Infinite Populations, Choice and Determinacy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Infinite Populations, Choice and Determinacy infinite populations, choice and determinacy tadeusz litak informatik 8 FAU erlangen-nurnberg¨ 1/54 By all means mathematicians should learn all the pure mathematics they want. But they must also learn applications. Get to be an expert in either the social sciences or in computer science. John Kemeny why am I giving this talk? 2/54 why am I giving this talk? By all means mathematicians should learn all the pure mathematics they want. But they must also learn applications. Get to be an expert in either the social sciences or in computer science. John Kemeny 2/54 3/54 Logics for Social Behaviour Workshop: 10 - 14 November 2014, Leiden, the Netherlands Scientific • Frederik Herzberg, Bielefeld U Organizers • Alexander Kurz, U Leicester • Alessandra Palmigiano, TU Delft Invited • Samson Abramsky, U Oxford Speakers • Bob Coecke, U Oxford The Lorentz Center is an international • Martin Hyland, U Cambridge center in the sciences. Its aim is to • Philippe Mongin, CNRS Paris organize workshops for scientists in an atmosphere that fosters collaborative • Ariel Rubinstein, U Tel Aviv work, discussions and interactions. • Carl Wagner, U Tennessee For registration see: www.lorentzcenter.nl • Viktor Winschel, U Mannheim Academic fencing in Göttingen, Germany (1847). Poster design: SuperNova Studios . NL a few years ago I was invited to some meetings on Logics for Social Behaviour ... but seriously, why? 4/54 Logics for Social Behaviour Workshop: 10 - 14 November 2014, Leiden, the Netherlands Scientific • Frederik Herzberg, Bielefeld U Organizers • Alexander Kurz, U Leicester • Alessandra Palmigiano, TU Delft Invited • Samson Abramsky, U Oxford Speakers • Bob Coecke, U Oxford The Lorentz Center is an international • Martin Hyland, U Cambridge center in the sciences. Its aim is to • Philippe Mongin, CNRS Paris organize workshops for scientists in an atmosphere that fosters collaborative • Ariel Rubinstein, U Tel Aviv work, discussions and interactions. • Carl Wagner, U Tennessee For registration see: www.lorentzcenter.nl • Viktor Winschel, U Mannheim Academic fencing in Göttingen, Germany (1847). Poster design: SuperNova Studios . NL but seriously, why? a few years ago I was invited to some meetings on Logics for Social Behaviour ... 4/54 I I didn’t know much about social choice at that time or set theory, for that matter. and it’s not that I know that much more now btw I but I got really bothered about importance of a surprisingly large industry, whose existence I discovered at those meetings I the original idea, I guess, was to have a look at coalgebraic/algebraic logic for preference aggregation more about this business later 5/54 I but I got really bothered about importance of a surprisingly large industry, whose existence I discovered at those meetings I the original idea, I guess, was to have a look at coalgebraic/algebraic logic for preference aggregation more about this business later I I didn’t know much about social choice at that time or set theory, for that matter. and it’s not that I know that much more now btw 5/54 I the original idea, I guess, was to have a look at coalgebraic/algebraic logic for preference aggregation more about this business later I I didn’t know much about social choice at that time or set theory, for that matter. and it’s not that I know that much more now btw I but I got really bothered about importance of a surprisingly large industry, whose existence I discovered at those meetings 5/54 6/54 I and now I got invited to give a talk in Freiburg about that piece . I . so, without further ado, what is this industry about? I well, formal economists have surprisingly often some use for infinite collections of agents or infinite populations I that, in itself, may be defensible in certain contexts we will briefly overview some of them in the next slide I the problem lies in how they handle them and what they prove I and then I got invited to submit a paper to a special issue of Studia Logica ... 7/54 I . so, without further ado, what is this industry about? I well, formal economists have surprisingly often some use for infinite collections of agents or infinite populations I that, in itself, may be defensible in certain contexts we will briefly overview some of them in the next slide I the problem lies in how they handle them and what they prove I and then I got invited to submit a paper to a special issue of Studia Logica ... I and now I got invited to give a talk in Freiburg about that piece . 7/54 I well, formal economists have surprisingly often some use for infinite collections of agents or infinite populations I that, in itself, may be defensible in certain contexts we will briefly overview some of them in the next slide I the problem lies in how they handle them and what they prove I and then I got invited to submit a paper to a special issue of Studia Logica ... I and now I got invited to give a talk in Freiburg about that piece . I . so, without further ado, what is this industry about? 