Propositional Quantifiers in Modal Logic1

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Propositional Quantifiers in Modal Logic1 Propositional quantifiers in modal logic' by KIT FINE (Oxford University) In this paper I shall present some of the results I have obtained on modal theories which contain quantifiers for propositions. The paper is in two parts: in the first part I consider theories whose non-quantificational part is S5; in the second part I consider theories whose non-quantificational part is weaker than or not contained in S5. Unless otherwise stated, each theory has the same language L. This consists of a countable set V of proposi- tional variables pl, pa, ... , the operators v (or), -(not) and 0 (necessarily),the universal quantifier (p), p a propositional variable, and brackets ( and ). The formulas of L are then defined in the usual way. 1.1. Semantics In Kripke's semantics for S5 [6],a proposition is, in effect, identi- fied with the set of possible worlds in which it is true. So on this view the propositional quantifier (p) should range over a set of subsets of possible worlds. Formally, a structure A is an ordered triple (W, P, u), where W (worlds) is a non-empty set, P (proposi- tions) is a non-empty set of subsets of Wand v (valuation) is a map from Vinto P. The truth-definition then goes as follows: for a structure A = (W, P, u), a world x in W,and formulas B and C, I am greatly indebted to the late Arthur Prior. Without his encouragement, this paper would not have been written. 2 The results of this part are contained in my Ph.D. thesis, submitted to the University of Warwick in the Summer term of 1969. PROPOSITIONAL QUANTIFIERS IN MODAL LOGIC 337 (v) (pi)B iff ILB for all structures A’ = (w,P, v’) X X such that v’(pJ= VIP3 for all j f i, i = 1, 2, . .. (Note: v’(pi) E P by the defini- tion of structure.) The formula A is valid in A, FEA, if A for all y in W. There are three natural conditions we can impose upon P: (i) P is Boolean i.e. closed under complementation and finite union. (The negation and disjunction of propositions are also propositions.) (ii) P is closedunder formulas i.e. for each structure A = (W, P,v) and for each formula A, IxEW : El- A EP. (Each formula expresses a proposition under any interpretation.) (iii) P is the power set of W, i.e. the set of all subsets of W. (For each set of worlds there is a proposition true in exactly those worlds.) These three conditions lead to three corresponding theories. Let S5x - (S5x; S5x +) be the set of formulas valid in each struc- ture A = (W, P, v) such that P is Boolean (closed under formulas, the power set of W). It should be clear that S5x - c S5x c S5x + . One can also show that the inclusions are proper. 338 KIT FINE 1.2. Axiomatizability Let Ax S5x- consist of the following axiom-schemes and rules of inference: 1. All tautologous formulas. 2. o(A+B)+(OA+OB). 3. UA+A. 4. -OA+O-OA. 5. (p)A(p)-+A(B), B a formula of PC, the non-modal propositional calculus, free for p in Alp). 6. (PICA 'B) -+llP)A +CP)B). 7. A+(p)A, p not free in A. MP. A, A+B/B. Nec. A/OA. Gen. A/(p)A. AxS5x is AxS5x -without scheme 5, Restricted Specification, but with Specification: 8. (p)A(p)-+A(B), B any formula free for p in A(p). AxS5x +is AxS5n with the axiom: 9. C3Pl)(Pl8Z CPaI(P2 -aPl 'Pa))) It should be clear that scheme 5 corresponds to the condition that the set of propositions P be Boolean and that scheme 8 corresponds to the condition that P be closed under formulas. Axiom 9 (with Nec.) corresponds to the condition that P be atomic over the set of worlds W, i.e. that for each x E W there is an atom in P (a minimal non-empty a in P) such that x E a. If one identifies indistinguishable worlds, i.e. those which belong to the same propositions in P, then axiom 9 says that each world is describable, i.e. that for each x E W, {x} E P. PROPOSITION l.3AxS5x - , AxS5x and AxS5x + are axiornatizations of S5x - , S5x and S5x + respectively. 8 R. Bull independently established this result for S5x and S5x+ [2]. His proof is by semantic tableaux, and his semantics is slightly different from mine. D. Kaplan independently established this result for S5x+ [5].His proof is by quantifier elimination, as in Proposition 2 below. PROPOSITIONAL QUANTIFIERS IN MODAL LOGIC 339 The simplest direct proof of these results is by the Henkin- Scott-Makinson method of maximally consistent (mc) theories (see [7]). One uses a technique of Cresswell's [3] to guarantee that each mc theory has the same language, and for S5x+ one also uses a construction which for each mc theory provides a variable which belongs to that theory and that theory alone. 