Equivalence Relations and Functions

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Equivalence Relations and Functions Equivalence Relations and Functions October 15, 2013 Week 13-14 1 Equivalence Relation A relation on a set X is a subset of the Cartesian product X £X. Whenever (x; y) 2 R we write xRy, and say that x is related to y by R. For (x; y) 62 R, we write xRy6 . De¯nition 1. A relation R on a set X is said to be an equivalence relation if (a) xRx for all x 2 X (reflexive). (b) If xRy, then yRx (symmetric). (c) If xRy and yRz, then xRz (transitive). Let X be a set and R an equivalence relation on X. It is quite common to denote the equivalence relation R by » if there is only one equivalence relation to be considered. So xRy becomes x » y. For each x 2 X we de¯ne [x] = fy 2 X j y » xg; called an equivalence class of »; each element of [x] is called a represen- tative of the class [x]. The collection all equivalence classes of » is called the quotient set of X modulo », denoted X=». De¯nition 2. A partition of set X is a collection P = fA1;:::;Akg of Sk disjoint nonempty subsets of X such that X = i=1 Ai. Proposition 3. Let X be a set. If » is an equivalence relation on X, then the collection f[x]: x 2 Xg of equivalence classes of » is a partition of X. Conversely, if P = fA1;:::;Akg be a partition of X, then the relation Sk 2 R = i=1 Ai is an equivalence relation on X. 1 Example 1. For any positive integer m, the congruence relation modulo m is an equivalence relation on the set Z of integers. The quotient set of Z modulo m is Z=»= f[0]; [1];:::; [m ¡ 1]g: Example 2. Let » be a relation on R2, de¯ned by (s; t) » (u; v) if v ¡ t = 2(u ¡ s). Example 3. Let f : X ! Y be a surjective function. De¯ne a relation » on X by x1 » x2 if f(x1) = f(x2). Then » is an equivalence relation on X. Moreover, the function f~ : X=»¡! Y; [x] 7! f(x) p is a bijection. For instance, f : R2 ! R by f(x; y) = x2 + y2. 2 Function and Inverse Function De¯nition 4. Let X and Y be sets. A function from X to Y is a rule f that assigns each element x of X a single element y in Y . We write the rule as f : X ! Y , and say that x is sent to y; we also write x 7! y or y = f(x). Functions are also known as maps or mappings. De¯nition 5. Let X and Y be nonempty sets. A function f : X ! Y is said to be ² injective if distinct elements are sent to distinct elements; ² surjective if for every element y 2 Y , there is an element x 2 X such that f(x) = y; ² bijective if f is both injective and surjective. If so it is called a one- to-one correspondence. De¯nition 6. Let X : X ! Y and g : Y ! Z be functions. The composi- tion of f and g is a function g ± f : X ! Z de¯ned by (g ± f)(x) = g(f(x)) for all x 2 X: Proposition 7. Let f : X ! Y , g : Y ! Z, h : Z ! W be functions. Then the composition functions h ± (g ± f) and (h ± g) ± f are the same. 2 Proof. For each x 2 X, (h ± (g ± f))(x) = h((g ± f)(x)) = h(g(f(x))) = (h ± g)(f(x)) = ((h ± g) ± f)(x): De¯nition 8. A function f : X ! Y is said to be invertible if there is a function g : Y ! X such that (g ± f)(x) = x for all x 2 X; (f ± g)(y) = y for all y 2 Y: If so, the function g is called an inverse of f, written g = f ¡1. Proposition 9. Let f : X ! Y be a function. (a) If f is invertible, then its inverse is unique. (b) The function f is invertible if and only if f is a bijection. Proof. (a) Let g1; g2 be functions g : Y ! X such that (gi ± f)(x) = x for all x 2 X and (f ± gi)(y) = y for all y 2 Y , i = 1; 2. Since y = f(g2(y)) and g1(f(x) = x, then g1(y) = g1(f(g2(y))) = g2(y) for all y 2 Y: (b) Let g be the inverse of f. For x1; x2 2 X, if f(x1) = f(x2), then x1 = g(f(x1)) = g(f(x2)) = x2. So f is injective. For any