The Law of Nature in State and Fed- Eral Judicial Decisions

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Law of Nature in State and Fed- Eral Judicial Decisions THE LAW OF NATURE IN STATE AND FED- ERAL JUDICIAL DECISIONS The notion that there is a law higher and better and more in accord with justice than positive law we are told has paralleled the existence of the law itself.' An appeal to reason or to the sense of mankind as to what is just and right and the insistence upon what ought to be law as binding because of its intrinsic reasonableness, are declared to be among the strongest liberalizing forces in legal history.2 This appeal to reason which commonly goes under the designation-the law of nature or law of reason- has had an eventful history since the formulation of the notion by the Greeks and the Romans. Natural law, a law to which legislation may or may not con- form, is a conception which is constantly taking new form. It may be described as the recurrence in the evolution of justice of ideas of right in accordance with reason, ideas which are fre- quently regarded as superior to positive law. The concept is one which is often held to belong more properly to ethics, to philosophy or to politics; but current usage, particularly in 3 continental European countries, terms it law. 1 Berolzheimer, The World's Legal Philosophies (Trans. by Rachel Szold Jastrow), Int., p. XII. "It is an ancient, never-ending dream of mankind that there is a peculiar, rigid and unchangeable law. This law is thought to be a law of reason. What is agreeable to the reason is supposed on. that account to be law, and necessary for all times and places." Windscheid, Rectoral Address, p. 7, quoted in Gareis, Introduc- tion to the Science of Law (Trans. by A. Kocourek), p. I9. See also Del Vecchio, Formal Bases of Law (Trans. by John Lisle), pp. 324-335 on "Natural Law as the Goal of Historical Development." Pound, Scope and Purpose of Sociological Jurisprudence, 24 Harvard Law Review, 6o8. 'Ahrens, Cours de droit naturel ou de philosophe du droit, gives a brief survey of the growth of the natural law concept. Natural law or the philosophy of law is defined as "the science which presents the first principles of right discovered by reason and founded in the nature of man." 8th ed., p. 1. Consult also Bergbohm, Jurisprudenz und Rechts- philosophie, Vol. I, Part I, "Das Naturrecht der Gegenwart"; Jellinek, Allegemeine Staatslehre, pp. 314-323; Stammler, Wirthschaft und Recht, pp. I69-I88 (the latter denies the existence of natural law); Charmont, La renaissance du droit naturel. YALE LAW JOURNAL That there is "besides the reason which guides us in fixing the letter of the law, a larger reason which informs the spirit of the law" and which is in last resort the ultimate justification for the law itself is a pervasive principle the significance of which has not at times been fully appreciated. Natural law, defined by Grotius, "right reason as it guides men in the ultimate determina- tion of right and wrong," is today as it has been in the past one of the important concepts in the realms of law, government and ethics. In the judicial decisions of the United States are to be found some notable applications of this concept, a survey of which is the purpose of this article. To understand and to better appreciate the modem use of the doctrine it is necessary to give a short account of the significant steps in the development of this far-reaching legal principle. The Law of Nature in Ancient and Mediaeval Times. The historical setting of the law of nature cannot be presented within the compass of a brief article. Moreover, the subject has been adequately treated in recent legal literature- and for the present purpose a brief summary of some significant historical facts will suffice. The idea of a law of nature-permanent and universal on which law is based-was familiar to the Greeks, particularly Aristotle and Demosthenes. The Greek concept developed under Stoic influence into the guiding principle of reason which was held to be immanent in the universe and of which natural law was an expression. Among the philosophers Cicero was the great advocate of the Stoic philosophy of natural law. But of greater importance is the .fact that the idea gained acceptance and received the approval of the jurists Paul and Gaius, and through them it was embodied among the principles of the great Corpus Juris.6 This law was regarded as the substance of the precepts 4Salmond, The Law of Nature, ii Law Q. Rev. 121; Pollock, Expan- sion of the Common Law, and Journal of the Society of Comparative Legislation, Vol. II, i9oo; Bryce, Studies in History and Jurisprudence, Vol. II, Essay, The Law of Nature. See also references on preceding page. Salmond, op. cit., pp. 123, ff. Cf. Rhet. I, Io and 13, wherein Aristotle refers to law that is universal "which is conformable merely to dictates of nature"; cf. Ahrens, Philosophie du droit dans l'antiquit6, p. 296. 