1.3. Decidability PROPOSITION 2. The theories S5x + and S5x are decidable. The proof proceeds by the elimination of quantifiers. Let L, be the language L with the unary operators MI, k = 1,2, . ., and let L, be L1 with the propositional constant g. For the new symbols we add the following clauses to the truth-definition: (vi) EMSiff at least k distinct atoms of P are inclu- ded in { y : €81. (vii) g iff x belongs to an atom of P. Given that indistinguishable worlds are identified, MkA says that A is true in at least k describable worlds, and g says that the actual world x is describable. One proves the decidability of S5x + (S5x) by showing that: A. There is an effective way of finding for each formula A of L a quantifier-free formula B of L1 (LJ such that A-eB E S5x + (S5x); and B. The set of quantifier-free formulas of L, n S5x + (L, n S5x) is effective. It is possible to define Mk and g within the language L. Write: QA for OA & ($)COCA +p) v C](A --f - p)) where p is the first variable not free in A. Then the following equivalences are valid in all structures: 340 KIT FINE AL(Qqi 8~ O(qi +A))), where qi is the i-th variable not free in A, i = 1, . , 12, k = 1, 2, . .. 11. g q3Pl)(Pl & QPJ By adding 10 (10 and 11) as axioms to AxSSx + (AxS5x), we may carry out the elimination argument above in the axiomatized theories. This gives a new proof of completeness. I presume that the above method could also be used to prove the decidability of S5x- . However, the details would be formi- dable, and, to date, my patience has not been the equal of my presumption. 1.4. Predicate and Boolean analogies S~X+is inter-translatable with the first-order theory of atomic Boolean algebras and also with M, the second-order monadic predicate calculus. For example, the translation T from formulas of S5x + to formulas of M is defined by: Tpj = Pixi; T-B= -TB; T(BvC)=TBvTB; TUB = (xi)TB; T(p i)B = (Pr)TB; where the Pi are quantifiers over predicates. One may easily show that: A. T is an effective map. B. A formula A of L is in S5x + iff TA is valid in M. A and B with the classical result that M is decidable provide a new proof of decidability for S5x + . S5x is inter-translatable with the first-order theory of separable Boolean algebras and, of course, with the second-order calculus defined by {TA : A E S~X}.(A Boolean algebra is separable if the set of all atoms in the algebra has a least upper bound). The former result depends upon: PROPOSITIONAL QUANTIFIERS IN MODAL LOGIC 341 PROPOSITION 3. P is closed under formulas if P is Boolean and separ- able. Syntactically, this proposition says that S5x can be axiomatized by adding to AxS5x - the axiom: 12. (~p1)0(p1og). (g, like Mr, will now be used as an abbreviation). The only proof 1 have of this result is indirect. It consists in showing that the quantifier-elimination argument for AxS5x also goes through for the new axiomatization. The elementary theory of Boolean algebras is translatable into S5x-, and I suspect that there is also a translation in the other direction. 1.5. Some further theories There is the following correspondence between conditions on P and axioms: P atomic g P atomless -g P atomic or atomless g -+Og P infinite MITvO-g, MaTvO-g, ... where T = (pl)(pl -+ pl). This means that the theory for a condition or combination of conditions on the left can be axiomatized by adding to AxS5x- the corresponding axioms on the right. Completeness and decida- bility for all such theories can be proved by quantifier elimination. Some of the theories are of special interest: (i) P atomic. The theory for this condition is the same as S5x + . In other words, the distinction between P being atomic and P being a power set cannot be expressed within L. The stronger condition would most naturally be expressed by using quantifiers over sets of propositions. (ii) P atomless. The theory for this condition does justice to a non-Platonist conception of proposition. (Every proposition is expressed by a sentence.) 342 KIT FINE (iii) P atomic or atomless. The theory for this condition is the intersection of the two theories above.
