Measurable Cardinals and Scott's Theorem

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Measurable Cardinals and Scott's Theorem Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Chris Mierzewski Mathematical Logic Seminar 1/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem From measures to cardinals Measurable Cardinals Lebesgue’s Measure Problem Is there a measure : P(R) R such that I is not the constant zero function ! I is -additive I For any sets X, Y R, if X = fy + r j y 2 Y g for some fixed r 2 R, then (X) = (Y )? Vitali (1905): No such thing. 2/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem From measures to cardinals Measurable Cardinals Banach: Is there any set S admitting a measure : P(S) [0, 1] such that I (S) = 1 ! I is -additive I (fsg) = 0 for all s 2 S? For which cardinals is there a non-trivial finite measure defined over (i.e. on P())? 3/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem From measures to cardinals Measurable Cardinals Ulam: If is the smallest cardinal with a non- trivial finite measure over , then 2@0 or admits a non-trivial measure that takes only values in f0, 1g. I If is the smallest cardinal with a non-trivial finite measure , then is -additive. I So we can ask: does there exist any uncountable with a f0, 1g-valued measure over it? 4/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem From measures to cardinals Measurable cardinals Relation between -additive measures and non-principal, -complete ultrafilters over : U = X j (X) = 1 Definition (Measurable Cardinal) An uncountable cardinal is mesurable if there exists a non-principal, -complete ultrafilter over . 5/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem From measures to cardinals Some facts about measurable cardinals Suppose is measurable, and U a non-principal, -complete ultrafilter over . Then the following hold: I If X 2 U, then jXj = . I is regular. I (Tarski–Ulam) is inaccessible. So if is measurable, then (V, 2) ZFC; thus ZFC cannot prove the existence of measurable cardinals. They are indeed large. In fact: I (Hanf–Tarski (1960)) Least inaccessible cardinal < least measurable cardinal. J.Bell: “GARGANTUAN proportions...” 6/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem From measures to cardinals Scott’s Theorem Theorem (Scott) If there exists a measurable cardinal, then V =6 L. Woodin’s "Meta-Corollary" “The whole point of set theory is to study infinity. You can’t deny large cardinals. So [the statement V=L] is just not true.” 7/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem From measures to cardinals Scott’s Theorem Theorem (Scott) If there exists a measurable cardinal, then V =6 L. Woodin’s "Meta-Corollary" “The whole point of set theory is to study infinity. You can’t deny large cardinals. So [the statement V=L] is just not true.” 8/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Background about L The constructible universe: Göd-L Recall: I L is the smallest inner model (in V ). That is, if M is a transitive class containing all ordinals, then L M. Aternative characterisation of L: via Gödel operations and the associated closure operator. Def(A) = cl(A [ fAg) \P(A) 9/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Background about L Alternative characterisation of L: Gödel operations I G1(X, Y ) := fX, Y g I G2(X, Y ) := X ¢ Y I G3(X, Y ) := (u, v) j u 2 X ^ v 2 Y ^ u 2 v I G4(X, Y ) := X n Y I G5(X, Y ) := X \ Y I G6(X) := S X I G7(X) := dom(X) I G8(X) := (u, v) j (v, u) 2 X I G9(X) := (u, v, w) j (v, w, v) 2 X I G10(X) := (u, v, w) j (v, w, u) 2 X 10/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Background about L Alternative characterisation of L: Gödel operations We can define: L0 := ; L +1 := cl(L [ fL g) \P(L ) [ L := L 2On Theorem (Gödel) A transitive class M is an inner model of ZF if and only if I M is closed under Gödel operations I M is almost universal (whenever X M, then X Y for some Y 2 M. 11/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Scott’s Proof Scott’s Proof I Take , the least measurable cardinal, and U a non-principal, -complete ultrafilter over . I Build an ultrapower (V /U, 2U ) of V , and collapse it to form a transitive class model (M, 2). I Using a variant of Łoś’ Theorem, there is an elementary embedding : V M. I Using V = L, show that M = V , so that is an elementary embedding ! of V . (V , 2) (M, 2) id (V /U, 2U ) 12/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Scott’s Proof Scott’s Proof I Using the -completeness of U, show that (i) for any < , ( ) < , and (ii) we have () > . I By Łoś’ Theorem, we have that (M, 2) ‘() is the least measurable cardinal’, and since M = V , () is the least measurable cardinal in V . I But we have shown that () > , which contradicts the minimality of (). I Contradiction. If V = L, there can be no measurable cardinals. 