'Wardship is characterized by Gaius as an institution based on natural reason and a similar basis for leases is suggested by Paul. Cf. Gains I, i89. Inst. i, 2o, 6. Phrases referring to the law of nature and of reason in Roman Law are: THE LAW OF NATURE approved by "the common sense of all nations as embodying what '7 was practically useful and convenient." In the Middle Ages the law of nature and of reason which held such an important place in the Stoic philosophy of the later Roman Empire was gradually absorbed by the church and was eventually given definite and specific application in the canon law courts. To secure additional sanction from Aristotle, Cicero and Justinian for the civil jurisdiction of the clergy, it became advan- tageous to identify the law of nature with the law of God and to apply the principle in the application of law to concrete cases. Natural law came to be regarded as law in its fullest sense; it possessed the same imperative elements as legislative enactments.' The law of nature came to be differentiated from ordinary stat- utes. All sovereigns were subject to this natural law which set limitations "to the exercise of every kind of human authority and the enactment of all positive law."9 In the hands of Grotius and his successors the law of nature took the form of a rather well-defined code relative to such mat- ters as reverence for God, family virtues, love of country, and the rights of liberty and property. Natural law in its pure form was to Grotius equivalent to the dictates of right reason, and as such, absolutely immutable, subject to change not even by God ius commune omnium hominum-Gaius Inst. I, i; Dif. i. 1, 9. ius quod naturalis ratio constituit-Gaius Inst. i, i; also the famous phrase-aequum et bonum, aequitas; cited among others in the essay by Bryce, op. cit., p. 578. TBryce, Essay on The Law of Nature, p. 578; Pollock, The History of the Law of Nature, Journal of the Society of Comparative Legislation, Vol. II, 19oo; Salmond, pp. 128, ff. Gareis, Introduction to the Science of Law, p. 18. Cf. my volume, The American Doctrine of Judicial Supremacy, pp. i8, ff. and 289. A portion of the historical part of this article follows with certain modifications the account given in the above volume. 8Dunning, Political Theories, Ancient and Mediaeval, p. 211; Bryce, P. 597; Pound, Common Law and Legislation, 21 Harvard Law Review, 39o; an able advocate of the "lex naturalis" was Thomas Aquinas, see Berolzheimer, op. cit., p. 98; "A civil statute that contravenes natural justice," affirms the mediaeval jurist Suarez, "is ipso facto void, for in the hierarchy of the laws the precepts of nature are higher both in source and in effect than those of any merely human power," Suarez, III, xii, 4; also Salmond, 131, ff. "Dunning, Political Theories, Ancient and Mediaeval, p. 281; Ahrens, Sec. 41, p. 308. YALE LAW JOURNAL himself.' 0 The law of nature by its very definition was a rule of life discoverable by human reason apart from any special revela- tion or the decision of any particular authority. Often it was 11 equivalent to "a pretty frank appeal to expediency." Law of Nature in English Law. At an early day in England the law merchant was declared to be "a part of the law of nature and nations" and as such universal, and the king's judges in the absence of other authority were accorded the privilege of a "resort to the law of nature which is the ground of all laws. 1 2 Following the mediaeval practice it was announced in 1563 that the law of nature rendered any custom or statute in conflict therewith void. In the seventeenth century the Court of King's Bench held that the law of nature was implied in "the law of the land" as used in Magna Charta. 3 With the advent of the dogma of a presocial state of nature and the possession by the individual of natural rights of superior sanctity, the conception of a law of nature acquired a new meaning. Locke, the apologist for revo- lution in England, declared the law of nature to be "a deter- mining body of rules for the conduct of men in their natural condition," embodying such fundamental matters as the right to life, liberty and property.'4 The law of nature was regarded as an outgrowth of a state of nature which Locke used as a postulate and which Rousseau rendered a popular concept of the eighteenth century political philosophy.'15 "Ibid., p.
Recommended publications
  • Constitutional Jurisprudence of History and Natural Law: Complementary Or Rival Modes of Discourse?