Recommended publications
  • Chapter 2 Introduction to Classical Propositional
    CHAPTER 2 INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC 1 Motivation and History The origins of the classical propositional logic, classical propositional calculus, as it was, and still often is called, go back to antiquity and are due to Stoic school of philosophy (3rd century B.C.), whose most eminent representative was Chryssipus. But the real development of this calculus began only in the mid-19th century and was initiated by the research done by the English math- ematician G. Boole, who is sometimes regarded as the founder of mathematical logic. The classical propositional calculus was ¯rst formulated as a formal ax- iomatic system by the eminent German logician G. Frege in 1879. The assumption underlying the formalization of classical propositional calculus are the following. Logical sentences We deal only with sentences that can always be evaluated as true or false. Such sentences are called logical sentences or proposi- tions. Hence the name propositional logic. A statement: 2 + 2 = 4 is a proposition as we assume that it is a well known and agreed upon truth. A statement: 2 + 2 = 5 is also a proposition (false. A statement:] I am pretty is modeled, if needed as a logical sentence (proposi- tion). We assume that it is false, or true. A statement: 2 + n = 5 is not a proposition; it might be true for some n, for example n=3, false for other n, for example n= 2, and moreover, we don't know what n is. Sentences of this kind are called propositional functions. We model propositional functions within propositional logic by treating propositional functions as propositions.
    [Show full text]
  • 12 Propositional Logic
    CHAPTER 12 ✦ ✦ ✦ ✦ Propositional Logic In this chapter, we introduce propositional logic, an algebra whose original purpose, dating back to Aristotle, was to model reasoning. In more recent times, this algebra, like many algebras, has proved useful as a design tool. For example, Chapter 13 shows how propositional logic can be used in computer circuit design. A third use of logic is as a data model for programming languages and systems, such as the language Prolog. Many systems for reasoning by computer, including theorem provers, program verifiers, and applications in the field of artificial intelligence, have been implemented in logic-based programming languages. These languages generally use “predicate logic,” a more powerful form of logic that extends the capabilities of propositional logic. We shall meet predicate logic in Chapter 14. ✦ ✦ ✦ ✦ 12.1 What This Chapter Is About Section 12.2 gives an intuitive explanation of what propositional logic is, and why it is useful. The next section, 12,3, introduces an algebra for logical expressions with Boolean-valued operands and with logical operators such as AND, OR, and NOT that Boolean algebra operate on Boolean (true/false) values. This algebra is often called Boolean algebra after George Boole, the logician who first framed logic as an algebra. We then learn the following ideas. ✦ Truth tables are a useful way to represent the meaning of an expression in logic (Section 12.4). ✦ We can convert a truth table to a logical expression for the same logical function (Section 12.5). ✦ The Karnaugh map is a useful tabular technique for simplifying logical expres- sions (Section 12.6).
    [Show full text]
  • Propositional Calculus
    CSC 438F/2404F Notes Winter, 2014 S. Cook REFERENCES The first two references have especially influenced these notes and are cited from time to time: [Buss] Samuel Buss: Chapter I: An introduction to proof theory, in Handbook of Proof Theory, Samuel Buss Ed., Elsevier, 1998, pp1-78. [B&M] John Bell and Moshe Machover: A Course in Mathematical Logic. North- Holland, 1977. Other logic texts: The first is more elementary and readable. [Enderton] Herbert Enderton: A Mathematical Introduction to Logic. Academic Press, 1972. [Mendelson] E. Mendelson: Introduction to Mathematical Logic. Wadsworth & Brooks/Cole, 1987. Computability text: [Sipser] Michael Sipser: Introduction to the Theory of Computation. PWS, 1997. [DSW] M. Davis, R. Sigal, and E. Weyuker: Computability, Complexity and Lan- guages: Fundamentals of Theoretical Computer Science. Academic Press, 1994. Propositional Calculus Throughout our treatment of formal logic it is important to distinguish between syntax and semantics. Syntax is concerned with the structure of strings of symbols (e.g. formulas and formal proofs), and rules for manipulating them, without regard to their meaning. Semantics is concerned with their meaning. 1 Syntax Formulas are certain strings of symbols as specified below. In this chapter we use formula to mean propositional formula. Later the meaning of formula will be extended to first-order formula. (Propositional) formulas are built from atoms P1;P2;P3;:::, the unary connective :, the binary connectives ^; _; and parentheses (,). (The symbols :; ^ and _ are read \not", \and" and \or", respectively.) We use P; Q; R; ::: to stand for atoms. Formulas are defined recursively as follows: Definition of Propositional Formula 1) Any atom P is a formula.