7/54 I that, in itself, may be defensible in certain contexts we will briefly overview some of them in the next slide I the problem lies in how they handle them and what they prove I and then I got invited to submit a paper to a special issue of Studia Logica ... I and now I got invited to give a talk in Freiburg about that piece . I . so, without further ado, what is this industry about? I well, formal economists have surprisingly often some use for infinite collections of agents or infinite populations 7/54 I the problem lies in how they handle them and what they prove I and then I got invited to submit a paper to a special issue of Studia Logica ... I and now I got invited to give a talk in Freiburg about that piece . I . so, without further ado, what is this industry about? I well, formal economists have surprisingly often some use for infinite collections of agents or infinite populations I that, in itself, may be defensible in certain contexts we will briefly overview some of them in the next slide 7/54 I and then I got invited to submit a paper to a special issue of Studia Logica ... I and now I got invited to give a talk in Freiburg about that piece . I . so, without further ado, what is this industry about? I well, formal economists have surprisingly often some use for infinite collections of agents or infinite populations I that, in itself, may be defensible in certain contexts we will briefly overview some of them in the next slide I the problem lies in how they handle them and what they prove 7/54 intergenerational social choice the assumption of an infinite time horizon, e.g., infinitely repeating patterns of behaviour in games or utility streams social choice under uncertainty an infinite set of possible states of the world, each with its own (conceptual) inhabitants see Pivato 2014 for a more detailed analysis voting theory... ??? . analogous to that of idealized markets ?? perhaps not coincidentally, most authors do not seem overly explicit about their motivations whence infinite populations? idealized markets uncountably many agents when studying an idealized notion of perfect competition (Aumann 1964) the essential idea . is that the economy under consideration has a “very large” number of participants, and that the influence of each individual participant is “negligible” . one can integrate over a continuum, and changing the integrand at a single point does not affect the value of the integral 8/54 social choice under uncertainty an infinite set of possible states of the world, each with its own (conceptual) inhabitants see Pivato 2014 for a more detailed analysis voting theory... ??? . analogous to that of idealized markets ?? perhaps not coincidentally, most authors do not seem overly explicit about their motivations whence infinite populations? idealized markets uncountably many agents when studying an idealized notion of perfect competition (Aumann 1964) the essential idea . is that the economy under consideration has a “very large” number of participants, and that the influence of each individual participant is “negligible” . one can integrate over a continuum, and changing the integrand at a single point does not affect the value of the integral intergenerational social choice the assumption of an infinite time horizon, e.g., infinitely repeating patterns of behaviour in games or utility streams 8/54 voting theory... ??? . analogous to that of idealized markets ?? perhaps not coincidentally, most authors do not seem overly explicit about their motivations whence infinite populations? idealized markets uncountably many agents when studying an idealized notion of perfect competition (Aumann 1964) the essential idea . is that the economy under consideration has a “very large” number of participants, and that the influence of each individual participant is “negligible” . one can integrate over a continuum, and changing the integrand at a single point does not affect the value of the integral intergenerational social choice the assumption of an infinite time horizon, e.g., infinitely repeating patterns of behaviour in games or utility streams social choice under uncertainty an infinite set of possible states of the world, each with its own (conceptual) inhabitants see Pivato 2014 for a more detailed analysis 8/54 whence infinite populations? idealized markets uncountably many agents when studying an idealized notion of perfect competition (Aumann 1964) the essential idea . is that the economy under consideration has a “very large” number of participants, and that the influence of each individual participant is “negligible” . one can integrate over a continuum, and changing the integrand at a single point does not affect the value of the integral intergenerational social choice the assumption of an infinite time horizon, e.g., infinitely repeating patterns of behaviour in games or utility streams social choice under uncertainty an infinite set of possible states of the world, each with its own (conceptual) inhabitants see Pivato 2014 for a more detailed analysis voting theory..