    California Western Law Review Volume 24 Number 2 Bicentennial Constitutional and Legal Article 6 History Symposium 1988 Constitutional Jurisprudence of History and Natural Law: Complementary or Rival Modes of Discourse? C.M.A. McCauliff Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.cwsl.edu/cwlr Recommended Citation McCauliff, C.M.A. (1988) "Constitutional Jurisprudence of History and Natural Law: Complementary or Rival Modes of Discourse?," California Western Law Review: Vol. 24 : No. 2 , Article 6. Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.cwsl.edu/cwlr/vol24/iss2/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by CWSL Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in California Western Law Review by an authorized editor of CWSL Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. McCauliff: Constitutional Jurisprudence of History and Natural Law: Compleme Constitutional Jurisprudence of History and Natural Law: Complementary or Rival Modes of Discourse? C.M.A. MCCAULIFF* The Bill of Rights provides broadly conceived guarantees which invite specific judicial interpretation to clarify the purpose, scope and meaning of particular constitutional safeguards. Two time- honored but apparently divergent approaches to the jurisprudence of constitutional interpretation have been employed in recent first amendment cases: first, history has received prominent attention from former Chief Justice Burger in open-trial, family and reli- gion cases; second, natural law has been invoked by Justice Bren- nan in the course of responding to the Chief Justice's historical interpretation. History, although indirectly stating constitutional values, provides the closest expression of the Chief Justice's own jurisprudence and political philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Idea of Public Law 1
    3 THE IDEA OF PUBLIC LAW 1 CHAPTER OVERVIEW Introduction The predominance of states Sovereignty and the origin of law’s authority The nature of law Empowerment and constraint The social contract Constitutionalism Constitutional change The scope of public law Public law and private law The rule of law The values underpinning public law Freedom Equality Community Conclusion Oxford University Press Sample Chapter 01_APP_APL3E_10899_TXT_SI.indd 3 3/8/18 9:22 am 4 PART I: Introducing Australian Public Law OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Introduction We are alone in the world, making our own way; and we are part of a community, with a collective understanding of the conditions for a good and meaningful life. Our lives are a complex combination of the individual and the collective. In the 4th century BCE, the Greek philosopher Aristotle (384– 22 BCE) described the organisation of humans by reference to a progression from the individual to the collective.1 e collective nature of our existence operates at a number of levels— at the level of the family or household, the neighbourhood, and the social or political organisation; at the level of the nation- state; and, increasingly, at the global level, both regionally and across all nation- states. At each of these levels there are rules for how we interact with each other and with those who hold power. e larger and more complex the organisational unit, the more elaborate and complicated the rules for functioning within it. For Aristotle, the level of the state was the highest form
    [Show full text]
  • Private Law and Public Law
    Private Law and Public Law F.J.M. Feldbrugge Emeritus Professor of East European Law University of Leiden, Faculty of Law We talk about private law and public law as if everybody knew what was meant when these words are being used about law. This probably holds true for lawyers and even law students, but not for the general population. Most people will have some sort of idea about labor law, or bankruptcy law, but the distinction between private law and public law, considered as most fundamental by most lawyers, means next to nothing to the man or woman in the street. Is the problem perhaps avoidable, do we actually need the public/ private law distinction? If we do not, the matter could be left to those inclined to such intellectual pastimes. Unfortunately, the distinction between public and private law entails practical consequences, at least in continental legal systems, so it can- not be referred to the convenient and already very large file of problems that do not need a solution. To start at the simplest and most practical level: our law happens to be divided into two boxes; some of it has been put into the box marked “public law”, and the rest into the box marked “private law”, and the contents of these two boxes are treated somewhat differently. For the law student and the humble practitioner this may be enough to know. But the more discerning lawyer would of course like to know why some law goes into one box and some into the other. Two thousand years of jurisprudence—because the distinction goes back at least as far as the Romans—have produced a vast body of literature containing answers to this question.
