Richard Rorty and Political Liberalism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Richard Rorty and Political Liberalism ‘That’s the way we happen to do things around here’: Richard Rorty and Political Liberalism. Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Alan Michael James Bacon Government Department London School of Economics and Political Science University of London UMI Number: U185634 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Disscrrlation Publishing UMI U185634 Published by ProQuest LLC 2014. Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 O f POllTICAL L and cui ‘1^V(cs2> /i4^S£S F 8212 1016 700 Abstract This thesis advances a defence of Richard Rorty’s political liberalism. It is widely held that what Rorty calls anti-foundationalism either consciously proposes, or logically entails, the denial both of ethical commitment and the possibility of moral justification. Others argue that Rorty reduces commitment to a parochial concern, and that justification is relative to the standards of a narrowly conceived community. Commitment and justification, it is said, reduce to pointing out whatever it is that constitutes ‘the way we happen to do things around here’. In turn, anti-foundationalism is said to render obsolete any normative project in political theory. The thesis rejects these claims, arguing that Rorty does not reduce commitment and justification in this way. Anti-foundationalism is shown not to reduce reason-giving to ‘what we happen to think around here’, and it is also cleansed of claims that it is relativistic, irrational and nihilistic. Justification as the response for reasonable requests for explanation of our beliefs and practices remains important for Rorty, centrally in his account of justification through ‘wide reflective equilibrium’. The thesis shows how Rorty’s view of liberal ironism is the completion, not the negation, of liberalism. It demonstrates that he is able both to justify and defend liberal principles and institutions, and to do so in a way that undercuts many of the criticisms of liberalism that have been levelled by communitarian critics and others. It examines his view of liberal political thought not as providing a philosophical justification of liberalism, but as offering an articulation of it. It closes by considering the scope of liberal claims, suggesting that Rorty is, in the only meaningful sense of the term, a liberal universaHst. Acknowledgements I would like to thank my supervisors, Dr Paul Kelly and Professor Rodney Barker. Together they have carefully read successive drafts of this thesis, and have been unfailingly helpful, encouraging, and supportive. I have benefited considerably from the Government Department’s Political Theory Workshop, and would like to thank all who participated. Parts of the thesis have been presented at seminars and conferences, and my thanks go to the participants at the Third Essex Political Thought Conference in May 2002, the University of Sussex Social and Political Thought conference in September 2002, and the London Political Theory Group at the LSE. Over the course of writing the thesis, I have had the pleasure of discussing my ideas with many friends and colleagues. I would like to thank Clare Chambers, Chun-Hung Chen, Po-Chung Chow, Philip Cook, Oliver Curry, Paul Dawson, Cécile Fabre, Chico Gaetani, David Graham, James Gregory, Damian Krushner, Martin Lodge, Cillian McBride, Martin Mclvor, Tord Moi, Edmund Neill, David L. Paletz, Phil Parvin, Johannes PoUak, Ramida Vijitphan, Mei-Chuan Wei, and Pete Woodcock. Finally, and most importantly, my thanks go to my parents Linda and Alan, and my brother David, for their unflagging support, despite their having only the haziest idea of what I’ve been doing for the last five years. Contents Abstract Acknowledgements Chapter One: Introduction , 1. The issues outlined 1.1 Foundationalism and commitment 1.2 Anti-foundationalism and political theory 2. The aim o f the thesis 3. The approach adopted in the thesis 3.1 Argument and re-description 4. Organisation o f the thesis Chapter Two: Anti-authoritarianism and political liberalism 5. Philosophical narrative of maturation 5.1 ‘The philosophical urge’ 5.2 Answerability to the world 5.3 Understanding under a description 6. The political narrative of maturity 6.1 Postmodernism and the Enlightenment 6.2 The relationship of philosophy and democracy 6.3 Liberalism and the ‘Enlightenment Project’ 6.4 Political hberalism as the avoidance of cruelty Chapter Three: Contingency and universal validity 7. The inescapabibty of ethnocentrism 7.1 Ethnocentrism, acceptance, and validity 7.2 The order of reasons 7.3 Validity and the contingency of language 7.4 Truth and truthfulness 8. Ethnocentrism, irrationality, and relativism 8.1 Philosophical and political freedom 8.2 Irrationality and moral relativism 8.3 Ethnocentrism and moral arbitrariness Chapter Four: Ironism, liberalism, and conviction 9. Ironism and the possibility of moral commitment 9.1 Anti-foundationalism and ironism 9.2 The impact of ironism on conviction 9.3 Two suggestions in support of ironic conviction 9.4 The nature of ironic doubt 10. Liberalism and ironism 10.1 The liberal ironist? 