13/29 The ultrapower V /U is the class of minimal-rank representatives of equivalence classes (Scott’s trick): [f]:= g2 V f ∼U g and 8h 2 V , if f ∼U h then rk(g) rk(h) Then each[f] is a set. I Thus we get a proper class V /U := [f] f : V ! Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Scott’s Proof Ultrapowers of proper classes: Scott’s trick I We want to build ultrapowers of proper class models. Let a cardinal and U an ultrafilter over . For any f, g 2 V , we let f∼U g if and only if f < j f( ) = g( )g 2 U 14/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Scott’s Proof Ultrapowers of proper classes: Scott’s trick I We want to build ultrapowers of proper class models. Let a cardinal and U an ultrafilter over . For any f, g 2 V , we let f∼U g if and only if f < j f( ) = g( )g 2 U The ultrapower V /U is the class of minimal-rank representatives of equivalence classes (Scott’s trick): [f]:= g2 V f ∼U g and 8h 2 V , if f ∼U h then rk(g) rk(h) Then each[f] is a set. I Thus we get a proper class V /U := [f] f : V ! 14/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Scott’s Proof Ultrapowers of proper classes We have V /U = [f] f 2 V The ultrapower structure comes with a membership relation 2U , defined as [f] 2U [g] if and only if < f( ) 2 g( ) 2 U We obtain the ultrapower structure (V /U, 2U ). Useful notation: write jjf 2 gjj := f < j f( ) 2 g( )g. In general, for any first order formula '(x1, ..., xn), write '(f1, ..., fn) := < '(f1( ), ..., fn( )) . 15/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Scott’s Proof Łoś’ Theorem For any L2-formula ', and any f1, ..., fn 2 V , we have: (V , 2U ) '[f1], ..., [fn] if and only if < V , 2 'f , ..., f 2 U ( ) 1( ) n( ) (Equivalently, iff jj'(f1, ..., fn)jj 2 U.) 16/29 I We will show that V can be elementarily embedded in (V /U, 2U ), and (V /U, 2U ) can be collapsed to a transitive class model (M in),giving an elementary embedding of (V , 2) into (M, 2). (V , 2) id (V /U, 2U ) Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Scott’s Proof I Assume V = L, and assume there is a measurable cardinal. Let be the least measurable cardinal. I Take the ultrapower (V /U, 2U ), where U is a non-principal, -complete ultrafilter on . 17/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Scott’s Proof I Assume V = L, and assume there is a measurable cardinal. Let be the least measurable cardinal. I Take the ultrapower (V /U, 2U ), where U is a non-principal, -complete ultrafilter on . I We will show that V can be elementarily embedded in (V /U, 2U ), and (V /U, 2U ) can be collapsed to a transitive class model (M in),giving an elementary embedding of (V , 2) into (M, 2). (V , 2) id (V /U, 2U ) 17/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Scott’s Proof I Assume V = L, and assume there is a measurable cardinal. Let be the least measurable cardinal. I Take the ultrapower (V /U, 2U ), where U is a non-principal, -complete ultrafilter on . I We will show that V can be elementarily embedded in (V /U, 2U ), and (V /U, 2U ) can be collapsed to a transitive class model (M, 2), giving an elementary embedding of (V , 2) into (M, 2). (V , 2) (M, 2) id (V /U, 2U ) 18/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Scott’s Proof I Assume V = L, and assume there is a measurable cardinal. Let be the least measurable cardinal. I Take the ultrapower (V /U, 2U ), where U is a non-principal, -complete ultrafilter on . I We will show that V can be elementarily embedded in (V /U, 2U ), and (V /U, 2U ) can be collapsed to a transitive class model (M, 2), giving an elementary embedding of (V , 2) into (M, 2). (V , 2) (M, 2) id (V /U, 2U ) 19/29 Measurable Cardinals and Scott’s Theorem Scott’s Proof Embedding (V , 2) (M, 2) id (V /U, 2U ) I For any set x, let cx : V be the constant map cx : 7 x. I The map id : V V /U is defined as id(x) = [cx] ! ! ' 2 L By Łoś, for any !2 we have : (V , 2) ' a1, ..., an iff (V /U, 2U ) ' [ca1 ], ..., [can ] so that id is an elementary embedding of V into V /U.
