Copyrighted Material

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Copyrighted Material INDEX Abel, Niels, 342 Axiom scheme, 228 Abelian group, 342 Axiom(s), 24 Absolute value, 116 choice, 231, 235 Abstraction, 122 empty set, 227 Addition, inference rule, 25 equality, 226 Addition, matrix, 355 extensionality, 227 Additive identity, 199, 412 foundation, 234 Additive inverse, 199 Frege–Łukasiewicz, 24 Aleph, 313 group, 340 Algebraic, 315 paring, 228 Alphabet, 5 power set, 228 first-order, 68 regularity, 234 second-order, 73 replacement, 230 And, 4 ring, 353 Antecedent, 4 COPYRIGHTED MATERIALseparation, 228 Antichain, 183 subset, 229 Antisymmetric, 177 union, 228 Arbitrary, 88 Zermelo, 231 Argument form, 21 Axiomatizable, finitely, 409 Assignment, 7 Associative, 34, 139, 199, 412 Basis case, 258 Assumption, 46 Bernstein, Felix, 301 Asymmetric, 177 Beth, 316 Atom, 3, 6 Biconditional, 5 Automorphism, 380 Biconditional proof, 107 435 AFirst Course in Mathematical Logic and Set Theory, First Edition. Michael L. O’Leary. © 2016 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Published 2016 by John Wiley & Sons, Inc. 436 INDEX Bijection, 211 Complement, 128 Binary, 68 Complete, 56, 398 function, 189 Complete theory, 423 operation, 198 Completeness theorem, 61, 407 relation, 161 Gödel’s, 407 Binomial coefficient, 263 Completeness, real numbers, 275 Binomial theorem, 263 Complex number, 281 Boole, George, 117 Composite number, 107 Bound Composition, 163, 195 lower, 181 Compound, 4, 6 upper, 180 Concatenation, 178 Bound occurrence, 77 Conclusion, 22, 26 Burali-Forti paradox, 297 Conditional, 4 Burali-Forti theorem, 292 Conditional proof, 45 Congruent, 170 Cancellation, 248, 256, 414 Conjunct, 4 Candidate, 99 Conjunction, 4 Cantor–Schröder–Bernstein theorem, 301 Conjunction, inference rule, 25 Cantor, Georg, 117, 226, 229, 303, 313 Connective, 6 Cardinal, 307 Consequence, 22, 346, 352 large, 332 Consequent, 4 limit, 314 Consistency, relative, 407 regular, 328 Consistent, 52, 395 singular, 328 maximally, 53, 396 strongly inaccessible, 332 Constant symbol, 68 successor, 314 Constructive dilemma, 25 weakly inaccessible, 331 Contingency, 16 Cardinality, 308 Continuous, 94 Cartesian n-space, 131 Continuum hypothesis, 313 Cartesian plane, 130 generalized, 314 Cartesian product, 130 Contradiction, 16 Cases, 112 Contradiction, proof by, 47 Chain, 182 Contrapositive, 32, 103 elementary, 394 Contrapositive law, 34 of structures, 372 Converse, 32 Characteristic function, 304 Coordinates, 130 Choice axiom, 231, 235 Coordinatewise, 356 Choice function, 231 Copy, 214 Class, 420 Corollary, 20 Class (relation), 171 Corresponding occurrences, 77 Closed, 198 Countable, 310 Closed interval, 120 Counterexample, 102 Closed under deductions, 409 Cyclic group, 363, 365 Codomain, 190 Cofinal, 328 De Morgan, Augustus, 117 Cofinality, 328 De Morgan’s laws, 35, 137, 139 Cohen, Paul, 424 Decreasing, 184, 203 Coincidence, 349 Dedekind cut, 276 Combinatorics, 260 Dedekind, Richard, 229, 276 Common divisor, 140 Deduce, 26 Commutative, 34, 139, 199, 412 Deduction, 20 Commutative ring, 354 Deduction theorem, 42 Compactness theorem, 52, 415 Deductive logic, 2 Comparable, 181 Dense, 257 Compatible, 183 Denumerable, 310 INDEX 437 Descartes, René, 117 Even integer, 98 Destructive dilemma, 25 Excluded middle, 37 Diagonalization, 303 Exclusive or, 11 Diamond principle, 424 Existence, 104 Direct existential proof, 99 Existential formula, 72 Direct proof, 45 Existential generalization, 91 Discrete, 310 Existential instantiation, 91 Disjoint, 127, 155 Existential proof, 99, 106 pairwise, 155 Existential proposition, 65 Disjunct, 4 Existential quantifier, 65 Disjunction, 4 Expansion, 352 Disjunctive normal form, 38 Exponentiation, 249, 321, 322 Disjunctive syllogism, 25 Exportation, 