Tury Virtual Reality System

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Tury Virtual Reality System forum Short Papers Leibniz's Palace of the Fates: A Seventeenth-Cen- tury Virtual Reality System Abstract with the problems of information flow and coordination in massively parallel systems, and devised notions of per- In the late 1600s the mathematician and philosopher Leibniz spective and harmony to solve them. VR theorists (and produced the first description of a virtual reality system. He computer scientists generally) have much to learn from described an organized system of virtual worlds available for his thought, which, though often speculative, is always human perceptual exploration, along with an interface for clearheaded and rich. The most accessible collection of exploring them. Leibniz's work on the logic of possible worlds his work is Rescher (1991);2 MacDonald-Ross (1984) has direct relevance to the conceptual foundations of virtual offers a good survey of both his life and work. reality work today. Leibniz believed there were many possible worlds and that God selected "the best of all possible worlds" for actualization. All of these possible worlds exist conceptu- The philosopher Leibniz is well known as a discoverer as ideas in God's mind. The totality of possible (along with Newton) of the calculus. It is less well ally, worlds is a system (much like the to- known that he provides what is likely the earliest descrip- logically organized tality of mathematical theorems) and constitutes a con- tion of a virtual reality system. His description is neither ceptual structure available for human exploration. For a technical specification nor a fiction, but a precise and those of us in the real world, these possible worlds are conceptually correct description of an organized system virtual realities. At the end of his ofvirtual worlds available for human perceptual explora- Theodicy (1710/1996; sees. 414-17), Leibniz allegorically describes how an tion. Here we a brief overview of the VR system provide actual human this ofvirtual Leibniz describes. being might explore system realities. In his allegory, the Greek goddess Pallas Athena Although Leibniz never built anything like the VR (the goddess ofwisdom) leads the ancient mathemati- system he describes, he did build one of the first calculat- cian Theodorus into the "palace of the fates," a kind of ing machines (which he presented to the Royal Society library containing compressed representations of all pos- in 1673). Leibniz was among the first to use the binary sible worlds. Athena says to Theodorus: number system, and the central thesis of his thought is that the world is a kind of massively parallel computing "Here are representations not only ofthat which hap- system (Leibniz, 1720/1991). Viewing the world as a pens but also of all possibilities. Jupiter, having sur- totality of synchronized but independent computing he called Leibniz was concerned agents monads,1 deeply 2. Despite the conceptual coherence of his thought, Leibniz's writ- ings are almost exclusively fragmentary. Leibniz published relatively Presence, Vol. 6. No. I. February 1997. I 33-135 little, and most of what he wrote is in the form of letters and fragmen- © / 997 by the Massachusetts Institute of Technology tary articles. His short article "Monadology" functions as a guide to the of his In Rescher's each section of the 1. Monads arc deterministic automata; in many respects the collec- entirity thought. book, is followed four to five of related material col- tion of monads is like a cellular automaton, except that each monad Monadology by pages lected from the remainder of Leibniz's The result is an ex- computes a unique function whereby it derives its present state from writings. clear and detailed of Leibniz's work that is not only its own its past states. According to Leibniz, each monad is like a tremely presentation available else. musician playing in an orchestra: the score of each musician (i.e., the anywhere function of each monad) is given to that musician prior to playing (i.e., prior to the beginning of the world) and does not change. There is no causal interaction between musicians, but their scores are so written that together they form a causally coherent whole, the symphony. This Eric Steinhart coherence is what Leibniz called preestablished harmony. A striking of Philosophy and of this is that virtual communication channels exist be- Department Religion consequence Hofstra tween all musicians (i.e., monads), such that each perceives the sym- University New York 10025 phony (i.e., collective computations) of all others from its own unique Hempstead, perspective. [email protected] Steinhart 133 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/pres.1997.6.1.133 by guest on 02 October 2021 134 PRESENCE: VOLUME 6, NUMBER I veyed them before the beginning of the existing such path has been realized. This