Classification by Decomposition a Partitioning of the Space of 2 2

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Classification by Decomposition a Partitioning of the Space of 2 2 Classification by Decomposition A Partitioning of the Space of 2 × 2 Symmetric Games Department of Mathematics, Linköping University Mikael Böörs, Tobias Wängberg LiTH-MAT-EX–2017/10—SE Credits: 16 hp Level: G2 Supervisor: Tom Everitt, Marcus Hutter, Computer Science Department, Australian National University Examiner: Martin Singull, Department of Mathematics, Linköping University Linköping: May 2017 Abstract Game theory is the study of strategic interaction between rational agents. The need for understanding interaction arises in many different fields, such as: eco- nomics, psychology, philosophy, computer science and biology. The purpose of game theory is to analyse the outcomes and strategies of these interactions, in mathematical models called games. Some of these games have stood out from the rest, e.g. Prisoner’s Dilemma, Chicken and Stag Hunt. These games, com- monly referred to as the standard games, have attracted interest from many fields of research. In order to understand why these games are interesting and how they differ from each other and other games, many have attempted to sort games into interestingly different classes. In this thesis some already existing classifications are reviewed based on their mathematical structure and how well justified they are. Emphasis is put on mathematical simplicity because it makes the classification more generalisable to larger game spaces. From this review we conclude that none of the classifications captures both of these aspects. We therefore propose a classification of symmetric 2×2 games based on decomposi- tion. We show that our proposed method captures everything that the previous classifications capture. Our method arguably explains the interesting differ- ences between the games, and we justify this claim by computer experiments. Moreover it has a simple mathematical structure. We also provide some results concerning the size of different game spaces. Keywords: Game theory, Classification, 2 × 2 Games, Symmetric games, Decomposi- tion, Partition, Number of Games URL for electronic version: http://urn.kb.se/resolve?urn=urn:nbn:se:liu:diva-137991 Böörs, Wängberg, 2017. iii Acknowledgements First and foremost we would like to express our deep gratitude to our supervi- sors Tom Everitt and Dr. Marcus Hutter at the Australian National University for inviting us to write this thesis under their superior guidance and for their enthusiasm about this project. We would also like to thank our examiner Dr. Martin Singull at Linköping University for taking the time to read and examine this thesis. Johan Persson deserves a special thanks both for opposing our thesis and for his personal friendship. Also our fantastic classmates Erik Landstedt and André Malm deserve a special thanks for their highly valued friendship and for their companionship through many late nights of studying. My personal thanks goes to my family, my close friends and everyone else who have supported me and brightened my days throughout the years - you know who you are. -Mikael Böörs Apart from those mentioned earlier, I wish to also express my profound gratitude towards my family and friends. You have always been there to support me throughout the years. No accomplishment would have been possible without you. Thank you. -Tobias Wängberg Böörs, Wängberg, 2017. v Nomenclature The notation used in the thesis. Symbol Explanation R; N; ::: set of real,natural numbers k; l 2 N indices for the natural numbers i; j 2 N indices for players ui payoff function for player i U set of payoff functions Ai set of actions available to player i a action profile si strategy of player i Si set of strategies of player i s strategy profile S set of strategy profiles 2S Powerset of a set S Γ(G) The mixed extension of a game G Σi set of probability distributions over Si Σ set of mixed strategy profiles σi mixed strategy of player i σ mixed strategy profile Pi payoff matrix of player i G game end of proof P probability ~v vector ∼ strategical equivalence Böörs, Wängberg, 2017. vii viii NE Nash equilibrium HO Huertas optimality PO Pareto optimality zk Conflict parameter ck Common interest parameter Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Background 3 2.1 Game Theory . .3 2.1.1 Introduction to Game Theory . .3 2.1.2 Strategic Games and Equilibria . .5 2.1.3 Zero-Sum Game . .8 2.1.4 Mixed Strategies . 10 2.1.5 Pareto Optimality . 13 2.1.6 2 × 2 Games . 14 2.1.7 Standard 2 × 2 Games . 18 2.2 Classification of Games . 24 2.2.1 Classification of all ordinal 2 × 2 games by Rapoport, Guyer, and Gordon . 25 2.2.2 A Geometric Classification System for 2 × 2 Inverval- Symmetric Games, (Harris, 1969) . 29 2.2.3 A Classification of 2 × 2 Bimatrix Games (Borm, 1987) . 