y 2 Y , the element g(y) is sent to y, in fact, f(g(y)) = y by de¯nition of inverse. Example 4. (a) f : R ! R by f(x) = x2 is neither injective nor surjective. (b) f : R ! R by f(x) = x3 is bijective; its inverse g : R ! R is given by p g(x) = 3 x. x (c) f : R ! R+ by f(x) = e is bijective, where R+ = fx 2 R j x > 0g; and ¡1 ¡1 its inverse is f : R+ ! R is given by f (x) = ln x. 2 (d) f : R ! R¸0 by f(x) = x is surjective, where R¸0 = fx 2 R j x ¸ 0g. (e) f : R ! R by f(x) = x2 is bijective; its inverse f ¡1 : R ! R is 1 ¸0 ¸0 p + given by f ¡1(x) = x. 2 (f) f : R·0 ! R¸0 by f(x) = x bijective, where R·0 = fx 2 R j x · 0g; its ¡1 ¡1 p inverse f : R+ ! R is given by f (x) = ¡ x. 3 Example 5. (a) The function f : R ! R by f(θ) = sin θ is neither injective ¼ ¼ nor surjective. However, the function g :[¡ 2 ; 2 ] ! [¡1; 1] is bijective; ¡1 ¼ ¼ ¡1 its inverse g :[¡1; 1] ! [¡ 2 ; 2 ] is denoted by g (x) = arcsin x. (b) The function f : R ! R by f(θ) = cos θ is neither injective nor surjective. However, the function g : [0; ¼] ! [¡1; 1] is bijective; its inverse g¡1 : [¡1; 1] ! [0; ¼] is denoted by g¡1(x) = arccos x. ¼ 3¼ (c) The function f :[ 2 ; 2 ] ! [¡1; 1] by f(θ) = sin θ is bijective. Its inverse ¡1 ¼ 3¼ ¡1 ¼ f :[¡1; 1] ! [ 2 ; 2 ] is given by f (x) = 2 + arccos x. S1 ¼ ¼ (d) The function f : n=¡1(¡ 2 ; 2 ) ! R by f(θ) = tan θ is neither injective nor surjective. ¼ ¼ (e) The function f :(¡ 2 ; 2 ) ! R by f(θ) = tan θ is bijective; its inverse ¡1 ¼ ¼ ¡1 f : R ! (¡ 2 ; 2 ) is denoted by f (x) = arctan x. The function f1 : ¼ 3¼ ¡1 ¼ 3¼ ( 2 ; 2 ) ! R by f(θ) = tan θ is also bijective; its inverse f1 : R ! ( 2 ; 2 ) ¡1 is given by f1 (x) = ¼ + arctan x. Example 6. The complex exponential function f : C ! C is de¯ned by f(z) = ez, where if z is written as z = x + iy then ez = ex+iy := exeiy = ex(cos y + i sin y): The function f is injective but not surjective. Example 7. Hyperbolic functions (a) The hyperbolic sine function is de¯ned as ex ¡ e¡x sinh : R ! R; sinh(x) = 2 is bijective. Its inverse is the function p arsinh : R ! R; arsinh(x) = ln(x + x2 + 1): p Let y = 1(ex ¡e¡x). Then e2x ¡2yex ¡1 = 0. Thus ex = 1(2y § 4y2 + 4) = p 2 p 2 p y § y2 + 1. Since y2 + 1 > y and ex > 0, we must have ex = y + y2 + 1. Hence p x = ln(y + y2 + 1): (b) The hyperbolic cosine function ex + e¡x cosh : R ! R; cosh(x) = 2 4 is neither injective nor surjective. It has no inverse function! However, the restriction f : R¸0 ! [1; 1); f(x) = cosh(x) is bijective and its inverse function is given by p f ¡1 : [1; 1) ! R; f ¡1(x) = arcosh(x) = ln(x + x2 ¡ 1): p Let y = 1(ex + e¡x). Then e2x ¡ 2yex + 1 = 0. Thus ex = 1(2y § 4y2 ¡ 4) = p 2 2 p p 2 x y § y ¡ 1.p Since e goes top1 when y goes to 1 and y + 1 > y ¡ 1, 2 then 0 < y ¡ py ¡ 1 = y ¡ (y + 1)(y ¡ 1) < y ¡ (y ¡ 1) = 1, we must have ex = y + y2 ¡ 1. Hence p x = ln(y + y2 ¡ 1): The function g : R·0 ! [1; 1) by g(x) = cosh(x) is also bijective. Its inverse function is given by p ¡1 ¡1 2 g : [1; 1) ! R·0; g (x) = ¡ ln(x + x ¡ 1): (c) The hyperbolic tangent function sinh x ex ¡ e¡x e2x ¡ 1 tanh : R ! (¡1; 1); tanh = = = cosh x ex + e¡x e2x + 1 is bijective. Its inverse function is 1 1 + x artanh : (¡1; 1) ! R; artanh(x) = ln : 2 1 ¡ x e2x¡1 2x 2x 1+y 1 1+y Let y = e2x+1. Then (1 ¡ y)e = 1 + y, i.e., e = 1¡y . Thus x = 2 ln 1¡y . (d) The hyperbolic cotangent function coth : (¡1; 0) [ (0; 1) ! (¡1; ¡1) [ (1; 1); cosh x ex + e¡x e2x + 1 coth(x) = = = sinh x ex ¡ e¡x e2x ¡ 1 is bijective. Its inverse function is 1 x + 1 artanh : fx 2 R : jxj > 1g ! fx 2 R : jxj > 0g; arcoth(x) = ln : 2 x ¡ 1 Proposition 10. Let f : X ! Y be a function from a ¯nite set X to a ¯nite set Y .
Recommended publications
  • Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory
    Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory To criticize mathematics for its abstraction is to miss the point entirely. Abstraction is what makes mathematics work. If you concentrate too closely on too limited an application of a mathematical idea, you rob the mathematician of his most important tools: analogy, generality, and simplicity. – Ian Stewart Does God play dice? The mathematics of chaos In mathematics, a proof is a demonstration that, assuming certain axioms, some statement is necessarily true. That is, a proof is a logical argument, not an empir- ical one. One must demonstrate that a proposition is true in all cases before it is considered a theorem of mathematics. An unproven proposition for which there is some sort of empirical evidence is known as a conjecture. Mathematical logic is the framework upon which rigorous proofs are built. It is the study of the principles and criteria of valid inference and demonstrations. Logicians have analyzed set theory in great details, formulating a collection of axioms that affords a broad enough and strong enough foundation to mathematical reasoning. The standard form of axiomatic set theory is denoted ZFC and it consists of the Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) axioms combined with the axiom of choice (C). Each of the axioms included in this theory expresses a property of sets that is widely accepted by mathematicians. It is unfortunately true that careless use of set theory can lead to contradictions. Avoiding such contradictions was one of the original motivations for the axiomatization of set theory. 1 2 CHAPTER 1. LOGIC AND SET THEORY A rigorous analysis of set theory belongs to the foundations of mathematics and mathematical logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Surviving Set Theory: a Pedagogical Game and Cooperative Learning Approach to Undergraduate Post-Tonal Music Theory
    Surviving Set Theory: A Pedagogical Game and Cooperative Learning Approach to Undergraduate Post-Tonal Music Theory DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Angela N. Ripley, M.M. Graduate Program in Music The Ohio State University 2015 Dissertation Committee: David Clampitt, Advisor Anna Gawboy Johanna Devaney Copyright by Angela N. Ripley 2015 Abstract Undergraduate music students often experience a high learning curve when they first encounter pitch-class set theory, an analytical system very different from those they have studied previously. Students sometimes find the abstractions of integer notation and the mathematical orientation of set theory foreign or even frightening (Kleppinger 2010), and the dissonance of the atonal repertoire studied often engenders their resistance (Root 2010). Pedagogical games can help mitigate student resistance and trepidation. Table games like Bingo (Gillespie 2000) and Poker (Gingerich 1991) have been adapted to suit college-level classes in music theory. Familiar television shows provide another source of pedagogical games; for example, Berry (2008; 2015) adapts the show Survivor to frame a unit on theory fundamentals. However, none of these pedagogical games engage pitch- class set theory during a multi-week unit of study. In my dissertation, I adapt the show Survivor to frame a four-week unit on pitch- class set theory (introducing topics ranging from pitch-class sets to twelve-tone rows) during a sophomore-level theory course. As on the show, students of different achievement levels work together in small groups, or “tribes,” to complete worksheets called “challenges”; however, in an important modification to the structure of the show, no students are voted out of their tribes.