path is the possible world, classified all the possibilities into [possible] world realized by the program execution as determined worlds... I have only to speak, and we shall see a by the user's interactions. Exactly as in a VR system, the whole world that my father [Jupiter] might have pro- totality of possible worlds in the palace of fates is interac- duced, wherein will be represented anything that can tive, in the sense that one can actively construct any pos- be asked of him and in this way one may know also sible history by asking Jupiter to reveal successively re- what would happen if any particular possibilities fined equivalence classes of possible worlds. should attain unto existence. These worlds are all In the palace of fates, a human explorer navigates by . here, that is, in ideas. ." (Rescher, 1991, p. 305; posing "What if?" questions to Jupiter. For instance, . Leibniz, 1710/1996, sec. 414) What if JFK had not been assassinated? These questions constitute the human user's input to the Leibnizian VR As might be expected, the structure of the totality of system, and Jupiter's response constitutes the system's possible worlds is complex, since every alternative out- output. Each such question causes Jupiter to reveal an come of any event determines a distinct possible world. equivalence class of alternative possible worlds (e.g., the As an image of this complexity, Leibniz describes the set of all possible worlds in which JFK had not been as- palace of fates as an elaborate system of halls and rooms, The size of this class varies with all of which contain classes of possible worlds. Though sassinated). equivalence the of the a "What if?" daunting, this complexity is easily reduced to order by vagueness question (i.e., ques- tion about the color of socks on the of considering how worlds are formed from sequences of Kennedy's day the assassination determines a set of alternative events. Such sequences are possible histories, each of probably worlds one member, which is a successive refinement ofequivalence classes of possible containing only differing in but the color of his Successive interac- possible worlds. To see how this works, consider a trivial nothing socks). tions successive refinements of the to- series of alternatives: three coin tosses. If these are all the with Jupiter yield of worlds revealed, much as a user refines a possible events there are, then there are eight possible tality possible execution choices. worlds, corresponding to the eight different paths (i.e., program's paths by making input describes to user like histories) through the three tosses. Before the first coin Leibniz Jupiter's responses input this: toss, any of these eight possible worlds is open for actu- alization, so there is an equivalence class of eight worlds. "... whenever the conditions [specified by the user's After the first four of these are available for toss, only question] are not determinate enough, there will be as after the second after the actualization; toss, only two; many such worlds differing from one another as one first one world remains—the world that has in toss, only shall wish, which will answer differently the same fact been actualized by the three tosses. Every possible question, in as many ways as possible. But ifyou refines classes of history successively equivalence possible put a case [to Jupiter] that differs from the actual worlds, beginning with all possible worlds and ending world only in one single definite thing and in its re- with the single one that history in fact actualizes. sults, a certain one of those determinate worlds will In many respects, the totality of possible worlds is thus answer you." (Rescher, 1991, p. 305; Leibniz, 1710/ like a computer program, particularly a VR program, 1996, sec. 414) and each possible world is like an execution path. Any nontrivial program defines avast multiplicity of execu- As Athena and Theodorus explore the palace of the tion paths, a multiplicity that explodes as program com- fates, their investigations become focused on a person plexity increases. At program invocation, all possible ex- named Sextus, a character in ancient Rome. Leibniz con- ecution paths are open for realization. But each tends that Sextus has many possible lives (as we all do), a successive user interaction reduces the set of execution different one in each different possible world. These paths that remain open, until at termination exactly one lives will be explored by Theodorus and Athena: Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/pres.1997.6.1.133 by guest on 02 October 2021 Steinhart 135 "I will show you some [possible worlds], wherein your finger on any line you please, Pallas said to him, shall be found, not absolutely the same Sextus [as is in and you will see represented actually in all its detail the actual world] but several Sextuses resembling that which the line broadly indicates.