32 2.2.4 A Cartography for 2 × 2 Symmetric Games (Huertas- Rosero, 2003) . 41 2.2.5 A Topologically-Based Classification of the 2 × 2 Ordinal Games (Robinson and Goforth, 2003) . 49 2.2.6 Analysis . 53 3 Results 55 3.1 Classification by Decomposition . 55 3.1.1 Decomposition of Symmetric 2 × 2 Games . 55 3.1.2 Stereographic Projection . 59 3.2 Nash and Huertas Optimality . 62 3.3 Deterministic and Non-deterministic Classes . 69 Böörs, Wängberg, 2017. ix x Contents 3.4 Analysis of the Regions . 74 3.4.1 Stronger Zero-Sum . 78 3.4.2 Weaker Zero-Sum . 83 3.4.3 Mixed Strength . 87 3.4.4 Comparison Between the Standard Game Regions . 92 3.4.5 Conclusions . 93 3.5 Experimental Analysis . 93 3.5.1 Experiment Design . 93 3.5.2 Analysis of Action Frequencies . 97 3.5.3 Analysis of Strategy Frequencies . 105 3.6 Analysis of the Standard Game Regions . 107 3.6.1 Analysis of the Prisoner’s Dilemma Regions . 108 3.6.2 Analysis of the Stag Hunt Regions . 111 3.6.3 Analysis of the Chicken Regions . 112 3.6.4 Analysis of the Leader and Hero Regions . 113 3.7 Comparison with Reviewed Classifications . 114 3.8 Number of m × n Games . 117 3.8.1 Distinct players . 117 3.8.2 Non-distinct players . 119 4 Discussion 123 4.1 Outlook on Further Topics . 126 A Detailed Class Description 133 B Computer Experiment Plots 139 C Some Results Regarding the Number of Non-Strictly Ordinal Games With Distinct Players 143 Chapter 1 Introduction Game theory is described as the study of strategic interaction between ratio- nal agents. The first underlying assumption that the interactions are strategic means that the choices of the agents involved in the interaction affects each other and that they are aware of this. They therefore have to reason strategi- cally about not only their own action, but also about the actions of others. The second assumption states that the agent is rational. An agent is rational if it always takes an action which maximises its expected utility, according to the agents subjective preferences and information. The purpose of game theory is to model complex real world situations as abstract models with strategic inter- action between rational agents. These models are referred to as games, and are used to understand how agents will interact in various situations. In order to fully understand games, they need to be classified based on prop- erties that capture the essence of these games. A classification is a systematic way to investigate the properties of different games. If a game is to be useful, we need to understand what kind of real world situation it can represent. To achieve this we make up stories that enables us to relate these games to different real world scenarios, e.g. the story of the prisoners in the Prisoner’s Dilemma. A lot of different stories could, however, describe the same game. Therefore the essential properties of the game needs to be identified, upon which a classifi- cation is built. There is a need to understand what games are essentially the same and what games are different, and why. A classification of games is one approach to achieving this goal. An interesting question in game theory is what makes a game interesting and how the properties that define an interesting game can be formalised. When Böörs, Wängberg, 2017. 1 2 Chapter 1. Introduction defining a classification of games the goal is to divide games with different kinds of interesting properties into different classes. Therefore, before one defines a classification, the natural question to answer is what properties are interesting? and perhaps even more important, why do we find these properties interesting? We suggest that for a classification to be truly useful, it should have: 1. simple mathematical structure, 2. a priori justified conditions, 3. a posteriori justified conditions and 4. no ad hoc conditions. We motivate this as follows. We consider how well they justify their conditions a priori, that is how well the authors of the classification motivate their choice of conditions used to classify. There should also be some justification of whether the resulting regions captures all aspects which are considered interesting about the games. We call this a posteriori justification. Furthermore, most classifica- tions classify the smallest form of non-trivial games, that is the 2 × 2 games. These are games with only two players with two actions each. These games do, however, only make up a small fraction of the total amount of games. Hence, it is important that the classification can be generalised by adding, for example, more players. We therefore advocate that a classification should have a simple mathematical structure. A lot of research has already been done on the topic of classifying games. When reviewing previous research we argue that the previous classifications fail, on at least some account, to fulfil the conditions stated above.