    [Show full text]
  • Retaining Judicial Authority: a Preliminary Inquiry on the Dominion of Judges
    William & Mary Bill of Rights Journal Volume 12 (2003-2004) Issue 1 Article 4 December 2003 Retaining Judicial Authority: A Preliminary Inquiry on the Dominion of Judges Larry Catá Backer Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj Part of the Courts Commons, and the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Repository Citation Larry Catá Backer, Retaining Judicial Authority: A Preliminary Inquiry on the Dominion of Judges, 12 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 117 (2003), https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj/vol12/iss1/4 Copyright c 2003 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj RETAINING JUDICIAL AUTHORITY: A PRELIMINARY INQUIRY ON THE DOMINION OF JUDGES Larry Catd Backer* Why do the people and institutionsof democratic states, and in particularthose of the United States, obey judges ? This article examines the foundationsofjudicial authority in the United States. This authority is grounded on principles of dominance derivedfrom the organization of institutionalreligion. The judge in Western states asserts authority on the same basis as the priest - but not the priest as conventionallyunderstood. Rather, the authorityof the judge in modern Western democratic states is better understood when viewed through the analytical lens of priestlyfunction developed in the philosophy of FriedrichNietzsche. Focusing on the United States Supreme Court and the European Court of Justice, this paper examines the manner in which high-courtjudges have successfully internalizedthe characteristicsof Nietzsche's Paul and his priestly caste within the "religion" of Western constitutionalism. Paul wanted the end, consequently he also wanted the means.
    [Show full text]
  • Can Legislatures Constrain Judicial Interpretation of Statutes? Anthony D'amato Northwestern University School of Law, [email protected]
    Northwestern University School of Law Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons Faculty Working Papers 2010 Can Legislatures Constrain Judicial Interpretation of Statutes? Anthony D'Amato Northwestern University School of Law, [email protected] Repository Citation D'Amato, Anthony, "Can Legislatures Constrain Judicial Interpretation of Statutes?" (2010). Faculty Working Papers. Paper 71. http://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/facultyworkingpapers/71 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Working Papers by an authorized administrator of Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. Can Legislatures Constrain Judicial Interpretation of Statutes? by Anthony D’Amato*, 75 Va. L. Rev. 561-603 (1989) Abstract: An aspect of the battle over deconstruction is whether resort to legislative intent might help to determine the content of a statutory text that otherwise, in splendid isolation, could be deconstructed by simply positing different interpretive contexts. I examine the same issue by recounting my own quest for determinate meaning in statutes—a sort of personal legislative history. I do not claim for jurisprudence the role of ensuring faithful reception of the legislature's message, for that is impossible. At best, jurisprudential theory only reduces the degrees of interpretive freedom, and then only probably, not necessarily. The more significant thesis of this article is that all theories of statutory interpreta- tion can only do that much and no more. Tags: legislative intent, statutory interpretation, jurisprudence, deconstruction, doctrinalists [pg561]** An aspect of the current battle over deconstruction [FN1] is whether resort to legislative intent might help to determine the content of a statutory text that otherwise, in splendid isolation, could be deconstructed by simply positing different interpretive contexts.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Law As the Law of the Res Publica
    Maurer School of Law: Indiana University Digital Repository @ Maurer Law Articles by Maurer Faculty Faculty Scholarship 2008 Public Law as the Law of the Res Publica Elisabeth Zoller Follow this and additional works at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/facpub Part of the Comparative and Foreign Law Commons, European Law Commons, and the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Zoller, Elisabeth, "Public Law as the Law of the Res Publica" (2008). Articles by Maurer Faculty. 146. https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/facpub/146 This Conference Proceeding is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by Maurer Faculty by an authorized administrator of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. PUBLIC LAW AS THE LAW OF THE RES PUBLICA Elisabeth Zoller* A LECTURE GIVEN AS PART OF SUFFOLK TRANSNATIONAL LAW REVIEW'S 2008 DISTINGUISHED SPEAKER COLLOQUIUM SERIES In 1989, on the occasion of the Bicentennial of the French Revolution, I gave a talk at Suffolk University Law School on The Distinction Between Man and the Citizen in the Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen of 1789.1 In retrospect, I am afraid that this may not have been one of my best talks. The truth of the matter is that I failed to give the rationale for this crucial distinction and its meaning in the Declaration of 1789. I said that the distinction was almost invisible in this country and much less important than in the French legal system, but I did not explain why.