35 Distributive, 34, 139, 246, 323, 412 Extension, 197, 361 left, 320 elementary, 389 Divides, 98 Extensionality axiom, 227 Divisible, 98 Division algorithm, 185 Factor, 98, 110 polynomial, 110 Factorial, 242 Division ring, 357 False, 3 Divisor, 98 Family of sets, 148 common, 140 Fibonacci, 268 zero, 356 Fibonacci number, 269 Domain, 162, 334 Fibonacci sequence, 269 Dominate, 300 generalized, 273 Double negation, 35 Field, 357 Downward closed, 274 ordered, 69, 425 Downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, 415 Field theory, 69 Finite, 308 Element, 117 hereditarily, 417 Elementary chain, 394 Finitely axiomatizable, 409 Elementary equivalent, 387 First-order Elementary extension, 389 alphabet, 68 Elementary substructure, 389 formula, 73 Embedding, 214 language, 73 Empty set, 118, 141, 227 logic, 96 Empty set axiom, 227 Formal proof, 26 Empty string, 6 Formation sequence, 7 Endpoint, 120 Formula, 71, 72 Equal, 118 first-order, 73 Equality, 194 second-order, 73 Equality axioms, 226 Foundation axiom, 234 Equality symbol, 68 Fraenkel, Abraham, 229 Equinumerous, 298 Fraktur, 334, 428 Equivalence class, 171 Free occurrence, 77 Equivalence relation, 169 Free variable, 78 induced, 175 Frege, Gottlob, 24, 117 Equivalence rule, 110 Function, 189 Equivalence, logical, 31, 348 bijection, 211 Equivalent binary, 189 elementary, 387 characteristic, 304 pairwise, 109 choice, 231 Euclid, 19, 107, 265 continuous, 94 Euclid’s lemma, 265 decreasing, 203 Evaluation map, 193 embedding, 214 438 INDEX evaluation, 193 Half-open interval, 120 greatest integer, 192 Hartogs’ function, 327 homomorphism, 375 Hartogs’ theorem, 293 identity, 191 Hausdorff maximal principle, 237 inclusion, 203 Henkin, Leon, 399 increasing, 203 Henkin’s theorem, 406 injection, 206 Hereditarily finite sets, 417 inverse, 204 Hereditary set, 235 invertible, 204 Hierarchy, von Neumann, 417 isomorphism, 382 Hilbert, David, 226, 408 one-to-one, 206 Hilbert’s problems, 408 one-to-one correspondence, 211 Homomorphism, 375 onto, 208 group, 375 order-preserving, 212 ring, 375 periodic, 203 Hypothetical syllogism, 25 projection, 210 real-valued, 193 Ideal, 368 surjection, 208 improper, 368 unary, 189 left, 368 uniformly continuous, 94 maximal, 374 zero, 376 prime, 374 principal, 370 Function equality, 194 principal left, 370 Function notation, 190 proper, 368 Function symbol, 68 right, 368 Fundamental homomorphism theorem, 383 Idempotent laws, 139 Fundamental theorem of arithmetic, 271 Identity, 162, 199 additive, 199 Galois, Évariste, 342 multiplicative, 199 General linear group, 345 Identity map, 191 Generalization, 85 Image, 190, 208, 216 existential, 91 Implication, 4 universal, 88 Improper ideal, 368 Generalized continuum hypothesis, 314 Improper subgroup, 363 Generalized Fibonacci sequence, 273 Improper subring, 366 Generator, 363, 370 Improper subset, 136 Gödel, Kurt, 399, 407, 414, 423 Inaccessible cardinal, 331 Gödel’s completeness theorem, 407 Inclusion map, 203 Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, 423 Inclusive or, 11 Golden ratio, 271 Incomparable, 181 Grammar, 6 Incompatible, 183 Greatest common divisor, 140 Incomplete theory, 423 Greatest element, 180 Incompleteness theorems, 423 Greatest integer function, 192 Inconsistent, 52, 395 Greatest lower bound, 181 Increasing, 184, 203 Grounded, 419 Independent, 408 Group, 342 Index, 148 abelian, 342 Index set, 148 cyclic, 363 Indexed, 149 general linear, 345 Indirect existential proof, 106 Klein-4, 344 Indirect proof, 47 simple, 363 Induced equivalence relation, 175 Group axioms, 340 Induced partition, 174 Group theory, 69 Induction Grouping symbol, 6 mathematical, 257 INDEX 439 on formulas, 336 König’s theorem, 330 on propositional forms, 59 Kuratowski, Kazimierz, 130, 232, 237 on terms, 335 strong, 268 