    [Show full text]
  • Pitch-Class Set Theory: an Overture
    Chapter One Pitch-Class Set Theory: An Overture A Tale of Two Continents In the late afternoon of October 24, 1999, about one hundred people were gathered in a large rehearsal room of the Rotterdam Conservatory. They were listening to a discussion between representatives of nine European countries about the teaching of music theory and music analysis. It was the third day of the Fourth European Music Analysis Conference.1 Most participants in the conference (which included a number of music theorists from Canada and the United States) had been looking forward to this session: meetings about the various analytical traditions and pedagogical practices in Europe were rare, and a broad survey of teaching methods was lacking. Most felt a need for information from beyond their country’s borders. This need was reinforced by the mobility of music students and the resulting hodgepodge of nationalities at renowned conservatories and music schools. Moreover, the European systems of higher education were on the threshold of a harmoni- zation operation. Earlier that year, on June 19, the governments of 29 coun- tries had ratifi ed the “Bologna Declaration,” a document that envisaged a unifi ed European area for higher education. Its enforcement added to the urgency of the meeting in Rotterdam. However, this meeting would not be remembered for the unusually broad rep- resentation of nationalities or for its political timeliness. What would be remem- bered was an incident which took place shortly after the audience had been invited to join in the discussion. Somebody had raised a question about classroom analysis of twentieth-century music, a recurring topic among music theory teach- ers: whereas the music of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries lent itself to general analytical methodologies, the extremely diverse repertoire of the twen- tieth century seemed only to invite ad hoc approaches; how could the analysis of 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice and Its Implications
    THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND ITS IMPLICATIONS KEVIN BARNUM Abstract. In this paper we will look at the Axiom of Choice and some of the various implications it has. These implications include a number of equivalent statements, and also some less accepted ideas. The proofs discussed will give us an idea of why the Axiom of Choice is so powerful, but also so controversial. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. The Axiom of Choice and Its Equivalents 1 2.1. The Axiom of Choice and its Well-known Equivalents 1 2.2. Some Other Less Well-known Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice 3 3. Applications of the Axiom of Choice 5 3.1. Equivalence Between The Axiom of Choice and the Claim that Every Vector Space has a Basis 5 3.2. Some More Applications of the Axiom of Choice 6 4. Controversial Results 10 Acknowledgments 11 References 11 1. Introduction The Axiom of Choice states that for any family of nonempty disjoint sets, there exists a set that consists of exactly one element from each element of the family. It seems strange at first that such an innocuous sounding idea can be so powerful and controversial, but it certainly is both. To understand why, we will start by looking at some statements that are equivalent to the axiom of choice. Many of these equivalences are very useful, and we devote much time to one, namely, that every vector space has a basis. We go on from there to see a few more applications of the Axiom of Choice and its equivalents, and finish by looking at some of the reasons why the Axiom of Choice is so controversial.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Construction of a Set Theory in Coq
    Saarland University Faculty of Natural Sciences and Technology I Department of Computer Science Masters Thesis Formal Construction of a Set Theory in Coq submitted by Jonas Kaiser on November 23, 2012 Supervisor Prof. Dr. Gert Smolka Advisor Dr. Chad E. Brown Reviewers Prof. Dr. Gert Smolka Dr. Chad E. Brown Eidesstattliche Erklarung¨ Ich erklare¨ hiermit an Eides Statt, dass ich die vorliegende Arbeit selbststandig¨ verfasst und keine anderen als die angegebenen Quellen und Hilfsmittel verwendet habe. Statement in Lieu of an Oath I hereby confirm that I have written this thesis on my own and that I have not used any other media or materials than the ones referred to in this thesis. Einverstandniserkl¨ arung¨ Ich bin damit einverstanden, dass