    [Show full text]
  • THE LAWYER's ROLE in PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION FRITZ MORSTEIN Marxt
    THE LAWYER'S ROLE IN PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION FRITZ MORSTEIN MARXt I THE role played by the lawyer in public administration is not ade- quately described in a simple statement. His special skill is utilized in a great variety of ways. Moreover, lawyers occupy quite different posi- tions on various levels of the administrative hierarchy. And their actual influence goes in many instances beyond the range of their specific duties. Neither statutory prohibitions nor stipulations of political etiquette bar the lawyer from the highest posts of administrative leadership. It may even be said that legislative assemblies-with their heavy representation of legal talent-tend to show a certain fondness for government executives experienced in the practice of law.' More than a few lawyers have acquitted themselves creditably at the helm of gov- ernment agencies. This, however, does not suggest the possibility of a correlation between success or acclaim in the legal profession and those qualifications which should be expected of government executives. 2 On the contrary, prevailing opinion is accurately summarized in the ob- servation that "the lawyer is a good administrator by coincidence only; he is not specially trained for administration, and, indeed, the narrow and specialized legal education he has received may be considered to be particularly unsuited for the types of problems to be faced." I What is more relevant for our purposes, as administrator of an operating agency the lawyer is called upon to demonstrate his talent for executive direction and management rather than his legal knowledge and experi- ence. Much the same is true of those lawyers whose elevated positions t Associate Professor of Political Science, Queens College (on leave); Staff Assistant, Office of the Director, Bureau of the Budget, Executive Office of the President.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Law and Legal Reasoning Law Is
    CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION TO LAW AND LEGAL REASONING LAW IS "MAN MADE" IT CHANGES OVER TIME TO ACCOMMODATE SOCIETY'S NEEDS LAW IS MADE BY LEGISLATURE LAW IS INTERPRETED BY COURTS TO DETERMINE 1)WHETHER IT IS "CONSTITUTIONAL" 2)WHO IS RIGHT OR WRONG THERE IS A PROCESS WHICH MUST BE FOLLOWED (CALLED "PROCEDURAL LAW") I. Thomas Jefferson: "The study of the law qualifies a man to be useful to himself, to his neighbors, and to the public." II. Ask Several Students to give their definition of "Law." A. Even after years and thousands of dollars, "LAW" still is not easy to define B. What does law Consist of ? Law consists of enforceable rule governing relationships among individuals and between individuals and their society. 1. Students Need to Understand. a. The law is a set of general ideas b. When these general ideas are applied, a judge cannot fit a case to suit a rule; he must fit (or find) a rule to suit the unique case at hand. c. The judge must also supply legitimate reasons for his decisions. C. So, How was the Law Created. The law considered in this text are "man made" law. This law can (and will) change over time in response to the changes and needs of society. D. Example. Grandma, who is 87 years old, walks into a pawn shop. She wants to sell her ring that has been in the family for 200 years. Grandma asks the dealer, "how much will you give me for this ring." The dealer, in good faith, tells Grandma he doesn't know what kind of metal is in the ring, but he will give her $150.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Do Nations Obey International Law?
    Review Essay Why Do Nations Obey International Law? The New Sovereignty: Compliance with InternationalRegulatory Agreements. By Abram Chayes" and Antonia Handler Chayes.*" Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1995. Pp. xii, 404. $49.95. Fairness in International Law and Institutions. By Thomas M. Franck.- Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995. Pp. 500. $55.00. Harold Hongju Koh Why do nations obey international law? This remains among the most perplexing questions in international relations. Nearly three decades ago, Louis Henkin asserted that "almost all nations observe almost all principles of international law and almost all of their obligations almost all of the time."' Although empirical work since then seems largely to have confirmed this hedged but optimistic description,2 scholars Felix Frankfurter Professor of Law, Emeritus, Harvard Law School ** President, Consensus Building Institute. Murray and Ida Becker Professor of Law; Director. Center for International Studtcs. New York University School of Law. t Gerard C. and Bernice Latrobe Smith Professor of International Law; Director. Orville H, Schell, Jr., Center for International Human Rights, Yale University. Thts Essay sketches arguments to be fleshed out in a forthcoming book, tentatively entitled WHY NATIONS OBEY: A THEORY OF COMPLIANCE WITH INTERNATIONAL LAW. Parts of this Review Essay derive from the 1997 \Vaynflete Lectures. Magdalen College, Oxford University, and a brief book review of the Chayeses volume in 91 Am. J. INT'L L. (forthcoming 1997). 1 am grateful to Glenn Edwards, Jessica Schafer. and Douglas Wolfe for splendid research assistance, and to Bruce Ackerman, Peter Balsam, Geoffrey Brennan. Paul David, Noah Feldman. Roger Hood, Andrew Hurrell, Mark Janis, Paul Kahn, Benedict Kingsbury, Tony Kronran.