Recommended publications
  • Labsi Working Papers
    UNIVERSITY OF SIENA S.N. O’ H iggins Arturo Palomba Patrizia Sbriglia Second Mover Advantage and Bertrand Dynamic Competition: An Experiment May 2010 LABSI WORKING PAPERS N. 28/2010 SECOND MOVER ADVANTAGE AND BERTRAND DYNAMIC COMPETITION: AN EXPERIMENT § S.N. O’Higgins University of Salerno [email protected] Arturo Palomba University of Naples II [email protected] Patrizia Sbriglia §§ University of Naples II [email protected] Abstract In this paper we provide an experimental test of a dynamic Bertrand duopolistic model, where firms move sequentially and their informational setting varies across different designs. Our experiment is composed of three treatments. In the first treatment, subjects receive information only on the costs and demand parameters and on the price’ choices of their opponent in the market in which they are positioned (matching is fixed); in the second and third treatments, subjects are also informed on the behaviour of players who are not directly operating in their market. Our aim is to study whether the individual behaviour and the process of equilibrium convergence are affected by the specific informational setting adopted. In all treatments we selected students who had previously studied market games and industrial organization, conjecturing that the specific participants’ expertise decreased the chances of imitation in treatment II and III. However, our results prove the opposite: the extra information provided in treatment II and III strongly affects the long run convergence to the market equilibrium. In fact, whilst in the first session, a high proportion of markets converge to the Nash-Bertrand symmetric solution, we observe that a high proportion of markets converge to more collusive outcomes in treatment II and more competitive outcomes in treatment III.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Sequential Games
    1 Sequential Games We call games where players take turns moving “sequential games”. Sequential games consist of the same elements as normal form games –there are players, rules, outcomes, and payo¤s. However, sequential games have the added element that history of play is now important as players can make decisions conditional on what other players have done. Thus, if two people are playing a game of Chess the second mover is able to observe the …rst mover’s initial move prior to making his initial move. While it is possible to represent sequential games using the strategic (or matrix) form representation of the game it is more instructive at …rst to represent sequential games using a game tree. In addition to the players, actions, outcomes, and payo¤s, the game tree will provide a history of play or a path of play. A very basic example of a sequential game is the Entrant-Incumbent game. The game is described as follows: Consider a game where there is an entrant and an incumbent. The entrant moves …rst and the incumbent observes the entrant’sdecision. The entrant can choose to either enter the market or remain out of the market. If the entrant remains out of the market then the game ends and the entrant receives a payo¤ of 0 while the incumbent receives a payo¤ of 2. If the entrant chooses to enter the market then the incumbent gets to make a choice. The incumbent chooses between …ghting entry or accommodating entry. If the incumbent …ghts the entrant receives a payo¤ of 3 while the incumbent receives a payo¤ of 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Finitely Repeated Games