Recommended publications
  • Set-Theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms
    Set-theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms Justin William Henry Cavitt (860) 949-5686 [email protected] Advisor: W. Hugh Woodin Harvard University March 20, 2017 Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts in Mathematics and Philosophy Contents 1 Introduction 2 1.1 Author’s Note . .4 1.2 Acknowledgements . .4 2 The Independence Problem 5 2.1 Gödelian Independence and Consistency Strength . .5 2.2 Forcing and Natural Independence . .7 2.2.1 Basics of Forcing . .8 2.2.2 Forcing Facts . 11 2.2.3 The Space of All Forcing Extensions: The Generic Multiverse 15 2.3 Recap . 16 3 Approaches to New Axioms 17 3.1 Large Cardinals . 17 3.2 Inner Model Theory . 25 3.2.1 Basic Facts . 26 3.2.2 The Constructible Universe . 30 3.2.3 Other Inner Models . 35 3.2.4 Relative Constructibility . 38 3.3 Recap . 39 4 Ultimate L 40 4.1 The Axiom V = Ultimate L ..................... 41 4.2 Central Features of Ultimate L .................... 42 4.3 Further Philosophical Considerations . 47 4.4 Recap . 51 1 5 Set-theoretic Geology 52 5.1 Preliminaries . 52 5.2 The Downward Directed Grounds Hypothesis . 54 5.2.1 Bukovský’s Theorem . 54 5.2.2 The Main Argument . 61 5.3 Main Results . 65 5.4 Recap . 74 6 Conclusion 74 7 Appendix 75 7.1 Notation . 75 7.2 The ZFC Axioms . 76 7.3 The Ordinals . 77 7.4 The Universe of Sets . 77 7.5 Transitive Models and Absoluteness .
    [Show full text]
  • O&ONSTRUCTIBLE UNIVERSE and MEASURABLE CARDINALS 0
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 30 (1986) 293-320 293 North-Holland o&ONSTRUCTIBLE UNIVERSE AND MEASURABLE CARDINALS Claude SURESON Dkpartement de Mathkmatiques, Universitk de Caen, 1403.2 Caen, France Communicated by A. Nerode Received 23 September 1984 In analogy with K. Godel’s model L, C. Chang [l] formulated the wr- constructible universe C”‘, using the infinitary language L,,,, instead of the language of Set Theory L,,. The cumulative hierarchy of sets obtained in this way has many similarities with the hierarchy of the constructible universe (except for a major point: the axiom of choice [l], [9]). C”’ can also be characterized as the least inner model closed under arbitrary countable sequences. This paper is inspired by results of R. Jensen and J. Silver concerning the existence of O# and the covering property for L. We consider here a stronger notion of indiscernibles for the model C”’ and we say that C”’ satisfies the ‘covering property’ if any set of ordinals X in the universe can be covered by a set in C”’ of cardinality ]X]‘O. The existence of ‘indiscernibles’ for C”’ is also linked to large cardinal assumptions, and our main result (in ZFC) can be summarized as shown in Diagram 1: Diagram 1. The first part is devoted to the study of indiscernibles for PI. We prove the implications (1) and (2). In the second section, we deal with the covering property and show (3).