Language, 73 transfinite, 283, 291 first order, 73 Induction hypothesis, 59, 258 Large cardinal, 332 Induction step, 258 Law of noncontradiction, 37 Inductive logic, 1 Law of the excluded middle, 37 Inductive set, 238 Least element, 180 Infer, 24 Least upper bound, 180 Inference, 24 Left distributive, 320 Inference rule, 25 Left ideal, 368 Infinite, 308, 344 Left inverse, 215 Infinity axiom, 227 Left zero divisor, 356 Infinity symbol, 120 Leibniz, Gottfried, 117 Initial number, 327 Lemma, 20 Initial segment, 274 Leonardo of Pisa, 268 proper, 274 Lexicographical order, 187 Injection, 206 Liber abaci, 268 Instantiation, 85 Limit cardinal, 314 existential, 91 Limit ordinal, 290 universal, 87 Lindenbaum’s theorem, 397 Integers, 250 Linear combination, 186 Integral domain, 356 Linear order, 182 International Congress of Mathematicians, 408 Linearly ordered set, 182 Interpretation, 335 Logic, 1 Intersection, 126, 152 deductive, 2 Interval, 120 first-order, 96 Interval notation, 120 inductive, 1 Introduction, 97 mathematical, 2 Invalid propositional, 20 semantically, 21 second-order, 96 syntactically, 21 Logic symbol, 67 Inverse, 166, 199 Logical implication, 21 additive, 199 Logical system, 20 function, 204 Logically equivalent, 31, 348 image, 216 Löwenheim, Leopold, 415 left, 215 Löwenheim’s theorem, 416 multiplicative, 199 Löwenheim–Skolem theorem right, 216 downward, 415 Inverse image, 216 upward, 416 Inverse relation, 166 Lower bound, 181 Inverse statement, 37 greatest, 181 Invertible function, 204 Łukasiewicz, Jan, 24, 71 Invertible matrix, 345 Irrational number, 128, 276 Mal’tsev, Anatolij, 414 Irreflexive, 177 Map, 190 Isomorphic, 212, 344, 380, 382 Martin’s axiom, 424 Isomorphism, 212, 380 Material equivalence, 13, 35 group, 382 Material implication, 12, 35 ring, 382 Mathematical induction, 257 strong, 268 Kernel, 379 Mathematical logic, 2 Klein-4 group, 344, 363 Mathematics, 1 König, Julius, 301, 330 Mathesis universalis, 117 440 INDEX Matrix, 345 partial, 178 identity, 345 well, 183 invertible, 345 Order isomorphism, 212 zero, 355 Order of connectives, 8, 9 Matrix addition, 355 Order of operations, 132 Matrix multiplication, 345 Order
Recommended publications
  • Handbook Vatican 2014
    HANDBOOK OF THE WORLD CONGRESS ON THE SQUARE OF OPPOSITION IV Pontifical Lateran University, Vatican May 5-9, 2014 Edited by Jean-Yves Béziau and Katarzyna Gan-Krzywoszyńska www.square-of-opposition.org 1 2 Contents 1. Fourth World Congress on the Square of Opposition ..................................................... 7 1.1. The Square : a Central Object for Thought ..................................................................................7 1.2. Aim of the Congress.....................................................................................................................8 1.3. Scientific Committee ...................................................................................................................9 1.4. Organizing Committee .............................................................................................................. 10 2. Plenary Lectures ................................................................................................... 11 Gianfranco Basti "Scientia una contrariorum": Paraconsistency, Induction, and Formal Ontology ..... 11 Jean-Yves Béziau Square of Opposition: Past, Present and Future ....................................................... 12 Manuel Correia Machuca The Didactic and Theoretical Expositions of the Square of Opposition in Aristotelian logic ....................................................................................................................... 13 Rusty Jones Bivalence and Contradictory Pairs in Aristotle’s De Interpretatione ................................