    Repeated games 1: Finite repetition Universidad Carlos III de Madrid 1 Finitely repeated games • A finitely repeated game is a dynamic game in which a simultaneous game (the stage game) is played finitely many times, and the result of each stage is observed before the next one is played. • Example: Play the prisoners’ dilemma several times. The stage game is the simultaneous prisoners’ dilemma game. 2 Results • If the stage game (the simultaneous game) has only one NE the repeated game has only one SPNE: In the SPNE players’ play the strategies in the NE in each stage. • If the stage game has 2 or more NE, one can find a SPNE where, at some stage, players play a strategy that is not part of a NE of the stage game. 3 The prisoners’ dilemma repeated twice • Two players play the same simultaneous game twice, at ! = 1 and at ! = 2. • After the first time the game is played (after ! = 1) the result is observed before playing the second time. • The payoff in the repeated game is the sum of the payoffs in each stage (! = 1, ! = 2) • Which is the SPNE? Player 2 D C D 1 , 1 5 , 0 Player 1 C 0 , 5 4 , 4 4 The prisoners’ dilemma repeated twice Information sets? Strategies? 1 .1 5 for each player 2" for each player D C E.g.: (C, D, D, C, C) Subgames? 2.1 5 D C D C .2 1.3 1.5 1 1.4 D C D C D C D C 2.2 2.3 2 .4 2.5 D C D C D C D C D C D C D C D C 1+1 1+5 1+0 1+4 5+1 5+5 5+0 5+4 0+1 0+5 0+0 0+4 4+1 4+5 4+0 4+4 1+1 1+0 1+5 1+4 0+1 0+0 0+5 0+4 5+1 5+0 5+5 5+4 4+1 4+0 4+5 4+4 The prisoners’ dilemma repeated twice Let’s find the NE in the subgames.
    [Show full text]
  • Israel-Palestine Through the Lens of Game Theory
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Economics Department Working Paper Series Economics 2021 Land for peace? Israel-Palestine through the lens of game theory Amal Ahmad Department of Economics, University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/econ_workingpaper Part of the Economics Commons Recommended Citation Ahmad, Amal, "Land for peace? Israel-Palestine through the lens of game theory" (2021). Economics Department Working Paper Series. 301. https://doi.org/10.7275/21792057 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Economics at ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Economics Department Working Paper Series by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Land for peace? Israel-Palestine through the lens of game theory Amal Ahmad∗ February 2021 Abstract Why have Israel and the Palestinians failed to implement a \land for peace" solution, along the lines of the Oslo Accords? This paper studies the applica- tion of game theory to this question. I show that existing models of the conflict largely rely on unrealistic assumptions about what the main actors are trying to achieve. Specifically, they assume that Israel is strategically interested in withdrawing from the occupied territories pending resolvable security concerns but that it is obstructed from doing so by violent Palestinians with other objec- tives. I use historical analysis along with bargaining theory to shed doubt on this assumption, and to argue that the persistence of conflict has been aligned with, not contrary to, the interests of the militarily powerful party, Israel.