Recommended publications
  • Realizing Monads
    anDrás kornai Realizing Monads ABSTrACT We reconstruct monads as cyclic finite state automata whose states are what Leibniz calls perceptions and whose transitions are automatically triggered by the next time tick he calls entelechy. This goes some way toward explaining key as- pects of the Monadology, in particular, the lack of inputs and outputs (§7) and the need for universal harmony (§59). 1. INTrODUCTION Monads are important both in category theory and in programming language de- sign, clearly demonstrating that Leibniz is greatly appreciated as the conceptual forerunner of much of abstract thought both in mathematics and in computer sci- ence. Yet we suspect that Leibniz, the engineer, designer of the Stepped reck- oner, would use the resources of the modern world to build a very different kind of monad. Throughout this paper, we confront Leibniz with our contemporary scientific understanding of the world. This is done to make sure that what we say is not “concretely empty” in the sense of Unger (2014). We are not interested in what we can say about Leibniz, but rather in what Leibniz can say about our cur- rent world model. readers expecting some glib demonstration of how our current scientific theories make Leibniz look like a fool will be sorely disappointed. Looking around, and finding a well-built Calculus ratiocinator in Turing ma- chines, pointer machines, and similar abstract models of computation, Leibniz would no doubt consider his Characteristica Universalis well realized in modern proof checkers such as Mizar, Coq, or Agda to the extent mathematical deduc- tion is concerned, but would be somewhat disappointed in their applicability to natural philosophy in general.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz and Monads
    Leibniz and Monads The Human Situaon Team Omega, Spring 2010 Dr. Cynthia Freeland Overview • Leibniz’s Life • The Rise of Modernism • Monadology 1‐30 • All about Monads Leibniz 1646‐1716 The Duchess of Orleans said of him: “It's so rare for intellectuals to be smartly dressed, and not to smell, and to understand jokes.” A contemporary descripon of Leibniz “Leibniz was a man of medium height with a stoop, broad‐shouldered but bandy‐legged, as capable of thinking for several days sing in the same chair as of travelling the roads of Europe summer and winter. He was an indefagable worker, a universal leer writer (he had more than 600 correspondents), a patriot and cosmopolitan, a great scienst, and one of the most powerful spirits of Western civilisaon.” Goried Wilhelm von Leibniz “A walking encyclopedia” – King George I Monadology, 1714 Leibniz the Polymath • Studies in university: Law, philosophy, Lan, Greek • Independent: algebra, mathemacs, physics, dynamics, opcs, tried to create a submarine • Secretary of Nuremberg Alchemical Society • Laws of moon, gravity, mechanics, dynamics, topology, geology, linguiscs • Polics, internaonal affairs, economics, coinage, watches, lamps • Traveled to Paris, London, Vienna, Italy, etc. • Invented Infinitesimal calculus, created a notaon for it d(xn) = nxn‐1dx Leibniz’s Calculang Machine Leibniz and the Prince • 1676‐1716, Librarian to the Duke of Hanover • Privy councilor to successive members of the House of Brunswick of Hanover, and friend/correspondent/teacher of successive prominent women in the family
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz's Ultimate Theory Soshichi Uchii Abstract
    Leibniz’s Ultimate Theory Soshichi Uchii Abstract This is a short summary of my new interpretation of Leibniz’s philosophy, including metaphysics and dynamics. Monadology is the core of his philosophy, but according to my interpretation, this document must be read together with his works on dynamics and geometry Analysis Situs, among others. Monadology describes the reality, the world of monads. But in addition, it also contains a theory of information in terms of the state transition of monads, together with a sketch of how that information is transformed into the phenomena via coding. I will argue that Leibniz’s program has a surprisingly wide range, from classical physics to the theories of relativity (special and general) , and extending even to quantum mechanics. 1. How should we read Monadology? Among Leibniz’s papers he completed in his last years, the one that should be regarded as containing the core of his system of knowledge is Monadology (1714). It is a theory of metaphysics, but I take it that Leibniz thought that it is the foundation of dynamics, and he envisaged that dynamics should be combined with his new geometry, called Analysis Situs. There are two firm grounds for the preceding assertion. The first is that Leibniz sketched the relationship between his metaphysics and dynamics, in the two papers New System and Specimen Dynamicum (both published in 1695; English tr. in Ariew and Garber 1989). If we wish to figure out a reasonable interpretation of Monadology, this ground must be taken very seriously. The second ground is the amazing accomplishments shown in The Metaphysical Foundations of Mathematics (written around the same time as Monadology; English tr.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz' De Arte Combinatoria