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture Notes: Axiomatic Set Theory
    Lecture Notes: Axiomatic Set Theory Asaf Karagila Last Update: May 14, 2018 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Why do we need axioms?...............................3 1.2 Classes and sets.....................................4 1.3 The axioms of set theory................................5 2 Ordinals, recursion and induction7 2.1 Ordinals.........................................8 2.2 Transfinite induction and recursion..........................9 2.3 Transitive classes.................................... 10 3 The relative consistency of the Axiom of Foundation 12 4 Cardinals and their arithmetic 15 4.1 The definition of cardinals............................... 15 4.2 The Aleph numbers.................................. 17 4.3 Finiteness........................................ 18 5 Absoluteness and reflection 21 5.1 Absoluteness...................................... 21 5.2 Reflection........................................ 23 6 The Axiom of Choice 25 6.1 The Axiom of Choice.................................. 25 6.2 Weak version of the Axiom of Choice......................... 27 7 Sets of Ordinals 31 7.1 Cofinality........................................ 31 7.2 Some cardinal arithmetic............................... 32 7.3 Clubs and stationary sets............................... 33 7.4 The Club filter..................................... 35 8 Inner models of ZF 37 8.1 Inner models...................................... 37 8.2 Gödel’s constructible universe............................. 39 1 8.3 The properties of L ................................... 41 8.4 Ordinal definable sets................................. 42 9 Some combinatorics on ω1 43 9.1 Aronszajn trees..................................... 43 9.2 Diamond and Suslin trees............................... 44 10 Coda: Games and determinacy 46 2 Chapter 1 Introduction 1.1 Why do we need axioms? In modern mathematics, axioms are given to define an object. The axioms of a group define the notion of a group, the axioms of a Banach space define what it means for something to be a Banach space.
    [Show full text]
  • The Bristol Model (5/5)
    The Bristol model (5/5) Asaf Karagila University of East Anglia 22 November 2019 RIMS Set Theory Workshop 2019 Set Theory and Infinity Asaf Karagila (UEA) The Bristol model (5/5) 22 November 2019 1 / 23 Review Bird’s eye view of Bristol We started in L by choosing a Bristol sequence, that is a sequence of permutable families and permutable scales, and we constructed one step at a time models, Mα, such that: 1 M0 = L. Mα Mα+1 2 Mα+1 is a symmetric extension of Mα, and Vω+α = Vω+α . 3 For limit α, Mα is the finite support limit of the iteration, and Mα S Mβ Vω+α = β<α Vω+β. By choosing our Mα-generic filters correctly, we ensured that Mα ⊆ L[%0], where %0 was an L-generic Cohen real. We then defined M, the Bristol model, S S Mα as α∈Ord Mα = α∈Ord Vω+α. Asaf Karagila (UEA) The Bristol model (5/5) 22 November 2019 2 / 23 Properties of the Bristol model Small Violations of Choice Definition (Blass) We say that V |= SVC(X) if for every A there is an ordinal η and a surjection f : X × η → A. We write SVC to mean ∃X SVC(X). Theorem If M = V (x) where V |= ZFC, then M |= SVC. Theorem If M is a symmetric extension of V |= ZFC, Then M |= SVC. The following are equivalent: 1 SVC. 2 1 ∃X such that X<ω AC. 3 ∃P such that 1 P AC. 4 V is a symmetric extension of a model of ZFC (Usuba).