    [Show full text]
  • Collusion Constrained Equilibrium
    Theoretical Economics 13 (2018), 307–340 1555-7561/20180307 Collusion constrained equilibrium Rohan Dutta Department of Economics, McGill University David K. Levine Department of Economics, European University Institute and Department of Economics, Washington University in Saint Louis Salvatore Modica Department of Economics, Università di Palermo We study collusion within groups in noncooperative games. The primitives are the preferences of the players, their assignment to nonoverlapping groups, and the goals of the groups. Our notion of collusion is that a group coordinates the play of its members among different incentive compatible plans to best achieve its goals. Unfortunately, equilibria that meet this requirement need not exist. We instead introduce the weaker notion of collusion constrained equilibrium. This al- lows groups to put positive probability on alternatives that are suboptimal for the group in certain razor’s edge cases where the set of incentive compatible plans changes discontinuously. These collusion constrained equilibria exist and are a subset of the correlated equilibria of the underlying game. We examine four per- turbations of the underlying game. In each case,we show that equilibria in which groups choose the best alternative exist and that limits of these equilibria lead to collusion constrained equilibria. We also show that for a sufficiently broad class of perturbations, every collusion constrained equilibrium arises as such a limit. We give an application to a voter participation game that shows how collusion constraints may be socially costly. Keywords. Collusion, organization, group. JEL classification. C72, D70. 1. Introduction As the literature on collective action (for example, Olson 1965) emphasizes, groups often behave collusively while the preferences of individual group members limit the possi- Rohan Dutta: [email protected] David K.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 16 Oligopoly and Game Theory Oligopoly Oligopoly
    Chapter 16 “Game theory is the study of how people Oligopoly behave in strategic situations. By ‘strategic’ we mean a situation in which each person, when deciding what actions to take, must and consider how others might respond to that action.” Game Theory Oligopoly Oligopoly • “Oligopoly is a market structure in which only a few • “Figuring out the environment” when there are sellers offer similar or identical products.” rival firms in your market, means guessing (or • As we saw last time, oligopoly differs from the two ‘ideal’ inferring) what the rivals are doing and then cases, perfect competition and monopoly. choosing a “best response” • In the ‘ideal’ cases, the firm just has to figure out the environment (prices for the perfectly competitive firm, • This means that firms in oligopoly markets are demand curve for the monopolist) and select output to playing a ‘game’ against each other. maximize profits • To understand how they might act, we need to • An oligopolist, on the other hand, also has to figure out the understand how players play games. environment before computing the best output. • This is the role of Game Theory. Some Concepts We Will Use Strategies • Strategies • Strategies are the choices that a player is allowed • Payoffs to make. • Sequential Games •Examples: • Simultaneous Games – In game trees (sequential games), the players choose paths or branches from roots or nodes. • Best Responses – In matrix games players choose rows or columns • Equilibrium – In market games, players choose prices, or quantities, • Dominated strategies or R and D levels. • Dominant Strategies. – In Blackjack, players choose whether to stay or draw.
    [Show full text]
  • On Some Winning Strategies for the Iterated Prisoner's Dilemma Or Mr
    Chapter 1 On some winning strategies for the Iterated Prisoner’s Dilemma or Mr. Nice Guy and the Cosa Nostra Wolfgang Slany Wolfgang Kienreich Technical University Know-Center Graz, Austria Graz, Austria [email protected] [email protected] We submitted two kinds of strategies to the iterated prisoner’s dilemma (IPD) competitions organized by Graham Kendall, Paul Darwen and Xin Yao in 2004 and 20051. Our strategies performed exceedingly well in both years. One type is an intelligent and optimistic enhanced version of the well known TitForTat strategy which we named OmegaTitForTat. It recognizes common behaviour patterns and detects and recovers from repairable mutual defect deadlock situations, otherwise behaving much like TitForTat. OmegaTitForTat was placed as the first or second individual strategy in both competitions in the leagues in which it took part. The second type consists of a set of strategies working together as a team. The call for participation of the competitions explicitly stated that cooperative strategies would be allowed to participate. This allowed a form of implicit communication which is not in keeping with the original IPD idea, but represents a natural extension to the study of cooperative behaviour in reality as it is aimed at through the study of the simple, yet 1 See http://www.prisoners-dilemma.com/ for more details. 1 2 Book Title insightful, iterated prisoner’s dilemma model. Indeed, one’s behaviour towards another person in reality is very often influenced by one’s relation to the other person. In particular, we submitted three sets of strategies that work together as groups.