    Leibniz’ De arte combinatoria John N. Martin Department of Philosophy University of Cincinnati Cincinnati, OH 45221 [email protected] John N. Martin, 2003 Page 1 Leibniz’ De arte combinatoria I. INTRODUCTION Logicians, philosophers and to judge from the Internet even the general public are vaguely aware that Leibniz held views about logic that anticipate modern ideas of proof system and algorithm. Though there are many places in Leibniz’ works that might be cited as evidence for such claims, popular works cite virtually only two of Leibniz’ shorter papers, Characteristica universalis and De arte combinatoria. Curiously, though there are hundreds, maybe thousands, of references to these papers, nothing serious has been written in recent decades about the papers themselves that could be called a professional exegesis or discussion of their logical content. The purpose of this short paper is to remedy that lack by offering a “reconstruction” of the system Leibniz sketches in De arte combinatoria, which of the two essays is the one more focused on the notions of proof and algorithm. A point of caution about method should be made at the outset. Any modern “reconstruction” of views in the history of logic is by its nature a compromise. It is an attempt to preserve as much of the original content, including its terminology and formulas, as is possible while simultaneously meeting the standards of modern metatheory. For example, if it is possible to do justice to the original by observing standard formats, then they should be Page 2 followed. For example, if it is fair to the text, it is desirable to define the syntax inductively, state definitions set theoretically, develop notions of proof within an axiom or natural deduction system, and define semantic ideas in a recursive manner parallel to syntax.
    [Show full text]
  • Gabriel Tarde
    Gabriel Tarde Monadology and Sociology Monadology and Sociology re.press Edited & translated by Theo Lorenc Open Access Statement – Please Read This book is Open Access. This work is not simply an electronic book; it is the open access version of a work that exists in a number of forms, the traditional printed form being one of them. Copyright Notice This work is ‘Open Access’, published under a creative commons license which means that you are free to copy, distribute, display, and perform the work as long as you clearly attribute the work to the authors, that you do not use this work for any commercial gain in any form and that you in no way alter, transform or build on the work outside of its use in normal academic scholarship without express permission of the author and the publisher of this vol- ume. Furthermore, for any reuse or distribution, you must make clear to others the license terms of this work. For more information see the details of the creative commons licence at this website: http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/2.5/ This means that you can: • read and store this document free of charge • distribute it for personal use free of charge • print sections of the work for personal use • read or perform parts of the work in a context where no financial transactions take place However, you cannot: • gain financially from the work in anyway • sell the work or seek monies in relation to the distribution of the work • use the work in any commercial activity of any kind • profit a third party indirectly via use or distribution
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz and Hermeneutics
    Leibniz and Hermeneutics Leibniz and Hermeneutics Edited by Juan Antonio Nicolás, José M. Gómez Delgado and Miguel Escribano Cabeza Leibniz and Hermeneutics Edited by Juan Antonio Nicolás, José M. Gómez Delgado and Miguel Escribano Cabeza This book first published 2016 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2016 by Juan Antonio Nicolás, José M. Gómez Delgado, Miguel Escribano Cabeza and contributors All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-4438-8515-0 ISBN (13): 978-1-4438-8515-7 CONTENTS Preface ....................................................................................................... vii Part I: Leibniz and Hermeneutics Chapter One ................................................................................................ 3 The Possible Legacy of Leibniz’s Metaphysics in Hermeneutics JEAN GRONDIN Chapter Two ............................................................................................. 17 Perspective as Mediation between Interpretations JUAN A. NICOLÁS Part II: Leibniz and Heidegger Chapter Three ........................................................................................... 35 On