meine (bestandene) Arbeit in beiden Versionen in die Bibliothek der Informatik aufgenommen und damit vero¨ffentlicht wird. Declaration of Consent I agree to make both versions of my thesis (with a passing grade) accessible to the public by having them added to the library of the Computer Science Department. Saarbrucken,¨ (Datum/Date) (Unterschrift/Signature) iii Acknowledgements First of all I would like to express my sincerest gratitude towards my advisor, Chad Brown, who supported me throughout this work. His extensive knowledge and insights opened my eyes to the beauty of axiomatic set theory and foundational mathematics. We spent many hours discussing the minute details of the various constructions and he taught me the importance of mathematical rigour. Equally important was the support of my supervisor, Prof. Smolka, who first introduced me to the topic and was there whenever a question arose.
    [Show full text]
  • Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses A
    EQUIVALENTS TO THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND THEIR USES A Thesis Presented to The Faculty of the Department of Mathematics California State University, Los Angeles In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Science in Mathematics By James Szufu Yang c 2015 James Szufu Yang ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii The thesis of James Szufu Yang is approved. Mike Krebs, Ph.D. Kristin Webster, Ph.D. Michael Hoffman, Ph.D., Committee Chair Grant Fraser, Ph.D., Department Chair California State University, Los Angeles June 2015 iii ABSTRACT Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses By James Szufu Yang In set theory, the Axiom of Choice (AC) was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo. It is an addition to the older Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory. We call it Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice and abbreviate it as ZFC. This paper starts with an introduction to the foundations of ZFC set the- ory, which includes the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms, partially ordered sets (posets), the Cartesian product, the Axiom of Choice, and their related proofs. It then intro- duces several equivalent forms of the Axiom of Choice and proves that they are all equivalent. In the end, equivalents to the Axiom of Choice are used to prove a few fundamental theorems in set theory, linear analysis, and abstract algebra. This paper is concluded by a brief review of the work in it, followed by a few points of interest for further study in mathematics and/or set theory. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Between the two department requirements to complete a master's degree in mathematics − the comprehensive exams and a thesis, I really wanted to experience doing a research and writing a serious academic paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Mereology Then and Now
    Logic and Logical Philosophy Volume 24 (2015), 409–427 DOI: 10.12775/LLP.2015.024 Rafał Gruszczyński Achille C. Varzi MEREOLOGY THEN AND NOW Abstract. This paper offers a critical reconstruction of the motivations that led to the development of mereology as we know it today, along with a brief description of some questions that define current research in the field. Keywords: mereology; parthood; formal ontology; foundations of mathe- matics 1. Introduction Understood as a general theory of parts and wholes, mereology has a long history that can be traced back to the early days of philosophy. As a formal theory of the part-whole relation or rather, as a theory of the relations of part to whole and of part to part within a whole it is relatively recent and came to us mainly through the writings of Edmund Husserl and Stanisław Leśniewski. The former were part of a larger project aimed at the development of a general framework for formal ontology; the latter were inspired by a desire to provide a nominalistically acceptable alternative to set theory as a foundation for mathematics. (The name itself, ‘mereology’ after the Greek word ‘µρoς’, ‘part’ was coined by Leśniewski [31].) As it turns out, both sorts of motivation failed to quite live up to expectations. Yet mereology survived as a theory in its own right and continued to flourish, often in unexpected ways. Indeed, it is not an exaggeration to say that today mereology is a central and powerful area of research in philosophy and philosophical logic. It may be helpful, therefore, to take stock and reconsider its origins.