    [Show full text]
  • A Formal Mereology of Potential Parts
    Not Another Brick in the Wall: an Extensional Mereology for Potential Parts Contents 0. Abstract .................................................................................................................................................................................................. 1 1. An Introduction to Potential Parts .......................................................................................................................................................... 1 2. The Physical Motivation for Potential Parts ............................................................................................................................................ 5 3. A Model for Potential Parts .................................................................................................................................................................... 9 3.1 Informal Semantics: Dressed Electron Propagator as Mereological Model ...................................................................................... 9 3.2 Formal Semantics: A Join Semi-Lattice ............................................................................................................................................ 10 3.3 Syntax: Mereological Axioms for Potential Parts ............................................................................................................................ 14 4. Conclusions About Potential Parts .......................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Why Would You Trust B? Eric Jaeger, Catherine Dubois
    Why Would You Trust B? Eric Jaeger, Catherine Dubois To cite this version: Eric Jaeger, Catherine Dubois. Why Would You Trust B?. Logic for Programming, Artificial In- telligence, and Reasoning, Nov 2007, Yerevan, Armenia. pp.288-302, 10.1007/978-3-540-75560-9. hal-00363345 HAL Id: hal-00363345 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00363345 Submitted on 23 Feb 2009 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Why Would You Trust B? Eric´ Jaeger12 and Catherine Dubois3 1 LIP6, Universit´eParis 6, 4 place Jussieu, 75252 Paris Cedex 05, France 2 LTI, Direction centrale de la s´ecurit´edes syst`emes d’information, 51 boulevard de La Tour-Maubourg, 75700 Paris 07 SP, France 3 CEDRIC, Ecole´ nationale sup´erieure d’informatique pour l’industrie et l’entreprise, 18 all´ee Jean Rostand, 91025 Evry Cedex, France Abstract. The use of formal methods provides confidence in the cor- rectness of developments. Yet one may argue about the actual level of confidence obtained when the method itself – or its implementation – is not formally checked. We address this question for the B, a widely used formal method that allows for the derivation of correct programs from specifications.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Formal Methods for Philosophy Students
    An Introduction to Formal Methods for Philosophy Students Thomas Forster February 20, 2021 2 Contents 1 Introduction 13 1.1 What is Logic? . 13 1.1.1 Exercises for the first week: “Sheet 0” . 13 2 Introduction to Logic 17 2.1 Statements, Commands, Questions, Performatives . 18 2.1.1 Truth-functional connectives . 20 2.1.2 Truth Tables . 21 2.2 The Language of Propositional Logic . 23 2.2.1 Truth-tables for compound expressions . 24 2.2.2 Logical equivalence . 26 2.2.3 Non truth functional connectives . 27 2.3 Intension and Extension . 28 2.3.1 If–then . 31 2.3.2 Logical Form and Valid Argument . 33 2.3.3 The Type-Token Distinction . 33 2.3.4 Copies . 35 2.4 Tautology and Validity . 36 2.4.1 Valid Argument . 36 2.4.2 V and W versus ^ and _ .................... 40 2.4.3 Conjunctive and Disjunctive Normal Form . 41 2.5 Further Useful Logical Gadgetry . 46 2.5.1 The Analytic-Synthetic Distinction . 46 2.5.2 Necessary and Sufficient Conditions . 47 2.5.3 The Use-Mention Distinction . 48 2.5.4 Language-metalanguage distinction . 51 2.5.5 Semantic Optimisation and the Principle of Charity . 52 2.5.6 Inferring A-or-B from A . 54 2.5.7 Fault-tolerant pattern-matching . 54 2.5.8 Overinterpretation . 54 2.5.9 Affirming the consequent . 55 3 4 CONTENTS 3 Proof Systems for Propositional Logic 57 3.1 Arguments by LEGO . 57 3.2 The Rules of Natural Deduction . 57 3.2.1 Worries about reductio and hypothetical reasoning .