    [Show full text]
  • Two Squares of Opposition: the Conceptual Square Underwrites the Alethic Square’S Validity
    1 TWO SQUARES OF OPPOSITION: THE CONCEPTUAL SQUARE UNDERWRITES THE ALETHIC SQUARE’S VALIDITY ABSTRACT I have made explicit an implicit conceptual logic that exists in the English lang- uage and others; its evaluation terms of propositions are coherent|incoherent. This con- trasts with the usual alethic true|false evaluations for statement logic. I call conceptual logic a basement logic; it’s more basic than statement logic. I demonstrate this by show- ing how the long-standard, ever-present Alethic Square of Opposition’s AEIO state- ments’ truth value and the validity of their immediate inferences rests on the Conceptual Square’s (a) coherent propositions and (b) coherent emplacements of substantives and tropes into, respectively, AEIOs’ subjects and predicates. ConceptFunctor operations bear the leutic [Enjoined] modal that governs the coherence of de dicto and de jure grounded propositions. The FactFunctor operation bears the [Allowed] modal that govern coherent emplacement of the world’s substantives and tropes into sentences’ subjects and predicates and, subsequent to that, the truth value of their allied statements. My strategy is (1) to construct a Conceptual Square of Opposition by rewriting the Aletic Square’s AEIO statements as conceptual propositions. (2) If the propositions are coherent by virtue of coherent emplacements of substantives and tropes into their subjects and predicates that turns them into conceptualized substantives and tropes, then, by the Coherence Account of Truth, they entail the truth of the Alethic Squares’ statements and the validity of its traditionally accepted inferences. (3) This is enough to prove conceptual logic is the basement ground for the traditional Alethic Square, and on which any alethic logic rests; and it supports the claims made in (2) above.1 KEY WORDS: Coherence, [Emplace], [Functor], ConceptFunctor, FactFunctor, [Any], collective, distributive, and singular (uses of [Any]), grammatical and semantic subjects and predicates, Concepttual and Alethic Square (of opposition), leutic modal- ities, [Enjoin], [Allow].
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Extensions of Aristotle's Square
    Logical Extensions of Aristotle’s Square Dominique Luzeaux, Jean Sallantin, Christopher Dartnell To cite this version: Dominique Luzeaux, Jean Sallantin, Christopher Dartnell. Logical Extensions of Aristotle’s Square. Logica Universalis, Springer Verlag, 2008, 2, pp.167-187. 10.1007/s11787-007-0022-y. lirmm- 00274314 HAL Id: lirmm-00274314 https://hal-lirmm.ccsd.cnrs.fr/lirmm-00274314 Submitted on 17 Apr 2008 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Logical extensions of Aristotle's square Dominique Luzeaux, Jean Sallantin and Christopher Dartnell Abstract. We start from the geometrical-logical extension of Aristotle's square in [Bla66], [Pel06] and [Mor04], and study them from both syntactic and semantic points of view. Recall that Aristotle's square under its modal form has the following four vertices: A is α, E is :α, I is ::α and O is :α, where α is a logical formula and is a modality which can be defined axiomatically within a particular logic known as S5 (classical or intuitionistic, depending on whether : is involutive or not) modal logic. [B´ez03]has proposed extensions which can be interpreted respectively within paraconsistent and paracomplete logical frameworks.
    [Show full text]
  • Alice in the Wonderful Land of Logical Notions)
    The Mystery of the Fifth Logical Notion (Alice in the Wonderful Land of Logical Notions) Jean-Yves Beziau University of Brazil, Rio de Janeiro, Brazilian Research Council and Brazilian Academy of Philosophy [email protected] Abstract We discuss a theory presented in a posthumous paper by Alfred Tarski entitled “What are logical notions?”. Although the theory of these logical notions is something outside of the main stream of logic, not presented in logic textbooks, it is a very interesting theory and can easily be understood by anybody, especially studying the simplest case of the four basic logical notions. This is what we are doing here, as well as introducing a challenging fifth logical notion. We first recall the context and origin of what are here called Tarski- Lindenbaum logical notions. In the second part, we present these notions in the simple case of a binary relation. In the third part, we examine in which sense these are considered as logical notions contrasting them with an example of a non-logical relation. In the fourth part, we discuss the formulations of the four logical notions in natural language and in first- order logic without equality, emphasizing the fact that two of the four logical notions cannot be expressed in this formal language. In the fifth part, we discuss the relations between these notions using the theory of the square of opposition. In the sixth part, we introduce the notion of variety corresponding to all non-logical notions and we argue that it can be considered as a logical notion because it is invariant, always referring to the same class of structures.