    [Show full text]
  • P0138R2 2016-03-04 Reply-To: [email protected]
    P0138R2 2016-03-04 Reply-To: [email protected] Construction Rules for enum class Values Gabriel Dos Reis Microsoft Abstract This paper suggests a simple adjustment to the existing rules governing conversion from the underlying type of a scoped enumeration to said enumeration. This effectively supports programming styles that rely on definition of new distinct integral types out of existing integer types, without the complexity of anarchic integer conversions, while retaining all the ABI characteristics and benefits of the integer types, especially for system programming. 1 INTRODUCTION There is an incredibly useful technique for introducing a new integer type that is almost an exact copy, yet distinct type in modern C++11 programs: an enum class with an explicitly specified underlying type. Example: enum class Index : uint32_t { }; // Note: no enumerator. One can use Index as a new distinct integer type, it has no implicit conversion to anything (good!) This technique is especially useful when one wants to avoid the anarchic implicit conversions C++ inherited from C. For all practical purposes, Index acts like a "strong typedef" in C++11. There is however, one inconvenience: to construct a value of type Index, the current language spec generally requires the use a cast -- either a static_cast or a functional notation cast. This is both conceptually wrong and practically a serious impediment. Constructing an Index value out of uint32_t is not a cast, no more than we consider struct ClassIndex { uint32_t val; }; ClassIndex idx { 42 }; // OK ClassIndex idx2 = { 7 }; // OK a cast. It is a simple construction of a value of type ClassIndex, with no narrowing conversion.
    [Show full text]
  • 06. Naive Set Theory I
    Topics 06. Naive Set Theory I. Sets and Paradoxes of the Infinitely Big II. Naive Set Theory I. Sets and Paradoxes of the Infinitely Big III. Cantor and Diagonal Arguments Recall: Paradox of the Even Numbers Claim: There are just as many even natural numbers as natural numbers natural numbers = non-negative whole numbers (0, 1, 2, ..) Proof: { 0 , 1 , 2 , 3 , 4 , ............ , n , ..........} { 0 , 2 , 4 , 6 , 8 , ............ , 2n , ..........} In general: 2 criteria for comparing sizes of sets: (1) Correlation criterion: Can members of one set be paired with members of the other? (2) Subset criterion: Do members of one set belong to the other? Can now say: (a) There are as many even naturals as naturals in the correlation sense. (b) There are less even naturals than naturals in the subset sense. To talk about the infinitely Moral: notion of sets big, just need to be clear makes this clear about what’s meant by size Bolzano (1781-1848) Promoted idea that notion of infinity was fundamentally set-theoretic: To say something is infinite is “God is infinite in knowledge” just to say there is some set means with infinite members “The set of truths known by God has infinitely many members” SO: Are there infinite sets? “a many thought of as a one” -Cantor Bolzano: Claim: The set of truths is infinite. Proof: Let p1 be a truth (ex: “Plato was Greek”) Let p2 be the truth “p1 is a truth”. Let p3 be the truth “p3 is a truth”. In general, let pn be the truth “pn-1 is a truth”, for any natural number n.