    [Show full text]
  • On the Origins of Bisimulation and Coinduction
    On the Origins of Bisimulation and Coinduction DAVIDE SANGIORGI University of Bologna, Italy The origins of bisimulation and bisimilarity are examined, in the three fields where they have been independently discovered: Computer Science, Philosophical Logic (precisely, Modal Logic), Set Theory. Bisimulation and bisimilarity are coinductive notions, and as such are intimately related to fixed points, in particular greatest fixed points. Therefore also the appearance of coinduction and fixed points is discussed, though in this case only within Computer Science. The paper ends with some historical remarks on the main fixed-point theorems (such as Knaster-Tarski) that underpin the fixed-point theory presented. Categories and Subject Descriptors: F.4.1 [Mathematical logic and formal languages]: Math- ematical Logic—Computational logic; Modal logic; Set theory; F.4.0 [Mathematical logic and formal languages]: General General Terms: Theory, Verification Additional Key Words and Phrases: Bisimulation, coinduction, fixed points, greatest fixed points, history Contents 1 Introduction 112 2 Background 114 2.1 Bisimulation................................ 114 2.2 Approximants of bisimilarity . 116 2.3 Coinduction................................116 3 Bisimulation in Modal Logic 119 3.1 Modallogics................................119 3.2 Fromhomomorphismtop-morphism . 120 3.3 JohanvanBenthem ........................... 122 3.4 Discussion.................................125 4 Bisimulation in Computer Science 125 4.1 Algebraictheoryofautomata . 125 4.2 RobinMilner ...............................128 Author’s address: Dipartimento di Scienze dell’Informazione Universita’ di Bologna Mura Anteo Zamboni, 7 40126 Bologna, ITALY. Permission to make digital/hard copy of all or part of this material without fee for personal or classroom use provided that the copies are not made or distributed for profit or commercial advantage, the ACM copyright/server notice, the title of the publication, and its date appear, and notice is given that copying is by permission of the ACM, Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • Determinacy and Large Cardinals
    Determinacy and Large Cardinals Itay Neeman∗ Abstract. The principle of determinacy has been crucial to the study of definable sets of real numbers. This paper surveys some of the uses of determinacy, concentrating specifically on the connection between determinacy and large cardinals, and takes this connection further, to the level of games of length ω1. Mathematics Subject Classification (2000). 03E55; 03E60; 03E45; 03E15. Keywords. Determinacy, iteration trees, large cardinals, long games, Woodin cardinals. 1. Determinacy Let ωω denote the set of infinite sequences of natural numbers. For A ⊂ ωω let Gω(A) denote the length ω game with payoff A. The format of Gω(A) is displayed in Diagram 1. Two players, denoted I and II, alternate playing natural numbers forming together a sequence x = hx(n) | n < ωi in ωω called a run of the game. The run is won by player I if x ∈ A, and otherwise the run is won by player II. I x(0) x(2) ...... II x(1) x(3) ...... Diagram 1. The game Gω(A). A game is determined if one of the players has a winning strategy. The set A is ω determined if Gω(A) is determined. For Γ ⊂ P(ω ), det(Γ) denotes the statement that all sets in Γ are determined. Using the axiom of choice, or more specifically using a wellordering of the reals, it is easy to construct a non-determined set A. det(P(ωω)) is therefore false. On the other hand it has become clear through research over the years that det(Γ) is true if all the sets in Γ are definable by some concrete means.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ultrafilter Characterization of Huge Cardinals 587
    proceedings of the american mathematical society Volume 90, Number 4, April 1984 THE ULTRAFILTERCHARACTERIZATION OF HUGE CARDINALS ROBERT J. MIGNONE1 Abstract. A huge cardinal can be characterized using ultrafilters. After an argu- ment is made for a particular ultrafilter characterization, it is used to prove the existence of a measurable cardinal above the huge cardinal, and an ultrafilter over the set of all subsets of this measurable cardinal of size smaller than the huge cardinal. Finally, this last ultrafilter is disassembled intact by a process which often produces a different ultrafilter from the one started out with. An important point of this paper is given the existence of the particular ultrafilter characterization of a huge cardinal mentioned above these results are proved in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice. Introduction. The notion of a huge cardinal was first introduced by Kunen. Its primary definition is given in terms of elementary embeddings. And just as measura- ble and supercompact cardinals have ultrafilter characterizations in ZFC, a huge cardinal can also be characterized by ultrafilters. In §1, after the elementary embedding definition for a huge cardinal and two equivalent ultrafilter characterizations are given, an argument is made for one characterization above the other in instances where the axiom of choice is not available. Once an ultrafilter characterization for k being huge is settled upon—which defines k as huge if for some X > k there exists a K-complete, normal ultrafilter over {x C X: x = k}—two theorems are proved in §2 which state that providing such an ultrafilter exists over {x czX: x = k}, then X is measurable and k is A-supercompact.