    [Show full text]
  • Order and Containment in Concurrent System Design Copyright Fall 2000
    Order and Containment in Concurrent System Design Copyright Fall 2000 by John Sidney Davis II 1 Abstract Order and Containment in Concurrent System Design by John Sidney Davis II Doctor of Philosophy in Engineering-Electrical Engineering and Computer Science University of California at Berkeley Professor Edward A. Lee, Chair This dissertation considers the dif®culty of modeling and designing complex, concurrent systems. The term concurrent is used here to mean a system consisting of a network of commu- nicating components. The term complex is used here to mean a system consisting of components with different models of computation such that the communication between different components has different semantics according to the respective interacting models of computation. Modeling and designing a concurrent system requires a clear understanding of the types of relationships that exist between the components found within a concurrent system. Two partic- ularly important types of relationships found in concurrent systems are the order relation and the containment relation. The order relation represents the relative timing of component actions within a concurrent system. The containment relation facilitates human understanding of a system by ab- stracting a system's components into layers of visibility. The consequence of improper management of the order and containment relationships in a complex, concurrent system is deadlock. Deadlock is an undesirable halting of a system's execution and is the most challenging type of concurrent system error to debug. The contents of this disserta- tion show that no methodology is currently available that can concisely, accurately and graphically 2 model both the order and containment relations found in complex, concurrent systems.
    [Show full text]
  • Managing Coopetition: Is Transparency a Fallacy Or a Mandatory Condition? a Case Study of a Coopetition Project with an Opportunistic Partner
    XXVIe Conférence Internationale de Management Stratégique Managing coopetition: Is transparency a fallacy or a mandatory condition? A case study of a coopetition project with an opportunistic partner Sea Matilda Bez Université de Montpellier (MOMA) et Université Paris-Dauphine (PSL) [email protected] Frédéric Le Roy Université de Montpellier (MOMA) et Montpellier Business School [email protected] Stéphanie Dameron Université Paris-Dauphine (PSL) [email protected] Abstract : We investigate why and how knowledge transparency between competitors are needed for radical innovation. Previous scholars considered that coopetition (i.e. collaboration between competing firms) could not be a suitable strategy. Knowledge transparency invites opportunism. Thus, even for a radical innovation purpose, being highly transparent with a competitor is a fallacy. Our research goes beyond this specific approach of coopetition and reveals that firms can preserve transparency even if the partners behave opportunistically. We develop counter-intuitive propositions based on a conceptual discussion followed by insight from an extreme case study of a pharmaceutical company opening its innovation project to a competitor who behaves opportunistically (i.e. the Plavix). Our study mainly highlights that firms need to fight against the intuitive reaction of reducing transparency when the partner behaves opportunistically. Reducing the transparency inevitably leads to “shooting itself in the foot” because the reduction of transparency of one partner leads to the destruction of any possibility to create a radical innovation. Moreover, our research represents interesting guidelines for top managers by : (1) confirming that coopetition strategies are relevant in addressing the challenges of radical innovation, and (2) highlighting a specific organization design to manage transparency in a coopetitive project.
    [Show full text]
  • Cooperation Spillovers in Coordination Games*
    Cooperation Spillovers in Coordination Games* Timothy N. Casona, Anya Savikhina, and Roman M. Sheremetab aDepartment of Economics, Krannert School of Management, Purdue University, 403 W. State St., West Lafayette, IN 47906-2056, U.S.A. bArgyros School of Business and Economics, Chapman University, One University Drive, Orange, CA 92866, U.S.A. November 2009 Abstract Motivated by problems of coordination failure observed in weak-link games, we experimentally investigate behavioral spillovers for order-statistic coordination games. Subjects play the minimum- and median-effort coordination games simultaneously and sequentially. The results show the precedent for cooperative behavior spills over from the median game to the minimum game when the games are played sequentially. Moreover, spillover occurs even when group composition changes, although the effect is not as strong. We also find that the precedent for uncooperative behavior does not spill over from the minimum game to the median game. These findings suggest guidelines for increasing cooperative behavior within organizations. JEL Classifications: C72, C91 Keywords: coordination, order-statistic games, experiments, cooperation, minimum game, behavioral spillover Corresponding author: Timothy Cason, [email protected] * We thank Yan Chen, David Cooper, John Duffy, Vai-Lam Mui, seminar participants at Purdue University, and participants at Economic Science Association conferences for helpful comments. Any remaining errors are ours. 1. Introduction Coordination failure is often the reason for the inefficient performance of many groups, ranging from small firms to entire economies. When agents’ actions have strategic interdependence, even when they succeed in coordinating they may be “trapped” in an equilibrium that is objectively inferior to other equilibria. Coordination failure and inefficient coordination has been an important theme across a variety of fields in economics, ranging from development and macroeconomics to mechanism design for overcoming moral hazard in teams.