10.2 Re-description and the avoidance of cruelty 10.3 Ironism and scepticism Chapter Five: Context and the justification of liberalism 11. Pragmatism and justification 11.1 Rorty’s ‘abandonment’ of justification 11.2 The need for justification 11.3 Justification as anthropology? 12. Justifying liberalism 12.1 The impossibility of a non-question-begging justification 12.2 Reasons for supporting liberal institutions 12.3 Challenges to political liberalism 12.4 Modus vivendi as the successor to political liberalism Chapter Six: Interpretation and political theory 13. Liberalism, interpretation and creativity 13.1 Creation and interpretation 13.2 Contested interpretations: liberalism verses mulficulturahsm 13.3 The necessity of argument 14. Rorty and radicalism 14.1 The relationship between philosophy and politics 14.2 The separation of philosophy and politics 15. Political philosophy verses internal social criticism? 15.1 Michael Walzer’s account of ‘internal social criticism’ 15.2 On Rawls Chapter Seven: Liberal ethnocentrism and the boundaries of community 16. Community as foundation? 16.1 Objectivity as solidarity 16.2 What can we say to ‘them’? 16.3 Incommensurability and incomparabihty 16.4 Two attempts to overcome ethnocentric parochialism 16.4.1.Matthew Festenstein: general versus substantive ethnocentrism 16.4.2 Hilary Putnam on ‘warranted assertabüity’ IV.Extending the boundaries 17.1 Justification through wide reflective equilibrium 17.2 ‘Ideal rational acceptability’ as an epistemological and as a pohtical notion 17.3 Degrees of parochialism Chapter Eight: Liberal universalism 18. The ‘universal validity’ o f Hberahsm 18.1 Liberalism and reason 18.2 Liberalism and human nature 19. ‘Universal validity’ verses ‘universal reach’ 19.1 The possibility of extending the scope of Hberahsm 19.2 The legitimacy of extending the scope of Hberahsm 20. Achieving universahty 20.1 A Hberal metanarrative? 20.2 Universahty through free discussion Chapter Nine: Conclusion Chapter One Introduction In this thesis I advance a defence of Richard Rorty’s political liberalism, which he characterises as liberalism shorn of all forms of what he calls ‘authoritarianism’ — both religious and secular — that claim to stand over and above freely arrived at agreement between human beings. Rorty’s political liberalism is a form of what he calls ‘anti-foundationalism’. Anti- foundationalism rejects the idea that there are unquestionable principles that exist independently of, and provide grounds for, our everyday practices. It is widely held that in advancing anti-foundationalism, Rorty either consciously proposes, or that his account logically entails, the negation of ethical commitment and the practice of moral justification. Others argue that Rorty reduces commitment to a parochial concern, and justification to correspondence to the standards of a narrowly conceived community. Anti-foundationalism is held to render obsolete any normative project in political theory; commitment and justification, it is said, are a matter of ‘the way we happen to do things around here’ or ‘merely what we happen to think around here’.’ ^ See for example Paul Kelly, ‘Political theory in retreat? Contemporary political theory and the historical order’, in Noël O ’Sullivan (ed.) Political Theory in Transition (London: Routledge, 2000), pp. 225 - 241 at 233. The thesis rejects these criticisms, arguing that the misunderstandings captured in them disguise Rorty’s actual position, which does not reduce commitment and justification in the way such comments imply. The two main claims of the thesis are, first, that Rorty’s anti- foundationalism does not collapse into parochialism, and secondly, that political liberalism can be justified and defended, indeed better defended, on Rorty’s account, since it undercuts many of the criticisms of liberalism that have been levelled by communitarian critics and others. 1. The issues outlined 1.1 Foundationalism and commitment Rorty
Recommended publications
  • Geuss-On-Rorty.Pdf
    Richard Rorty at Princeton: Personal Recollections RAYMOND GEUSS When i arrived in Princeton during the 1970s my addiction to tea was already long-standing and very well entrenched, but I was so concerned about the quality of the water in town that I used to buy large containers of allegedly “pure” water at Davidson’s—the local supermarket, which seems now to have gone out of business. I didn’t, of course, have a car, and given the amount of tea I consumed, the trans- port of adequate supplies of water was a highly labor-inten- sive and inconvenient matter. Dick and Mary Rorty must have noticed me lugging canisters of water home, because, with characteristic generosity, they developed the habit of call- ing around at my rooms in 120 Prospect, often on Sunday mornings, offering to take me by car to fill my water bottles at a hugely primitive and highly suspicious-looking outdoor water tap on the side of a pumphouse which was operated by the Elizabethtown Water Company on a piece of waste land near the Institute Woods. This pumphouse with its copiously dripping tap was like something out of Tarkhovski’s film about Russia after a nuclear accident, Stalker, and the sur- rounding area was a place so sinister one half expected to be attacked by packs of dogs in the final stages of radiation sick- ness or by troops of feral children who had been left by their parents to fend for themselves while the parents went off to the library to finish their dissertations.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: the Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin
    Cornell Law Review Volume 75 Article 2 Issue 4 May 1990 Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Robert Justin Lipkin, Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory , 75 Cornell L. Rev. 810 (1990) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol75/iss4/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BEYOND SKEPTICISM, FOUNDATIONALISM AND THE NEW FUZZINESS: THE ROLE OF WIDE REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM IN LEGAL THEORY Robert Justin Liphint TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION .............................................. 812 I. FOUNDATIONALISM AND SKEPTICISM ..................... 816 A. The Problem of Skepticism ........................ 816 B. Skepticism and Nihilism ........................... 819 1. Theoretical and PracticalSkepticism ................ 820 2. Subjectivism and Relativism ....................... 821 3. Epistemic and Conceptual Skepticism ................ 821 4. Radical Skepticism ............................... 822 C. Modified Skepticism ............................... 824 II. NEW FOUNDATIONALISM
    [Show full text]
  • Merily Salura Moral Epistemology and Totalitarianism: Reflections on Arendt, Bauman, Bernstein, and Rorty Bachelor’S Thesis
    TALLINN UNIVERSITY ESTONIAN INSTITUTE OF HUMANITIES Cultural Theory Merily Salura Moral epistemology and totalitarianism: reflections on Arendt, Bauman, Bernstein, and Rorty Bachelor’s thesis Supervisor: Siobhan Kattago Tallinn 2015 Table of Contents 1 RESÜMEE ..................................................................................................................... 4 2 INTRODUCTION .......................................................................................................... 5 3 METHOD ..................................................................................................................... 12 3.1 Reflection on sources ......................................................................................... 13 4 TOTALITARIANISM ................................................................................................. 15 5 THE CONCEPT OF MORALITY ............................................................................... 19 6 THE BANALITY OF EVIL ........................................................................................ 25 6.1 The banality of evil in the light of Stanley Milgram‘s social experiments ........ 29 7 ETHICAL OBJECTIVISM .......................................................................................... 39 7.1 Ethical objectivism in the context of totalitarianism .......................................... 41 7.1.1 The pretension for a firm foundation and universality ....................................... 41 7.1.2 Ethical objectivism and standards of morality
    [Show full text]
  • Post-Truth Politics and Richard Rorty's Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism
    Ash Center Occasional Papers Tony Saich, Series Editor Something Has Cracked: Post-Truth Politics and Richard Rorty’s Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism Joshua Forstenzer University of Sheffield (UK) July 2018 Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation Harvard Kennedy School Ash Center Occasional Papers Series Series Editor Tony Saich Deputy Editor Jessica Engelman The Roy and Lila Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation advances excellence and innovation in governance and public policy through research, education, and public discussion. By training the very best leaders, developing powerful new ideas, and disseminating innovative solutions and institutional reforms, the Center’s goal is to meet the profound challenges facing the world’s citizens. The Ford Foundation is a founding donor of the Center. Additional information about the Ash Center is available at ash.harvard.edu. This research paper is one in a series funded by the Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation at Harvard University’s John F. Kennedy School of Government. The views expressed in the Ash Center Occasional Papers Series are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect those of the John F. Kennedy School of Government or of Harvard University. The papers in this series are intended to elicit feedback and to encourage debate on important public policy challenges. This paper is copyrighted by the author(s). It cannot be reproduced or reused without permission. Ash Center Occasional Papers Tony Saich, Series Editor Something Has Cracked: Post-Truth Politics and Richard Rorty’s Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism Joshua Forstenzer University of Sheffield (UK) July 2018 Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation Harvard Kennedy School Letter from the Editor The Roy and Lila Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation advances excellence and innovation in governance and public policy through research, education, and public discussion.