    [Show full text]
  • Forcing and the Universe of Sets: Must We Lose Insight?
    Forcing and the Universe of Sets: Must we lose insight? Neil Barton∗ 29 January 2018y Abstract A central area of current philosophical debate in the foundations of mathe- matics concerns whether or not there is a single, maximal, universe of set theory. Universists maintain that there is such a universe, while Multiversists argue that there are many universes, no one of which is ontologically privileged. Often forc- ing constructions that add subsets to models are cited as evidence in favour of the latter. This paper informs this debate by analysing ways the Universist might interpret this discourse that seems to necessitate the addition of subsets to V . We argue that despite the prima facie incoherence of such talk for the Universist, she nonetheless has reason to try and provide interpretation of this discourse. We analyse extant interpretations of such talk, and argue that while tradeoffs in nat- urality have to be made, they are not too severe. Introduction Recent discussions of the philosophy of set theory have often focussed on how many universes of sets there are. The following is a standard position: Universism. There is a unique, maximal, proper class sized universe containing all the sets (denoted by ‘V ’). Universism has often been thought of as the ‘default’ position on the ontology of sets.1 However, some have seen the existence of many different epistemic pos- sibilities for the nature of the set-theoretic universe, shown by the large diversity of model-theoretic constructions witnessing independence (we discuss two of these methods later) as indicative of the existence of a diversity of different set-theoretic universes.
    [Show full text]
  • Hamkins' Analogy Between Set Theory and Geometry
    TAKING THE ANALOGY BETWEEN SET THEORY AND GEOMETRY SERIOUSLY SHARON BERRY Abstract. Set theorist Joel Hamkins uses considerations about forcing argu- ments in set theory together with an analogy between set theory and geometry to motivate his influential set-theoretic multiverse program: a distinctive and powerfully truthvalue-antirealist form of plenetudinous Platonism. However, I'll argue that taking this analogy seriously cuts against Hamkins' proposal in one important way. I'll then note that putting a (hyperintensional) modal twist on Hamkins' Multiverse lets take Hamkins' analogy further and address his motivations equally well (or better) while maintaining naive realism. 1. Introduction Philosophers who want to deny that there are right answers to mathematical ques- tions (like the Continuum Hypothesis) which are undecidable via deduction from mathematical axioms we currently accept often draw on an analogy between set theory and geometry [6, 12]1. In this paper I will discuss one of the most important and interesting recent examples of this phenomenon: set theorist Joel Hamkins' use of (a specific form of) this analogy to motivate his set-theoretic multiverse program. Hamkins has developed an influential2 multiverse approach to set theory, on which there are many different hierarchies of sets, and there's no fact of the matter about whether certain set-theoretic statements are true, beyond the fact that they are true of some hierarchies of sets within the multiverse and false in others. On this view there is no `full' intended hierarchy of sets which contains all subsets of sets it contains- or even all subsets of the natural numbers.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Absoluteness of $\Aleph 1 $-Freeness
    ON THE ABSOLUTENESS OF ℵ1-FREENESS DANIEL HERDEN, ALEXANDRA V. PASI Abstract. ℵ1-free groups, abelian groups for which every countable subgroup is free, exhibit a number of interesting algebraic and set-theoretic properties. In this paper, we give a complete proof that the property of being ℵ1-free is absolute; that is, if an abelian group G is ℵ1-free in some transitive model M of ZFC, then it is ℵ1-free in any transitive model of ZFC containing G. The absoluteness of ℵ1-freeness has the following remarkable consequence: an abelian group G is ℵ1-free in some transitive model of ZFC if and only if it is (countable and) free in some model extension. This set-theoretic characteri- zation will be the starting point for further exploring the relationship between the set-theoretic and algebraic properties of ℵ1-free groups. In particular, this paper will demonstrate how proofs may be dramatically simplified using model extensions for ℵ1-free groups. 1. Introduction ℵ1-free groups, abelian groups whose countable subgroups are free, are the sub- ject of significant study in abelian group theory. The Baer-Specker group, the direct product of countably many copies of Z, provides a simple example of an ℵ1-free group (which is not free), [1, 14]. The class of ℵ1-free groups exhibits a high degree of algebraic complexity, as evidenced by the test of ring-realization: any ring with free additive structure can be realized as the endomorphism ring of some ℵ1-free group [4, 5]. ℵ1-free groups also play an important role in the Whitehead Problem, as ev- ery Whitehead group can be shown to be ℵ1-free [15].