    [Show full text]
  • Saving the Square of Opposition∗
    HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC, 2021 https://doi.org/10.1080/01445340.2020.1865782 Saving the Square of Opposition∗ PIETER A. M. SEUREN Max Planck Institute for Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen, the Netherlands Received 19 April 2020 Accepted 15 December 2020 Contrary to received opinion, the Aristotelian Square of Opposition (square) is logically sound, differing from standard modern predicate logic (SMPL) only in that it restricts the universe U of cognitively constructible situations by banning null predicates, making it less unnatural than SMPL. U-restriction strengthens the logic without making it unsound. It also invites a cognitive approach to logic. Humans are endowed with a cogni- tive predicate logic (CPL), which checks the process of cognitive modelling (world construal) for consistency. The square is considered a first approximation to CPL, with a cognitive set-theoretic semantics. Not being cognitively real, the null set Ø is eliminated from the semantics of CPL. Still rudimentary in Aristotle’s On Interpretation (Int), the square was implicitly completed in his Prior Analytics (PrAn), thereby introducing U-restriction. Abelard’s reconstruction of the logic of Int is logically and historically correct; the loca (Leak- ing O-Corner Analysis) interpretation of the square, defended by some modern logicians, is logically faulty and historically untenable. Generally, U-restriction, not redefining the universal quantifier, as in Abelard and loca, is the correct path to a reconstruction of CPL. Valuation Space modelling is used to compute
    [Show full text]
  • Logic-Sensitivity of Aristotelian Diagrams in Non-Normal Modal Logics
    axioms Article Logic-Sensitivity of Aristotelian Diagrams in Non-Normal Modal Logics Lorenz Demey 1,2 1 Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science, KU Leuven, 3000 Leuven, Belgium; [email protected] 2 KU Leuven Institute for Artificial Intelligence, KU Leuven, 3000 Leuven, Belgium Abstract: Aristotelian diagrams, such as the square of opposition, are well-known in the context of normal modal logics (i.e., systems of modal logic which can be given a relational semantics in terms of Kripke models). This paper studies Aristotelian diagrams for non-normal systems of modal logic (based on neighborhood semantics, a topologically inspired generalization of relational semantics). In particular, we investigate the phenomenon of logic-sensitivity of Aristotelian diagrams. We distin- guish between four different types of logic-sensitivity, viz. with respect to (i) Aristotelian families, (ii) logical equivalence of formulas, (iii) contingency of formulas, and (iv) Boolean subfamilies of a given Aristotelian family. We provide concrete examples of Aristotelian diagrams that illustrate these four types of logic-sensitivity in the realm of normal modal logic. Next, we discuss more subtle examples of Aristotelian diagrams, which are not sensitive with respect to normal modal logics, but which nevertheless turn out to be highly logic-sensitive once we turn to non-normal systems of modal logic. Keywords: Aristotelian diagram; non-normal modal logic; square of opposition; logical geometry; neighborhood semantics; bitstring semantics MSC: 03B45; 03A05 Citation: Demey, L. Logic-Sensitivity of Aristotelian Diagrams in Non-Normal Modal Logics. Axioms 2021, 10, 128. https://doi.org/ 1. Introduction 10.3390/axioms10030128 Aristotelian diagrams, such as the so-called square of opposition, visualize a number Academic Editor: Radko Mesiar of formulas from some logical system, as well as certain logical relations holding between them.