Recommended publications
  • Frequently Asked Questions in Mathematics
    Frequently Asked Questions in Mathematics The Sci.Math FAQ Team. Editor: Alex L´opez-Ortiz e-mail: [email protected] Contents 1 Introduction 4 1.1 Why a list of Frequently Asked Questions? . 4 1.2 Frequently Asked Questions in Mathematics? . 4 2 Fundamentals 5 2.1 Algebraic structures . 5 2.1.1 Monoids and Groups . 6 2.1.2 Rings . 7 2.1.3 Fields . 7 2.1.4 Ordering . 8 2.2 What are numbers? . 9 2.2.1 Introduction . 9 2.2.2 Construction of the Number System . 9 2.2.3 Construction of N ............................... 10 2.2.4 Construction of Z ................................ 10 2.2.5 Construction of Q ............................... 11 2.2.6 Construction of R ............................... 11 2.2.7 Construction of C ............................... 12 2.2.8 Rounding things up . 12 2.2.9 What’s next? . 12 3 Number Theory 14 3.1 Fermat’s Last Theorem . 14 3.1.1 History of Fermat’s Last Theorem . 14 3.1.2 What is the current status of FLT? . 14 3.1.3 Related Conjectures . 15 3.1.4 Did Fermat prove this theorem? . 16 3.2 Prime Numbers . 17 3.2.1 Largest known Mersenne prime . 17 3.2.2 Largest known prime . 17 3.2.3 Largest known twin primes . 18 3.2.4 Largest Fermat number with known factorization . 18 3.2.5 Algorithms to factor integer numbers . 18 3.2.6 Primality Testing . 19 3.2.7 List of record numbers . 20 3.2.8 What is the current status on Mersenne primes? .
    [Show full text]
  • Uniqueness and Symmetry in Bargaining Theories of Justice
    Philos Stud DOI 10.1007/s11098-013-0121-y Uniqueness and symmetry in bargaining theories of justice John Thrasher Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013 Abstract For contractarians, justice is the result of a rational bargain. The goal is to show that the rules of justice are consistent with rationality. The two most important bargaining theories of justice are David Gauthier’s and those that use the Nash’s bargaining solution. I argue that both of these approaches are fatally undermined by their reliance on a symmetry condition. Symmetry is a substantive constraint, not an implication of rationality. I argue that using symmetry to generate uniqueness undermines the goal of bargaining theories of justice. Keywords David Gauthier Á John Nash Á John Harsanyi Á Thomas Schelling Á Bargaining Á Symmetry Throughout the last century and into this one, many philosophers modeled justice as a bargaining problem between rational agents. Even those who did not explicitly use a bargaining problem as their model, most notably Rawls, incorporated many of the concepts and techniques from bargaining theories into their understanding of what a theory of justice should look like. This allowed them to use the powerful tools of game theory to justify their various theories of distributive justice. The debates between partisans of different theories of distributive justice has tended to be over the respective benefits of each particular bargaining solution and whether or not the solution to the bargaining problem matches our pre-theoretical intuitions about justice. There is, however, a more serious problem that has effectively been ignored since economists originally J.
    [Show full text]
  • Implementation Theory*
    Chapter 5 IMPLEMENTATION THEORY* ERIC MASKIN Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton, NJ, USA TOMAS SJOSTROM Department of Economics, Pennsylvania State University, University Park, PA, USA Contents Abstract 238 Keywords 238 1. Introduction 239 2. Definitions 245 3. Nash implementation 247 3.1. Definitions 248 3.2. Monotonicity and no veto power 248 3.3. Necessary and sufficient conditions 250 3.4. Weak implementation 254 3.5. Strategy-proofness and rich domains of preferences 254 3.6. Unrestricted domain of strict preferences 256 3.7. Economic environments 257 3.8. Two agent implementation 259 4. Implementation with complete information: further topics 260 4.1. Refinements of Nash equilibrium 260 4.2. Virtual implementation 264 4.3. Mixed strategies 265 4.4. Extensive form mechanisms 267 4.5. Renegotiation 269 4.6. The planner as a player 275 5. Bayesian implementation 276 5.1. Definitions 276 5.2. Closure 277 5.3. Incentive compatibility 278 5.4. Bayesian monotonicity 279 * We are grateful to Sandeep Baliga, Luis Corch6n, Matt Jackson, Byungchae Rhee, Ariel Rubinstein, Ilya Segal, Hannu Vartiainen, Masahiro Watabe, and two referees, for helpful comments. Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, Volume 1, Edited by K.J Arrow, A.K. Sen and K. Suzumura ( 2002 Elsevier Science B. V All rights reserved 238 E. Maskin and T: Sj'str6m 5.5. Non-parametric, robust and fault tolerant implementation 281 6. Concluding remarks 281 References 282 Abstract The implementation problem is the problem of designing a mechanism (game form) such that the equilibrium outcomes satisfy a criterion of social optimality embodied in a social choice rule.