    [Show full text]
  • CE160 Determinacy Lesson Plan Vukazich
    Lesson Plan Instructor: Steven Vukazich Lesson: Evaluating the Determinacy of Planar Structures Timeframe: 50 minutes Materials needed: Paper Pencil Eraser Objectives: Basic: 1. Remember the number of independent equations of equilibrium available for a general planar (two-dimensional) structure (prerequisite course CE 95) 2. Remember the number of unknown reactive forces associated with common structural supports (e.g. pin support, roller support from prerequisite course CE 95) 3. Isolate and draw a Free Body Diagram (FBD) of a structural system (prerequisite course CE 95) Advanced: 1. Identify individual “pieces” of structure required to be isolated, draw FBDs of each “piece”, and evaluate determinacy 2. Idealize and evaluate determinacy of an actual planar structure presented 3. Modify the planar process to evaluate determinacy of a general three-dimensional structure Background: Read chapter material that reviews basic objectives 1, 2, and 3; Read chapter material and notes (and possible video lecture) provided by the instructor to introduce advanced learning objective 1. Procedure [Time needed, include additional steps if needed]: Pre-Class Individual Space Activities and Resources: Steps Purpose Estimated Learning Time Objective Step 1: Review basic statics 20 minutes Basic (pre-requisite Objectives Read section in Leet text material) and to 1,2,3 introduce the new material Step 2: In depth review and 30 Basic discussion of new minutes Objectives Read instructor notes (see notes below – these material 1,2,3 could be turned into a Camtasia video) Step 3: Reinforce the 10 Basic review and minutes Objective Complete example problem in instructor notes. extension to new 3 material CE 160 Notes – Determinacy for Planar (two-dimensional) Structures Recall from statics that for a planar structure there are 3 independent equilibrium equations available to solve for unknown forces per free body diagram (FBD).
    [Show full text]
  • Math 127: Equivalence Relations
    Math 127: Equivalence Relations Mary Radcliffe 1 Equivalence Relations Relations can take many forms in mathematics. In these notes, we focus especially on equivalence relations, but there are many other types of relations (such as order relations) that exist. Definition 1. Let X; Y be sets. A relation R = R(x; y) is a logical formula for which x takes the range of X and y takes the range of Y , sometimes called a relation from X to Y . If R(x; y) is true, we say that x is related to y by R, and we write xRy to indicate that x is related to y by R. Example 1. Let f : X ! Y be a function. We can define a relation R by R(x; y) ≡ (f(x) = y). Example 2. Let X = Y = Z. We can define a relation R by R(a; b) ≡ ajb. There are many other examples at hand, such as ordering on R, multiples in Z, coprimality relationships, etc. The definition we have here is simply that a relation gives some way to connect two elements to each other, that can either be true or false. Of course, that's not a very useful thing, so let's add some conditions to make the relation carry more meaning. For this, we shall focus on relations from X to X, also called relations on X. There are several properties that will be interesting in considering relations: Definition 2. Let X be a set, and let ∼ be a relation on X. • We say that ∼ is reflexive if x ∼ x 8x 2 X.
    [Show full text]
  • Well-Orderings, Ordinals and Well-Founded Relations. an Ancient
    Well-orderings, ordinals and well-founded relations. An ancient principle of arithmetic, that if there is a non-negative integer with some property then there is a least such, is useful in two ways: as a source of proofs, which are then said to be \by induction" and as as a source of definitions, then said to be \by recursion." An early use of induction is in Euclid's proof that every integer > 2 is a product of primes, (where we take \prime" to mean \having no divisors other than itself and 1"): if some number is not, then let n¯ be the least counter-example. If not itself prime, it can be written as a product m1m2 of two strictly smaller numbers each > 2; but then each of those is a product of primes, by the minimality of n¯; putting those two products together expresses n¯ as a product of primes. Contradiction ! An example of definition by recursion: we set 0! = 1; (n + 1)! = n! × (n + 1): A function defined for all non-negative integers is thereby uniquely specified; in detail, we consider an attempt to be a function, defined on a finite initial segment of the non-negative integers, which agrees with the given definition as far as it goes; if some integer is not in the domain of any attempt, there will be a least such; it cannot be 0; if it is n + 1, the recursion equation tells us how to extend an attempt defined at n to one defined at n + 1. So no such failure exists; we check that if f and g are two attempts and both f(n) and g(n) are defined, then f(n) = g(n), by considering the least n where that might fail, and again reaching a contradiction; and so, there being no disagreement between any two attempts, the union of all attempts will be a well-defined function, which is familiar to us as the factorial function.
    [Show full text]