    [Show full text]
  • Overcoming the Tradition: Heidegger and Dewey Author(S): Richard Rorty Source: the Review of Metaphysics , Dec., 1976, Vol
    Overcoming the Tradition: Heidegger and Dewey Author(s): Richard Rorty Source: The Review of Metaphysics , Dec., 1976, Vol. 30, No. 2 (Dec., 1976), pp. 280-305 Published by: Philosophy Education Society Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.com/stable/20126921 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Philosophy Education Society Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Metaphysics This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Sat, 27 Jun 2020 15:25:17 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms OVERCOMING THE TRADITION: HEIDEGGER AND DEWEY RICHARD RORTY I X HILOSOPHERS who envy scientists think that philosophy should deal only with problems formulated in neutral terms?terms satis factory to all those who argue for competing solutions. Without common problems and without argument, it would seem, we have no professional discipline, nor even a method for disciplining our own thoughts. Without discipline, we presumably have mysticism, or poetry, or inspiration?at any rate, something which permits an escape from our intellectual responsibilities. Heidegger is frequently
    [Show full text]
  • György Pápay: Pragmatism and the Ordinary: the Rorty-Putnam Debate
    PRAGMATISM AND THE ORDINARY: The Rorty-Putnam Debate from a Different Angle 1 György Pápay E-mail: [email protected] In his essay „Philosophy and Ordinary Experience” Stanley Rosen claims that when philosophers become increasingly interested in the question of the Ordinary— ordinary language or ordinary experience—it always indicates a crisis of philosophy. Both the phenomenological and the analytical school of modern philosophy included important thinkers who supposed that philosophical activity as such had reached a theoretical dead end, and therefore urged a return to the Ordinary. This enterprise itself can be carried out in a more or less theoretical way. The more theoretical approach is represented by Husserl or Heidegger. The less or sometimes even antitheoretical way of returning to the Ordinary is exemplified by Oxonian philosophers such as Ryle and Austin, and the later Wittgenstein. As Rosen adds, „Perhaps it would be fair to classify pragmatist like James and Dewey in this camp.” 2 Although the latter suggestion is not indisputable, I think Rosen has a point. If we put the scientistic vein aside that is common in some works of Peirce, Dewey and Sidney Hook, classical pragmatism with its firm critique of metaphysical dualisms and its emphasis on the practical character of human concerns could be seen as a philosophical movement that takes side with everyday life rather than pure theory. However, my aim is not to consider whether this classification of James and Dewey proves to be useful. I would rather focus on two influental contemporary pragmatists, Richard Rorty and Hilary Putnam, and especially on their relation to the question of the Ordinary.