    [Show full text]
  • Subgame-Perfect Ε-Equilibria in Perfect Information Games With
    Subgame-Perfect -Equilibria in Perfect Information Games with Common Preferences at the Limit Citation for published version (APA): Flesch, J., & Predtetchinski, A. (2016). Subgame-Perfect -Equilibria in Perfect Information Games with Common Preferences at the Limit. Mathematics of Operations Research, 41(4), 1208-1221. https://doi.org/10.1287/moor.2015.0774 Document status and date: Published: 01/11/2016 DOI: 10.1287/moor.2015.0774 Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Document license: Taverne Please check the document version of this publication: • A submitted manuscript is the version of the article upon submission and before peer-review. There can be important differences between the submitted version and the official published version of record. People interested in the research are advised to contact the author for the final version of the publication, or visit the DOI to the publisher's website. • The final author version and the galley proof are versions of the publication after peer review. • The final published version features the final layout of the paper including the volume, issue and page numbers. Link to publication General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal.
    [Show full text]
  • Tic-Tac-Toe Is Not Very Interesting to Play, Because If Both Players Are Familiar with the Game the Result Is Always a Draw
    CMPSCI 250: Introduction to Computation Lecture #27: Games and Adversary Search David Mix Barrington 4 November 2013 Games and Adversary Search • Review: A* Search • Modeling Two-Player Games • When There is a Game Tree • The Determinacy Theorem • Searching a Game Tree • Examples of Games Review: A* Search • The A* Search depends on a heuristic function, which h(y) = 6 2 is a lower bound on the 23 s distance to the goal. x 4 If x is a node, and g is the • h(z) = 3 nearest goal node to x, the admissibility condition p(y) = 23 + 2 + 6 = 31 on h is that 0 ≤ h(x) ≤ d(x, g). p(z) = 23 + 4 + 3 = 30 Review: A* Search • Suppose we have taken y off of the open list. The best-path distance from the start s to the goal g through y is d(s, y) + d(y, h(y) = 6 g), and this cannot be less than 2 23 d(s, y) + h(y). s x 4 • Thus when we find a path of length k from s to y, we put y h(z) = 3 onto the open list with priority k p(y) = 23 + 2 + 6 = 31 + h(y). We still record the p(z) = 23 + 4 + 3 = 30 distance d(s, y) when we take y off of the open list. Review: A* Search • The advantage of A* over uniform-cost search is that we do not consider entries x in the closed list for which d(s, x) + h(x) h(y) = 6 is greater than the actual best- 2 23 path distance from s to g.
    [Show full text]
  • MATCHING with RENEGOTIATION 1. Introduction Deferred Acceptance
    MATCHING WITH RENEGOTIATION AKIHIKO MATSUI AND MEGUMI MURAKAMI Abstract. The present paper studies the deferred acceptance algorithm (DA) with renegotiation. After DA assigns objects to players, the players may renegotiate. The final allocation is prescribed by a renegotiation mapping, of which value is a strong core given an allocation induced by DA. We say that DA is strategy-proof with renegotiation if for any true preference profile and any (poten- tially false) report, an optimal strategy for each player is to submit the true preference. We then have the first theorem: DA is not strategy-proof with renegotiation for any priority structure. The priority structure is said to be unreversed if there are two players who have higher priority than the others at any object, and the other players are aligned in the same order across objects. Then, the second theorem states that the DA rule is implemented in Nash equilibrium with renegotiation, or equivalently, any Nash equilibrium of DA with renegotiation induces the same allocation as the DA rule, if and only if the priority structure is unreversed. Keywords: deferred acceptance algorithm (DA), indivisible object, renegotiation mapping, strong core, strategy-proofness with renegotiation, Nash implementation with renegotiation, unreversed priority JEL Classification Numbers: C78, D47 1. Introduction Deferred acceptance algorithm (DA) has been studied since the seminal paper by Gale and Shapley (1962). A class of problems investigated therein includes college admissions and office assignments. In these problems, the centralized mechanism assigns objects to players based on their preferences over objects and priorities for the objects over the players. Two notable prop- erties of DA are stability and strategy-proofness (Gale & Shapley, 1962; Dubins & Freedman, 1981; Roth, 1982).
