "aggressively" regulated, "substantive criminal law" has been essentially left "to the politicians."' It takes an entire law school course to read just the highlights of the search and seizure cases; with respect to what can be a crime and how it must be defined, though, "constitutional law places few limits .
    [Show full text]
  • REVIEW the Inescapability of Constitutional Theory
    REVIEW The Inescapability of Constitutional Theory Erwin Chemerinskyt Cosmic ConstitutionalTheory: Why Americans Are Losing Their Inalienable Right to Self-Governance J. Harvie Wilkinson III. Oxford, 2012. Pp 3, 161. INTRODUCTION The Constitution inevitably must be interpreted. There are countless issues-such as whether the president can fire cabinet officials' or rescind treaties2 or assert executive privilegea- where the document is silent, but a constitutional answer is nec- essary. So much of the Constitution is written in broad language that must be given meaning and applied to specific situations. What is "Commerce ... among the several States"N or 'liberty"B or "cruel and unusual punishments"6 or "equal protection of the laws"7-and countless other phrases-must be defined and ap- plied. The assurances of freedom and equality in the Constitution are not absolute,8 and it is necessary to decide what justifications t Founding Dean and Distinguished Professor of Law, University of California- Irvine School of Law. 1 See Myers v United States, 272 US 52, 134 (1926). 2 See Goldwater v Carter,444 US 996, 1002 (1979) (Rehnquist concurring in denial of certiorari) (positing that a challenge to the president's rescinding a treaty was nonjusticiable). 3 See United States v Nixon, 418 US 683, 706 (1974) (holding that the president may invoke executive privilege, but it must yield to other overriding needs for information). 4 US Const Art I, § 8, cl 3. See United States v Lopez, 514 US 549, 567-68 (1995) (holding that the Gun Free School Zone Act, prohibiting firearms within one-thousand feet of a school, exceeded the scope of Congress's Commerce Power).
    [Show full text]