    [Show full text]
  • And Solidarity
    Contingency,rencYrlfooY, andsolidarity RICHARD RORTY U niaersityProfessor of Hamanities, Uniaersityof Virginia ry,,,*-_qCaUBRTDGE WP uNrvERsrrY PREss Published by the PressSyndicarc of dre University of Cambridge The Pitt Building Trumpington Street, Cambridge CB2 IRP 40 Vest 20th Suect, New York, NY 10011-4211,USA l0 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia @ Cambridgc University Press1989 First published 1989 Reprinted 1989 (thrice), 1990, l99l (cwice), 1992, 1993, 1994, r995 Printed in the United Sratesof America Library of Congess Catdoging-in-Publication Daa is available British Library Cataloging in Publication applied for ISBN0-521 -3538r -5 hardback ISBN0-52 I -1678l -6 paperback In memory of six liberals: my parentsand grandparents The agdlasrer lRabelais's word for those who do not laughJ, the non- thought of received ideas, and kitsch are one and the same, the three- headed enemy of the art born as the echo of God's laughter, the art that created the fascinating imaginative realm where no one owns the truth and everyone has the right to be understood. That imaginative realm of tolerance was born with modern Europe, it is the very image of Europe- of at least our dream of Europe, a dream many times betrayed but nonetheless strong enough to unite us all in the fraternity that stretches far beyond the little European continent. But we know that the wodd where the individual is respected (the imaginative world of the novel, and the real one of Europe) is fragile and perishable. if European culture seems under threat today, if the threat from within and without hangs over what is most precious about it - its respect for the individual, for his original thought, and for his right to an inviolable private life - then, I believe, that precious essenceof the European spirit is being held safe as in a treasure chest inside the history of the novel, the wisdom of the novel.
    [Show full text]
  • Taking Rorty's Irony Seriously
    Humanities 2013, 2, 292–312; doi:10.3390/h2020292 OPEN ACCESS humanities ISSN 2076-0787 www.mdpi.com/journal/humanities Article Taking Rorty’s Irony Seriously Andrew Inkpin School of Historical and Philosophical Studies, University of Melbourne, Victoria 3010, Australia; E-Mail: [email protected] Received: 4 May 2013; in revised form: 26 May 2013 / Accepted: 6 June 2013 / Published: 12 June 2013 Abstract: Richard Rorty’s Contingency, Irony and Solidarity (CIS) is an ambitious and provocative, but for many readers a deeply flawed work. This paper argues that many of its apparent flaws can be understood as integral to Rorty’s attempt to write a work of private, post-theoretical irony. The paper’s first section outlines the substantive theoretical claims about language, selfhood and community which Rorty proposes as an antiessentialist alternative to ‘metaphysics’. The second identifies three difficulties—residual dualism, conceptual problems with the public-private distinction, and the work’s self-referential consistency—which constitute serious, but obvious problems for those substantive claims. The third section argues that Rorty’s metaphilosophical discussion of ‘ironist theory’ suggests CIS should be read as a personal work of irony which eschews theoretical ambitions, showing how this is consistent with and provides a motive for accepting the presence of conspicuous difficulties. The final section considers how the work’s metaphilosophical views interact with its substantive theoretical claims. The work’s irony is interpreted as resulting from the tension between these, so as to coexist rather than conflict with Rorty’s enduring commitments to liberalism and pragmatism. Keywords: Rorty; irony; metaphilosophy; pragmatism; continental philosophy 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Richard Rorty
    Richard Rorty Reprinted from Philosophy and Social Hope (Penguin Books, 1999) If there is anything to the idea that the best in- tellectual position is one which is attacked with equal vigor from the political right and the political left, then I am in good shape. I am often cited by conservative culture warriors as one of the relativistic, irrationalist, deconstructing, sneering, smirking intellectuals whose writings are weakening the moral fibre of the young. Neal Kozody, writing in the monthly bulle- tin of the Committee for the Free World, an organization known for its vigilance against symp- toms of moral weakness, denounces my 'cynical and nihilistic view' and says 'it is not enough for him [Rorty] that American students should be merely mindless; he would have them posi- tively mobilized for mindlessness'. Richard Neuhaus, a theologian who doubts that atheists can be good American citizens, says that the 'ironist vocabulary' I advocate 'can neither pro- vide a public language for the citizens of a democracy, nor contend intellectually against the enemies of democracy, nor transmit the reasons for democracy to the next generation'. My criticisms of Allan Bloom's The Closing of the American Mind led Harvey Mansfield - recently appointed by President Bush to the National Council for the Humanities - to say that I have 'given up on America' and that I 'manage to diminish even Dewey'. (Mansfield recently de- scribed Dewey as a 'medium-sized malefactor'.) His colleague on the council, my fellow phi- losopher John Searle, thinks that standards can only be restored to American higher education if people abandon the views on truth, knowledge and objectivity that I do my best to inculcate.