    [Show full text]
  • Universal Machines
    Universal Machines In his magisterial Introduction to Logic, Paul Herrick (2013) not only guides the reader through a history of symbolic logic, but he also comments on the various links between logic and the history of computation. Aristotle, 384-322 BCE The Square of Opposition “We have seen that Aristotle’s Square of Opposition can be used to compute the truth-value of one statement given the truth-value of another. Mathematicians calls this type of procedure an algorithm… Aristotle’s Square of Opposition was the first large-scale, general-purpose algorithm in the history of logic. This might help explain why the first person in history to design a mechanical computer was an Aristotelian logician…” “Inspired by Aristotle’s Square of Opposition, Raymond Lull (1232-1315), a medieval logician who was also a Catholic priest, designed a computing machine consisting of two rotating disks, each inscribed with symbols for categorical propositions…” “The disks were aligned in such a way that one could turn a dial and see which statements validly follow from a given statement. Although extremely rudimentary, Lull’s basic idea underlies the modern digital computer...” “For the first time in history, someone had conceived of a machine that takes inputs of a certain sort and then, on the basis of rules of logic, computes an exact answer, which is then read off some other part of the device...” “The first designs in history for machines that compute were designs for mechanical devices that would operate according to the exact laws not of mathematics but of logic” (Herrick 2013: 121-2).
    [Show full text]
  • A New Light on the Nameless Corner of the Square of Oppositions
    New Light on the Square of Oppositions and its Nameless Corner Jean-Yves Béziau Institute of Logic and Semiological Research Center University of Neuchâtel, Espace Louis Agassiz 1 CH - 2000 Neuchâtel, Switzerland [email protected] Abstract It has been pointed out that there is no primitive name in natural and formal languages for one corner of the famous square of oppositions. We have all, some and no, but no primitive name for not all. It is true also in the modal version of the square, we have necessary, possible and impossible, but no primitive name for not necessary. I shed here a new light on this mysterious non-lexicalisation of the south- east corner of the square of oppositions, the so-called O-corner, by establishing some connections between negations and modalities. The E-corner, impossible, is a paracomplete negation (intuitionistic negation if the underlying modal logic is S4) and the O-corner, not necessary, is a paraconsistent negation. I argue that the three notions of opposition of the square of oppositions (contradiction, contrariety, subcontrariety) correspond to three notions of negation (classical, paracomplete, paraconsistent). We get a better understanding of these relations of opposition in the perspective of Blanché’s hexagon and furthermore in the perspective of a three dimensional object, a stellar dodecahedron of oppositions that I present at the end of the paper. Contents 1.The non lexicalization of the O-corner of the Square of Oppositions 2.Three oppositions and three negations 3.Some controversies about the theory of oppositions 4.The O corner within the Octagon and the Stellar Dodecahedron of Oppositions 5.Conclusions 6.Bibliography 1 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Traditional Square of Opposition and Generalized Quantifiers
    The traditional square of opposition and generalized quantifiers∗ Dag Westerst˚ahl University of Gothenburg Abstract The traditional square of opposition dates back to Aristotle’s logic and has been intensely discussed ever since, both in medieval and mod- ern times. It presents certain logical relations, or oppositions, that hold between the four quantifiers all, no, not all, and some. Aristotle and tradi- tional logicians, as well as most linguists today, took all to have existential import, so that “All As are B” entails that there are As, whereas modern logic drops this assumption. Replacing Aristotle’s account of all with the modern one (and similarly for not all) results in the modern version of the square, and there has been much recent debate about which of these two squares is the ‘right’ one. My main point in the present paper is that this question is not, or should not primarily be, about existential import, but rather about pat- terns of negation. I argue that the modern square, but not the traditional one, presents a general pattern of negation one finds in natural language. To see this clearly, one needs to apply the square not just to the four Aristotelian quantifiers, but to other generalized quantifiers of that type. Any such quantifier spans a modern square, which exhibits that pattern of negation but, very often, not the oppositions found in the traditional square. I provide some technical results and tools, and illustrate with sev- eral examples of squares based on quantifiers interpreting various English determiners. The final example introduces a second pattern of negation, which occurs with certain complex quantifiers, and which also is repre- sentable in a square.