    [Show full text]
  • Michael Jraven
    MICHAEL J RAVEN Department of Philosophy | University of Victoria P.O. BOX 1700 STN CSC | Victoria, BC V8W 2Y2 | CANADA [email protected] • raven.site RESEARCH INTERESTS metaphysics • ground; fundamentality; essence; social items; time; change language/mind • de re thought; mental states; aesthetic judgment epistemology • explanation; epistemic relativism ACADEMIC POSITIONS Professor, Philosophy, University of Victoria 2021— Affiliate Professor, Philosophy, University of Washington 2018— Associate Professor, Philosophy, University of Victoria 2013—2021 Visiting Scholar, Philosophy, University of Washington 2016-2017, 2012-2013 Assistant Professor, Philosophy, University of Victoria 2009-2013 Instructor, Philosophy, New York University 2008-2009 EDUCATION PHD, Philosophy, New York University 2009 [Kit Fine (chair), Ted Sider, Crispin Wright] MA, Philosophy, New York University 2007 [Ned Block (adviser) BA, Philosophy, Reed College 2002 [Mark Hinchliff (adviser)] GRANTS & FELLOWSHIPS Connection Grant ($15,640), Social Science & Humanities Research Council 2020 Humanities Faculty Fellowship (course release), University of Victoria 2020 Insight Grant ($152,589), Social Science & Humanities Research Council 2018-2022 [principal investigator: 2021-2022, collaborator: 2018-2020; co-applicant with Kathrin Koslicki] Connection Grant ($15,965), Social Science & Humanities Research Council 2018 Internal Research Grants ($29,428 total), University of Victoria 2010-2014,2016,2020 Conference Grant ($2000 - declined), Canadian Journal of Philosophy
    [Show full text]
  • Matter and Mereology∗
    Matter and mereology∗ Jeremy Goodman Draft of March 22, 2015 I am a material thing. But I am not the same thing as the matter out of which I am composed, since my matter, unlike me, could have existed as scattered interstellar dust. The distinction between matter and objects that are merely composed of matter is central to our ordinary conception of the material world. According to that conception, material objects have a hierarchical structure with matter at its foundation. This paper shows how matter and material constitution can be understood in terms of the part-whole relation.1 I present a novel mereology and apply it to debates about the persistence and plenitude of material objects, and compare my view to more familiar hylomorphic ones. A formal model of the theory is given in an appendix. 1 Anti-symmetry Consider the following principle: weak supplementation: If x is a proper part of y, then y has a part that does not overlap x. where x is a proper part of y =df x is a part of y and x 6= y. x overlaps y =df some part of x is part of y. Everyday cases of material coincidence are counterexamples to weak supple- mentation. A statue s composed of some clay c. c is distinct from s, since squashing c would destroy s but would not destroy c.2 c is part of s, since any ∗Thanks to Andrew Bacon, Cian Dorr, Maegan Fairchild, Kit Fine, Peter Fritz, John Hawthorne, Harvey Lederman, Gabriel Uzquiano, Tim Williamson and an anonymous referee for No^us for comments on previous versions of this paper, and to an audience at the University of Cambridge.
    [Show full text]
  • Vagueness at Every Order
    Vagueness at every order Andrew Bacon* May 4, 2020 Abstract There are some properties, like being bald, for which it is vague where the boundary between the things that have it, and the things that do not, lies. A number of argument threaten to show that such properties can still be associated with determinate and knowable boundaries: not between the things that have it and those that don't, but between the things such that it is borderline at some order whether they have it, and the things for which it is not. I argue that these arguments, if successful, turn on a contentious prin- ciple in the logic of determinacy: Brouwer's Principle, that every truth is determinately not determinately false. Other paradoxes which do not appear to turn on this principle often tacitly make assumptions about assertion, knowledge and higher order vagueness. In this paper I'll show how one can avoid sharp higher-order boundaries by rejecting these as- sumptions. I used to be a child, but now I am not. It follows, given classical logic, that I stopped being a child at some point. Indeed, there was a first nanosecond at which I stopped: a nanosecond before which I was a child (or unborn) but at which I was not a child. Although such a nanosecond exists, it is a vague matter when it occurred: it happened during a period when it was borderline whether I was a child. Different theories provide different accounts of what borderlineness consists in | perhaps it's ignorance, or semantic indecision, or something else.