    [Show full text]
  • Richard Rorty Papers MS.C.017
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/kt9p3038mq Online items available Guide to the Richard Rorty Papers MS.C.017 Dawn Schmitz Special Collections and Archives, University of California, Irvine Libraries 2016 The UCI Libraries P.O. Box 19557 University of California, Irvine Irvine 92623-9557 [email protected] URL: http://special.lib.uci.edu Guide to the Richard Rorty Papers MS.C.017 1 MS.C.017 Language of Material: English Contributing Institution: Special Collections and Archives, University of California, Irvine Libraries Title: Richard Rorty papers Creator: Rorty, Richard Identifier/Call Number: MS.C.017 Physical Description: 24.3 Linear Feet(61 boxes and 1 oversized folder) Date (inclusive): 1863-2003 Date (bulk): bulk Language of Material: The collection is primarily in English, with some materials in other languages, particularly German and French. Abstract: Richard Rorty (1931-2007) was a pragmatist philosopher, critical theorist, and public intellectual. This collection comprises manuscripts, teaching files, professional correspondence, research notes, biographical material, and ephemera. It also includes some family papers and correspondence, as well as writings dating to his youth. The collection includes digital files transferred from Rorty's computer disks and made available to researchers electronically. http://ucispace.lib.uci.edu/handle/10575/7 Access The collection is open for research, with the exception of some materials relating to students in Series 5, Teaching files. Restrictions on the earliest of these student records will be lifted beginning in 2033. Publication Rights Property rights reside with the University of California. Literary rights are retained by the creators of the records and their heirs.
    [Show full text]
  • Rorty Nineteenth Century Idealism and Twentieth Century Textualism.Pdf
    NINETEENTH-CENTURY IDEALISM AND TWENTIETH-CENTURY TEXTUALISM Author(s): Richard Rorty Source: The Monist , APRIL, 1981, Vol. 64, No. 2, Nineteenth-Century Thought Today (APRIL, 1981), pp. 155-174 Published by: Oxford University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.com/stable/27902689 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Oxford University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Monist This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Sat, 27 Jun 2020 15:22:14 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms NINETEENTH-CENTURY IDEALISM AND TWENTIETH-CENTURY TEXTUALISM I In the last century there were philosophers who argued that nothing ex ists but ideas. In our century there are people who write as if there were nothing but texts. These people, whom I shall call "textualists," include for example, the so-called Yale school of literary criticism centering around Harold Bloom, Geoffrey Hartmann, and Paul De Man, "post-structuralist" French thinkers like Jacques Derrida and Michel Foucault, historians like Hayden White, and social scientists like Paul Rabinow. Some of these people take their point of departure from Heidegger, but usually the influence of philosophers is relatively remote.
    [Show full text]
  • Consequences of Pragmatism University of Minnesota Press, 1982
    estratto dal volume: RICHARD RORTY Consequences of Pragmatism University of Minnesota Press, 1982 INTRODUCTION 1. Platonists, Positivists, and Pragmatists The essays in this book are attempts to draw consequences from a prag- matist theory about truth. This theory says that truth is not the sort of thing one should expect to have a philosophically interesting theory about. For pragmatists, “truth” is just the name of a property which all true statements share. It is what is common to “Bacon did not write Shakespeare,” “It rained yesterday,” “E equals mc²” “Love is better than hate,” “The Alle- gory of Painting was Vermeer’s best work,” “2 plus 2 is 4,” and “There are nondenumerable infinities.” Pragmatists doubt that there is much to be said about this common feature. They doubt this for the same reason they doubt that there is much to be said about the common feature shared by such morally praiseworthy actions as Susan leaving her husband, Ameri- ca joining the war against the Nazis, America pulling out of Vietnam, Socrates not escaping from jail, Roger picking up litter from the trail, and the suicide of the Jews at Masada. They see certain acts as good ones to perform, under the circumstances, but doubt that there is anything gen- eral and useful to say about what makes them all good. The assertion of a given sentence—or the adoption of a disposition to assert the sentence, the conscious acquisition of a belief—is a justifiable, praiseworthy act in certain circumstances. But, a fortiori, it is not likely that there is something general and useful to be said about what makes All such actions good-about the common feature of all the sentences which one should ac- quire a disposition to assert.
    [Show full text]