    [Show full text]
  • Analytic Continuation of Ζ(S) Violates the Law of Non-Contradiction (LNC)
    Analytic Continuation of ζ(s) Violates the Law of Non-Contradiction (LNC) Ayal Sharon ∗y July 30, 2019 Abstract The Dirichlet series of ζ(s) was long ago proven to be divergent throughout half-plane Re(s) ≤ 1. If also Riemann’s proposition is true, that there exists an "expression" of ζ(s) that is convergent at all s (except at s = 1), then ζ(s) is both divergent and convergent throughout half-plane Re(s) ≤ 1 (except at s = 1). This result violates all three of Aristotle’s "Laws of Thought": the Law of Identity (LOI), the Law of the Excluded Middle (LEM), and the Law of Non- Contradition (LNC). In classical and intuitionistic logics, the violation of LNC also triggers the "Principle of Explosion" / Ex Contradictione Quodlibet (ECQ). In addition, the Hankel contour used in Riemann’s analytic continuation of ζ(s) violates Cauchy’s integral theorem, providing another proof of the invalidity of Riemann’s ζ(s). Riemann’s ζ(s) is one of the L-functions, which are all in- valid due to analytic continuation. This result renders unsound all theorems (e.g. Modularity, Fermat’s last) and conjectures (e.g. BSD, Tate, Hodge, Yang-Mills) that assume that an L-function (e.g. Riemann’s ζ(s)) is valid. We also show that the Riemann Hypothesis (RH) is not "non-trivially true" in classical logic, intuitionistic logic, or three-valued logics (3VLs) that assign a third truth-value to paradoxes (Bochvar’s 3VL, Priest’s LP ). ∗Patent Examiner, U.S. Patent and Trademark Office (USPTO).
    [Show full text]
  • The Balance Sheet and the Assets-Claims on Assets Relationship in the Axiomatic Method
    WSEAS TRANSACTIONS on MATHEMATICS Fernando Juárez The Balance Sheet and the Assets-Claims on Assets Relationship in the Axiomatic Method FERNANDO JUÁREZ Escuela de Administración Universidad del Rosario Autopista Norte, No. 200 COLOMBIA [email protected] Abstract: - The purpose of this study is to analyze the set structure of the balance sheet and assets-claims on assets relationship, considering the dual concept of monetary units, the axiomatic theory and accounting- specific axioms. The structure of the balance sheet and assets-claims on assets relationship are examined using a rationalistic, analytical and deductive method ; this method uses the axiomatic set theory and predicate logic to define a set of axioms and the logical rationale to apply them to any deductive proof. The method includes accounting primitives and axioms to use in combination with those of the axiomatic theory. A direct proof is applied to test the balance sheet fit to a hereditary set structure according to the axiomatic theory, and proof by contraposition is employed to examine the assets-claims on assets equality by comparing their elements. Results show that balance sheet has a set structure that can be defined and analyzed with the axiomatic method and fits a hereditary set structure. Also, by comparing the elements of assets and claims on assets and considering their financial classification, it is shown that these sets do not contain the same elements and, consequently, they are not equal under the postulates of the axiomatic method. Key-Words: Dual concept, accounting transactions, axiomatic method, assets, claims on assets, balance sheet. 1 Introduction difficulties in understanding the applications of this This paper addresses the issue of identifying a set method.
    [Show full text]
  • On Two Squares of Opposition: the Leśniewski's Style Formalization Of
    Acta Anal (2013) 28:71–93 DOI 10.1007/s12136-012-0162-4 On Two Squares of Opposition: the Leśniewski’s Style Formalization of Synthetic Propositions Andrew Schumann Received: 31 October 2011 /Accepted: 3 May 2012 /Published online: 15 July 2012 # The Author(s) 2012. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract In the paper we build up the ontology of Leśniewski’s type for formalizing synthetic propositions. We claim that for these propositions an unconventional square of opposition holds, where a, i are contrary, a, o (resp. e, i) are contradictory, e, o are subcontrary, a, e (resp. i, o) are said to stand in the subalternation. Further, we construct a non-Archimedean extension of Boolean algebra and show that in this algebra just two squares of opposition are formalized: conventional and the square that we invented. As a result, we can claim that there are only two basic squares of opposition. All basic constructions of the paper (the new square of opposition, the formalization of synthetic propositions within ontology of Leśniewski’s type, the non-Archimedean explanation of square of opposition) are introduced for the first time. Keywords Synthetic propositions . Non-Archimedean extension of Boolean algebra . Synthetic square of opposition . Synthetic ontology 1 Introduction The square of opposition is one of the main concepts of traditional as well as classical logic. For instance, it fixes the following fundamental relations in classical logic: 1) The duality relation between conjunction and disjunction ðÞðÞ)p ^ q ðÞp _ q , the law of non-contradiction ðÞp ^:p 0 , the law of tertium non datur ðÞp _:p 1 : A.
    [Show full text]