    [Show full text]
  • Constructing Stationary Sunspot Equilibria in a Continuous Time Model*
    A Note on Woodford's Conjecture: Constructing Stationary Title Sunspot Equilibria in a Continuous Time Model(Nonlinear Analysis and Mathematical Economics) Author(s) Shigoka, Tadashi Citation 数理解析研究所講究録 (1994), 861: 51-66 Issue Date 1994-03 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/83844 Right Type Departmental Bulletin Paper Textversion publisher Kyoto University 数理解析研究所講究録 第 861 巻 1994 年 51-66 51 A Note on Woodford’s Conjecture: Constructing Stationary Sunspot Equilibria in a Continuous Time Model* Tadashi Shigoka Kyoto Institute of Economic Research, Kyoto University, Yoshidamachi Sakyoku Kyoto 606 Japan 京都大学 経済研究所 新後閑 禎 Abstract We show how to construct stationary sunspot equilibria in a continuous time model, where equilibrium is indeterninate near either a steady state or a closed orbit. Woodford’s conjecture that the indeterminacy of equilibrium implies the existence of stationary sunspot equilibria remains valid in a continuous time model. 52 Introduction If for given equilibrium dynamics there exist a continuum of non-stationary perfect foresight equilibria all converging asymptoticaUy to a steady state (a deterministic cycle resp.), we say the equilibrium dynamics is indeterminate near the steady state (the deterministic cycle resp.). Suppose that the fundamental characteristics of an economy are deterministic, but that economic agents believe nevertheless that equihibrium dynamics is affected by random factors apparently irrelevant to the fundamental characteristics (sunspots). This prophecy could be self-fulfilling, and one will get a sunspot equilibrium, if the resulting equilibrium dynamics is subject to a nontrivial stochastic process and confirns the agents’ belief. See Shell [19], and Cass-Shell [3]. Woodford [23] suggested that there exists a close relation between the indetenninacy of equilibrium near a deterministic steady state and the existence of stationary sunspot equilibria in the immediate vicinity of it.
    [Show full text]
  • Strategies in Games: a Logic-Automata Study
    Strategies in games: a logic-automata study S. Ghosh1 and R. Ramanujam2 1 Indian Statistical Institute SETS Campus, Chennai 600 113, India. [email protected] 2 The Institute of Mathematical Sciences C.I.T. Campus, Chennai 600 113, India. [email protected] 1 Introduction Overview. There is now a growing body of research on formal algorithmic mod- els of social procedures and interactions between rational agents. These models attempt to identify logical elements in our day-to-day social activities. When in- teractions are modeled as games, reasoning involves analysis of agents' long-term powers for influencing outcomes. Agents devise their respective strategies on how to interact so as to ensure maximal gain. In recent years, researchers have tried to devise logics and models in which strategies are “first class citizens", rather than unspecified means to ensure outcomes. Yet, these cover only basic models, leaving open a range of interesting issues, e.g. communication and coordination between players, especially in games of imperfect information. Game models are also relevant in the context of system design and verification. In this article we will discuss research on logic and automata-theoretic models of games and strategic reasoning in multi-agent systems. We will get acquainted with the basic tools and techniques for this emerging area, and provide pointers to the exciting questions it offers. Content. This article consists of 5 sections apart from the introduction. An outline of the contents of the other sections is given below. 1. Section 2 (Exploring structure in strategies): A short introduction to games in extensive form, and strategies.
    [Show full text]
  • Whither Game Theory? Towards a Theory of Learning in Games
    Whither Game Theory? Towards a Theory of Learning in Games The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation Fudenberg, Drew, and David K. Levine. “Whither Game Theory? Towards a Theory of Learning in Games.” Journal of Economic Perspectives, vol. 30, no. 4, Nov. 2016, pp. 151–70. As Published http://dx.doi.org/10.1257/jep.30.4.151 Publisher American Economic Association Version Final published version Citable link http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/113940 Terms of Use Article is made available in accordance with the publisher's policy and may be subject to US copyright law. Please refer to the publisher's site for terms of use. Journal of Economic Perspectives—Volume 30, Number 4—Fall 2016—Pages 151–170 Whither Game Theory? Towards a Theory of Learning in Games Drew Fudenberg and David K. Levine hen we were graduate students at MIT (1977–81), the only game theory mentioned in the first-year core was static Cournot (1838) oligopoly, W although Eric Maskin taught an advanced elective on game theory and mechanism design. Just ten years later, game theory had invaded mainstream economic research and graduate education, and instructors had a choice of three graduate texts: Fudenberg and Tirole (1991), Osborne and Rubinstein (1994), and Myerson (1997). Game theory has been successful in economics because it works empirically in many important circumstances. Many of the theoretical applications in the 1980s involved issues in industrial organization, like commitment and timing in patent races and preemptive investment.