    [Show full text]
  • Monadology a New Translation and Guide
    Leibniz’s Monadology A New Translation and Guide Lloyd Strickland Leibniz’s Monadology A New Translation and Guide LLOYD STRICKLAND For Dan Cook and Vernon Pratt, for all of the help and support over the years: thank you © Lloyd Strickland, 2014 Edinburgh University Press Ltd The Tun - Holyrood Road, 12(2f) Jackson’s Entry, Edinburgh EH8 8PJ www.euppublishing.com Typeset in 11/13pt Ehrhardt MT Pro by Servis Filmsetting Ltd, Stockport, Cheshire and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon CR0 4YY A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 0 7486 9321 4 (hardback) ISBN 978 0 7486 9323 8 (webready PDF) ISBN 978 0 7486 9322 1 (paperback) ISBN 978 0 7486 9324 5 (epub) The right of Lloyd Strickland to be identified as Author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, and the Copyright and Related Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No. 2498). Contents Acknowledgements iv Key vi Abbreviations vii Introduction 1 About the Text and Translation 13 The Monadology 14 The Structure of the Monadology 34 The Monadology: Text with Running Commentary 39 Appendix 162 1. Theodicy 162 2. The Principles of Nature and Grace, Founded on Reason 270 3. Leibniz to Nicole Remond: Appendix on Monads 278 Glossary of Terms 280 Questions for Further Study 283 Further Reading 285 Index 292 Acknowledgements I would like to extend my warmest thanks to an anonymous reviewer for Edinburgh University Press for feedback on the entire manuscript. Parts of the commentary were incorporated into a talk given to members of the Oxford Philosophical Society in November 2013.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz on China and Christianity: the Reformation of Religion and European Ethics Through Converting China to Christianity
    Bard College Bard Digital Commons Senior Projects Spring 2016 Bard Undergraduate Senior Projects Spring 2016 Leibniz on China and Christianity: The Reformation of Religion and European Ethics through Converting China to Christianity Ela Megan Kaplan Bard College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.bard.edu/senproj_s2016 Part of the European History Commons This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Kaplan, Ela Megan, "Leibniz on China and Christianity: The Reformation of Religion and European Ethics through Converting China to Christianity" (2016). Senior Projects Spring 2016. 279. https://digitalcommons.bard.edu/senproj_s2016/279 This Open Access work is protected by copyright and/or related rights. It has been provided to you by Bard College's Stevenson Library with permission from the rights-holder(s). You are free to use this work in any way that is permitted by the copyright and related rights. For other uses you need to obtain permission from the rights- holder(s) directly, unless additional rights are indicated by a Creative Commons license in the record and/or on the work itself. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Leibniz on China and Christianity: The Reformation of Religion and European Ethics through Converting China to Christianity Senior Project submitted to The Division of Social Studies Of Bard College by Ela Megan Kaplan Annandale-on-Hudson, New York May 2016 5 Acknowledgements I would like to thank my mother, father and omniscient advisor for tolerating me for the duration of my senior project.
    [Show full text]
  • The Principles of Philosophy Known As Monadology
    The Principles of Philosophy known as Monadology G. W. Leibniz 1714 Copyright © Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. First launched: 2004 ******** 1. My topic here will be the monad, which is just a simple substance to •come into existence naturally, for that would substance. By calling it ‘simple’ I mean that it has no parts, involve its being put together, assembled, composed, and a though it can be a part of something composite. simple substance couldn’t be formed in that way because it 2. There must be simple substances, because there are has no parts. composites. A composite thing is just a collection of simple 6. So we can say that the only way for monads to begin ones that happen to have come together. or end—to come into existence or go out of existence—is 3. Something that has no parts can’t be extended, can’t have •instantaneously, being created or annihilated all at once. a shape, and can’t be split up. So monads are the true atoms Composite things, in contrast with that, can begin or end of Nature—the elements out of which everything is made.