    [Show full text]
  • The Question of Realism Ity
    My aim in this paper is to help lay the conceptual and meth- odological foundations for the study of realism. I come to two main conclusions: first, that there is a primitive meta- physical concept of reality, one that cannot be understood in fundamentally different terms; and second, that questions of what is real are to be settled upon the basis of considerations of ground. The two conclusions are somewhat in tension with one another, for the lack of a definition of the concept of reality would appear to stand in the way of developing a sound methodology for determining its application; and one of my main concerns has been to show how the tension be- tween the two might be resolved. The paper is in two main parts. In the first, I point to the difficulties in making out a metaphysical conception of real- The Question of Realism ity. I begin by distinguishing this conception from the ordi- nary conception of reality (§1) and then show how the two leading contenders for the metaphysical conception—the factual and the irreducible—both appear to resist formula- tion in other terms. This leads to the quietist challenge, that Kit Fine questions of realism are either meaningless or pointless (§4); and the second part of the paper (§§5-10) is largely devoted to showing how this challenge might be met. I begin by in- troducing the notion of ground (§5) and then show how it can be used as a basis for resolving questions both of factual- ity (§§6-7) and of irreducibility (§§8-9).
    [Show full text]
  • Categorical Proof Theory of Classical Propositional Calculus
    Categorical Proof Theory of Classical Propositional Calculus Gianluigi Bellin Martin Hyland Edmund Robinson Christian Urban Queen Mary, University of London, UK University of Cambridge, UK Technical University of Munich (TUM), D Abstract We investigate semantics for classical proof based on the sequent calculus. We show that the propositional connectives are not quite well-behaved from a traditional categorical per- spective, and give a more refined, but necessarily complex, analysis of how connectives may be characterised abstractly. Finally we explain the consequences of insisting on more familiar categorical behaviour. Key words: classical logic, proof theory, category theory 1 Introduction In this paper we describe the shape of a semantics for classical proof in accord with Gentzen’s sequent calculus. For constructive proof we have the familiar correspondence between deductions in minimal logic and terms of a typed lambda calculus. Deductions in minimal logic (as in most constructive systems) reduce to a unique normal form, and around 1970 Per Martin-L¨of (see [18]) suggested using equality of normal forms as the identity criterion for proof objects in his constructive Type Theories: normal forms serve as the semantics of proof. But ¬ -normal forms for typed lambda calculus give maps in a free cartesian closed category; so we get a whole range of categorical models of constructive proof. This is the circle of connections surrounding the Curry-Howard isomorphism. We seek analogues of these ideas for classical proof. There are a number of immediate problems. The established term languages for classical proofs are either incompatible with the symmetries apparent in the sequent calculus (Parigot [16]) or in reconciling themselves to that symmetry at least make evaluation deterministic (cf Danos et al [5,21]).
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Derivability of the Concept of Meaning, Formulation I
    IOSR Journal of Humanities and Social Science (IOSRJHSS) ISSN: 2279-0845 Volume 1, Issue 5 (Sep-Oct 2012), PP 01-04 www.iosrjournals.org Logical Derivability of the Concept of Meaning, Formulation I Jonathan Chimakonam Okeke, Department of Philosophy,University of Calabar, Calabar, P. M. B 1115, Cross River State Nigeria ABSTRACT: Expressions, words and symbols without reference to something else which could be called their meanings are semantically helpless. But not all expressions and words refer; some even come with ambiguities and equivocations like Golden Mountain, Chimera etc., however, any symbol which does not refer could not properly be called a symbol. So because every symbol necessarily refers to something definite, it is not the case that ambiguities and equivocations would sneak into symbolic expressions. Hence, logic becomes that science which prefers symbolic or artificial or formal language to natural language. Therefore, since “meaning” or semantics is a central focus of logic together with syntax, we attempted in this work to obtain a logical derivation of it in the symbolic language of logic devoid of the ambiguities and equivocations of natural language. Keywords- language, logic, meaning, semantics, symbol, syntax. I. Introduction Meaning can be defined as having a fixed sense or conveying a fixed idea or a fixed thought. This means that having a transitory or tentative sense does not qualify as having meaning. In philosophy of language meaning is very crucial for our words and sentences will be useless if they contain no meaning. But meaning is not something peculiar to words or sentences alone, it can in similar way be extended to symbols or whatever stands as symbol.
    [Show full text]