    [Show full text]
  • Economics 286: Game Theory 1 Overview
    Economics 286: Game Theory Stanford University, Fall 2016 Mon, Wed 9:30 – 11:20 AM, Landau 218 https://canvas.stanford.edu/courses/47170 Syllabus version: September 23, 2016 Gabriel Carroll, [email protected] | Landau 245 | Office hours by appointment 1 Overview What this class is: This is an intermediate-level, mathematically oriented class in game theory, aimed at economics PhD students (but qualified students in other depart- ments are very much welcome to attend). The goals are twofold: to provide technical tools for studying game-theoretic problems that arise in economic models, and to discuss conceptual issues in interpreting predictions made using game theory. What this class is not: • A class just for micro theorists. This class is meant to provide concepts and analytical tools useful in every area of economics (and beyond). • A first course in game theory. Technically, the mathematical content will be developed in a way that doesn’t presume game theory background; but in practice, if you haven’t taken a previous game theory class it will be steep going. (The official prerequisite is ECON 203. If you have taken a different game theory class and are unsure if you are prepared, you are encouraged to discuss with me.) • An introduction to the research frontiers. This is intended as a foundational course, although we will run across some relatively recent papers. ECON 290 or MGTECON 616 are more like “advanced topics” classes. Textbooks: The main source for this class, which covers much (though not all) of the material, is the still-classic • Drew Fudenberg and Jean Tirole, Game Theory, MIT Press, 1991.
    [Show full text]
  • Coalitional Rationalizability*
    Coalitional Rationalizability∗ Attila Ambrus This Version: September 2005 Abstract This paper investigates how groups or coalitions of players can act in their collective interest in non-cooperative normal form games even if equilibrium play is not assumed. The main idea is that each member of a coalition will confine play to a subset of their strategies if it is in their mutual interest to do so. An iterative procedure of restrictions is used to define a non-cooperative solution concept, the set of coalitionally rational- izable strategies. The procedure is analogous to iterative deletion of never best response strategies, but operates on implicit agreements by different coalitions. The solution set is a nonempty subset of the rationalizable strategies. ∗I thank Dilip Abreu for support and extremely valuable comments at all stages of writingthispaper.Iwouldalsoliketothank Drew Fudenberg, Faruk Gul, Wolfgang Pesendorfer, Ariel Rubinstein and Marciano Siniscalchi for useful comments and dis- cussions. Finally, I would like to thank Eddie Dekel, Haluk Ergin, Erica Field, Jozsef Molnar, Wojciech Oszlewski, Hugo Sonnenschein, Andrea Wilson, seminar participants at various universities for useful comments. 1 I. Introduction The main solution concept in noncooperative game theory, Nash equilibrium, requires stability only with respect to individual deviations by players. It does not take into account the possibility that groups of players might coordinate their moves, in order to achieve an outcome that is better for all of them. There have been several attempts to incorporate this consideration into the theory of noncooperative games, starting with the pioneering works of Schelling [1960] and Aumann [1959]. The latter offered strong Nash equilibrium, the first for- mal solution concept in noncooperative game theory that takes into account the interests of coalitions.
    [Show full text]
  • Determinacy in Discrete-Bidding Infinite-Duration Games
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Dagstuhl Research Online Publication Server Determinacy in Discrete-Bidding Infinite-Duration Games Milad Aghajohari Sharif University of Technology, Iran [email protected] Guy Avni IST Austria, Klosterneuburg, Austria [email protected] Thomas A. Henzinger IST Austria, Klosterneuburg, Austria [email protected] Abstract In two-player games on graphs, the players move a token through a graph to produce an infinite path, which determines the winner of the game. Such games are central in formal methods since they model the interaction between a non-terminating system and its environment. In bidding games the players bid for the right to move the token: in each round, the players simultaneously submit bids, and the higher bidder moves the token and pays the other player. Bidding games are known to have a clean and elegant mathematical structure that relies on the ability of the players to submit arbitrarily small bids. Many applications, however, require a fixed granularity for the bids, which can represent, for example, the monetary value expressed in cents. We study, for the first time, the combination of discrete-bidding and infinite-duration games. Our most important result proves that these games form a large determined subclass of concurrent games, where determinacy is the strong property that there always exists exactly one player who can guarantee winning the game. In particular, we show that, in contrast to non-discrete bidding games, the mechanism with which tied bids are resolved plays an important role in discrete-bidding games.
    [Show full text]