    [Show full text]
  • Paul B. Larson a BRIEF HISTORY of DETERMINACY §1. Introduction
    Paul B. Larson A BRIEF HISTORY OF DETERMINACY x1. Introduction. Determinacy axioms are statements to the effect that certain games are determined, in that each player in the game has an optimal strategy. The commonly accepted axioms for mathematics, the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms with the Axiom of Choice (ZFC; see [??, ??]), im- ply the determinacy of many games that people actually play. This applies in particular to many games of perfect information, games in which the players alternate moves which are known to both players, and the out- come of the game depends only on this list of moves, and not on chance or other external factors. Games of perfect information which must end in finitely many moves are determined. This follows from the work of Ernst Zermelo [??], D´enesK}onig[??] and L´aszl´oK´almar[??], and also from the independent work of John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern (in their 1944 book, reprinted as [??]). As pointed out by Stanis law Ulam [??], determinacy for games of perfect information of a fixed finite length is essentially a theorem of logic. If we let x1,y1,x2,y2,::: ,xn,yn be variables standing for the moves made by players player I (who plays x1,::: ,xn) and player II (who plays y1,::: ,yn), and A (consisting of sequences of length 2n) is the set of runs of the game for which player I wins, the statement (1) 9x18y1 ::: 9xn8ynhx1; y1; : : : ; xn; yni 2 A essentially asserts that the first player has a winning strategy in the game, and its negation, (2) 8x19y1 ::: 8xn9ynhx1; y1; : : : ; xn; yni 62 A essentially asserts that the second player has a winning strategy.1 We let ! denote the set of natural numbers 0; 1; 2;::: ; for brevity we will often refer to the members of this set as \integers".
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:Math/0009240V1
    A simple maximality principle Joel David Hamkins∗ The City University of New York† Carnegie Mellon University‡ http://math.gc.cuny.edu/faculty/hamkins October 24, 2018 Abstract. In this paper, following an idea of Christophe Chalons, I propose a new kind of forcing axiom, the Maximality Principle, which asserts that any sentence ϕ holding in some ˙ forcing extension V P and all subsequent extensions V P∗Q holds already in V . It follows, in fact, that such sentences must also hold in all forcing extensions of V . In modal terms, therefore, the Maximality Principle is expressed by the scheme (✸ ϕ) =⇒ ϕ, and is equivalent to the modal theory S5. In this article, I prove that the Maximality Principle is relatively consistent with zfc. A boldface version of the Maximality Principle, obtained by allowing real parameters to appear in ϕ, is equiconsistent with the scheme asserting that Vδ ≺ V for an inaccessible cardinal δ, which in turn is equiconsistent with the scheme asserting that ord is mp mp V Mahlo. The strongest principle along these lines is ∼ , which asserts that ∼ holds in and all forcing extensions. From this, it follows that 0# exists, that x# exists for every set x, that projective truth is invariant by forcing, that Woodin cardinals are consistent and much more. Many open questions remain. 1 The Maximality Principle arXiv:math/0009240v1 [math.LO] 28 Sep 2000 Christophe Chalons has introduced a delightful new axiom, asserting in plain language that anything that is forceable and not subsequently unforceable is true. Specifically, in [2] he proposes the following principle: ∗My research has been supported by grants from the PSC-CUNY Research Foundation and the NSF.
    [Show full text]