    [Show full text]
  • The Reception of Hobbes's Leviathan
    This is a repository copy of The reception of Hobbes's Leviathan. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/71534/ Version: Published Version Book Section: Parkin, Jon (2007) The reception of Hobbes's Leviathan. In: Springborg, Patricia, (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes's Leviathan. The Cambridge Companions to Philosophy, Religion and Culture . Cambridge University Press , Cambridge , pp. 441-459. https://doi.org/10.1017/CCOL0521836670.020 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ jon parkin 19 The Reception of Hobbes’s Leviathan The traditional story about the reception of Leviathan was that it was a book that was rejected rather than read seriously.1 Leviathan’s perverse amalgamation of controversial doctrine, so the story goes, earned it universal condemnation. Hobbes was outed as an athe- ist and discredited almost as soon as the work appeared. Subsequent criticism was seen to be the idle pursuit of a discredited text, an exer- cise upon which young militant churchmen could cut their teeth, as William Warburton observed in the eighteenth century.2 We need to be aware, however, that this was a story that was largely the cre- ation of Hobbes’s intellectual opponents, writers with an interest in sidelining Leviathan from the mainstream of the history of ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Judicial Interpretation of Statutes April 2020
    Judicial Interpretation of Statutes April 2020 Executive Summary Courts in the United States serve several functions. They oversee civil and criminal trials, issue orders requiring or prohibiting certain actions, decide whether a particular law violates the constitution, and determine the meaning of language in a contract or law. This publication discusses the role the courts play in interpreting statutes. The primary focus of statutory interpretation is the language of a statute. Courts only move beyond that language when there is ambiguity. This publication discusses the tests and tools the court uses to resolve ambiguity and includes questions for legislators to consider when crafting legislation. Authority to Interpret Statutes The judicial system in the United States adopted the common law system from England.1 Under that system there were few statutes. Courts developed the law by relying on general principles, following decisions of prior courts, and applying that guidance to the specific facts of a case. The common law tradition gave courts great power to say what the law was, and there was an understanding that courts in the United States retained that power. In one of the most famous decisions by the United States Supreme Court, Marbury v. Madison, the court said: “It is emphatically the province and duty of the judicial department to say what the law is. Those who apply the rule to particular cases, must of necessity expound and interpret that rule.”2 Every court has the authority to interpret statutes. Minnesota has three levels of courts— district courts, the court of appeals, and the supreme court.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Persons of Public Law” in Foreign Legal Instruments
    Middle-East Journal of Scientific Research 20 (11): 1541-1545, 2014 ISSN 1990-9233 © IDOSI Publications, 2014 DOI: 10.5829/idosi.mejsr.2014.20.11.21082 The Use of the Category of “Legal Persons of Public Law” in Foreign Legal Instruments Oleg Jastrebov Head of the Department of Administrative and Financial Law, Peoples’ Friendship University of Russia, Miklukho-Maklaja ul., 6, Moscow, 117198, Russia Abstract: Recent years have witnessed a new upsurge in the development of the European legislation on new organizational and legal forms of legal persons in Europe. The article deals with issues of the legal mode of their operation. Attention is given to the specifics of legal status of legal persons of public law in legislation of individual countries, France in the first place as a citadel of effective and carefully thought out administration. Subjected to analysis is the history of emergence of the theory a legal person in France. Specified is the system of outlooks on a legal person in the comparative legal aspect. Discussed are nuances of using the term “legal person of public law” in a number of current constitutions. Studied are the issues of spreading the legal construction of legal person of public law over the post-Soviet space. Argumentation is given for need to use the construction of public legal person. Based on analysis of legal experience of foreign countries a conclusion is made that in terms of legislative regulation the formation procedure, the legal status and the legal operating mode of legal persons of public law must be determined by public law legislation whilst some general provisions pertaining to realization of their legal capacity must be governed by civil law conventions.
    [Show full text]