    [Show full text]
  • 570: Minimax Sample Complexity for Turn-Based Stochastic Game
    Minimax Sample Complexity for Turn-based Stochastic Game Qiwen Cui1 Lin F. Yang2 1School of Mathematical Sciences, Peking University 2Electrical and Computer Engineering Department, University of California, Los Angeles Abstract guarantees are rather rare due to complex interaction be- tween agents that makes the problem considerably harder than single agent reinforcement learning. This is also known The empirical success of multi-agent reinforce- as non-stationarity in MARL, which means when multi- ment learning is encouraging, while few theoret- ple agents alter their strategies based on samples collected ical guarantees have been revealed. In this work, from previous strategy, the system becomes non-stationary we prove that the plug-in solver approach, proba- for each agent and the improvement can not be guaranteed. bly the most natural reinforcement learning algo- One fundamental question in MBRL is that how to design rithm, achieves minimax sample complexity for efficient algorithms to overcome non-stationarity. turn-based stochastic game (TBSG). Specifically, we perform planning in an empirical TBSG by Two-players turn-based stochastic game (TBSG) is a two- utilizing a ‘simulator’ that allows sampling from agents generalization of Markov decision process (MDP), arbitrary state-action pair. We show that the em- where two agents choose actions in turn and one agent wants pirical Nash equilibrium strategy is an approxi- to maximize the total reward while the other wants to min- mate Nash equilibrium strategy in the true TBSG imize it. As a zero-sum game, TBSG is known to have and give both problem-dependent and problem- Nash equilibrium strategy [Shapley, 1953], which means independent bound.
    [Show full text]
  • Formation of Coalition Structures As a Non-Cooperative Game
    Formation of coalition structures as a non-cooperative game Dmitry Levando, ∗ Abstract We study coalition structure formation with intra and inter-coalition externalities in the introduced family of nested non-cooperative si- multaneous finite games. A non-cooperative game embeds a coalition structure formation mechanism, and has two outcomes: an alloca- tion of players over coalitions and a payoff for every player. Coalition structures of a game are described by Young diagrams. They serve to enumerate coalition structures and allocations of players over them. For every coalition structure a player has a set of finite strategies. A player chooses a coalition structure and a strategy. A (social) mechanism eliminates conflicts in individual choices and produces final coalition structures. Every final coalition structure is a non-cooperative game. Mixed equilibrium always exists and consists arXiv:2107.00711v1 [cs.GT] 1 Jul 2021 of a mixed strategy profile, payoffs and equilibrium coalition struc- tures. We use a maximum coalition size to parametrize the family ∗Moscow, Russian Federation, independent. No funds, grants, or other support was received. Acknowledge: Nick Baigent, Phillip Bich, Giulio Codognato, Ludovic Julien, Izhak Gilboa, Olga Gorelkina, Mark Kelbert, Anton Komarov, Roger Myerson, Ariel Rubinstein, Shmuel Zamir. Many thanks for advices and for discussion to participants of SIGE-2015, 2016 (an earlier version of the title was “A generalized Nash equilibrium”), CORE 50 Conference, Workshop of the Central European Program in Economic Theory, Udine (2016), Games 2016 Congress, Games and Applications, (2016) Lisbon, Games and Optimization at St Etienne (2016). All possible mistakes are only mine. E-mail for correspondence: dlevando (at) hotmail.ru.
    [Show full text]