    [Show full text]
  • Strickland Leibniz’S Monadology a New Translation and Guide
    Leibniz’s Monadology A New Translation and Guide Lloyd Strickland Leibniz’s Monadology A New Translation and Guide LLOYD STRICKLAND For Dan Cook and Vernon Pratt, for all of the help and support over the years: thank you © Lloyd Strickland, 2014 Edinburgh University Press Ltd The Tun - Holyrood Road, 12(2f) Jackson’s Entry, Edinburgh EH8 8PJ www.euppublishing.com Typeset in 11/13pt Ehrhardt MT Pro by Servis Filmsetting Ltd, Stockport, Cheshire and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon CR0 4YY A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 0 7486 9321 4 (hardback) ISBN 978 0 7486 9323 8 (webready PDF) ISBN 978 0 7486 9322 1 (paperback) ISBN 978 0 7486 9324 5 (epub) The right of Lloyd Strickland to be identified as Author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, and the Copyright and Related Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No. 2498). Contents Acknowledgements iv Key vi Abbreviations vii Introduction 1 About the Text and Translation 13 The Monadology 14 The Structure of the Monadology 34 The Monadology: Text with Running Commentary 39 Appendix 162 1. Theodicy 162 2. The Principles of Nature and Grace, Founded on Reason 270 3. Leibniz to Nicole Remond: Appendix on Monads 278 Glossary of Terms 280 Questions for Further Study 283 Further Reading 285 Index 292 Acknowledgements I would like to extend my warmest thanks to an anonymous reviewer for Edinburgh University Press for feedback on the entire manuscript. Parts of the commentary were incorporated into a talk given to members of the Oxford Philosophical Society in November 2013.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz As Idealist Donald Rutherford
    Forthcoming in Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 4 (2008). Leibniz as Idealist Donald Rutherford Leibniz has long been held to be an idealist.i Minimally, this involves the claim that, in his late writings at least, Leibniz’s fundamental ontology—his inventory of the ultimately real, independently existing things—is limited to mind-like, simple substances, or monads. This fixes one meaning of the term ‘idealism’, and considerable evidence confirms that in his late writings Leibniz is, in this sense, an idealist.ii I will call this position ‘substance idealism’: the view that the only things that meet the strictest conditions on being a substance are unextended, mind-like entities. As it stands, this way of framing the commitments of an idealist metaphysics is incomplete, for it leaves undefined the ontological status of actual or concrete matter.iii In its usual signification, ‘idealism’ designates a position according to which matter lacks a mind- independent reality; it exists only as an object of perception or thought. Thus, idealism is defined not simply in terms of what kinds of things are ontologically most basic—minds or other mental entities (ideas, forms, etc.)—but also in terms of the relation of those things to matter. Broadly speaking, for the idealist, material things exist only as appearances, ideas, or the contents of mental representations. In order to distinguish this position from substance idealism, I will refer to it as ‘matter idealism’. 1 It is commonly assumed that if Leibniz is a substance idealist, he must also be a matter idealist. He must, in other words, hold that material things are merely the contents of mental representations.
    [Show full text]
  • Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics
    THEODICY AND REASONTHEODICY Philosophica 2 — Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics, GERETTO, PERISSINOTTO CAMPOSAMPIERO, FAVARETTI and Theology in Leibniz’s Essais de Théodicée (1710) edited by Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero, Mattia Geretto, and Luigi Perissinotto Edizioni Ca’Foscari Theodicy and Reason Philosophica Collana diretta da Luigi Perissinotto Cecilia Rofena 2 Edizioni Ca’Foscari Philosophica Direttori Luigi Perissinotto (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Cecilia Rofena (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Comitato scientifico Silvana Borutti (Università degli studi di Pavia, Italia) Jean-Pierre Cometti (Université de Provence - Aix-Marseille I, France) Arnold Davidson (University of Chicago, USA) Roberta Dreon (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Giuseppe Goisis (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Daniele Goldoni (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Mauro Nobile (Università degli Studi di Milano-Bicocca, Italia) Gian Luigi Paltrinieri (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Vicente Sanfélix Vidarte (Universitat de València-Estudi General, España) Direzione e redazione Univerisità Ca’ Foscari Venezia Dipartimento di Filosofia e Beni Culturali Palazzo Malcanton Marcorà Dorsoduro 3484/D, 30123 Venezia http://edizionicafoscari.unive.it/col/dbc/10/Philosophica Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics, and Theology in Leibniz’s Essais de Théodicée (1710) edited by Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero, Mattia Geretto, and Luigi Perissinotto Venezia Edizioni Ca’ Foscari - Digital Publishing 2016 Theodicy and Reason:
    [Show full text]