The Use of Metalanguage Among Second Language Learners to Mediate L2 Grammar Learning
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Issues in Applied Linguistics
UCLA Issues in Applied Linguistics Title The Practice of Theory in the Language Classroom Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/2s36f41d Journal Issues in Applied Linguistics, 18(2) ISSN 1050-4273 Author Norton, Bonny Publication Date 2010 DOI 10.5070/L4182005336 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California The Practice of Theory in the Language Classroom Bonny Norton University of British Columbia In this article, the author makes the case that poststructuralist theories of language, identity, and investment can be highly relevant for the practical deci- sion-making of language teachers, administrators and policy makers. She draws on her research in the international community to argue that while markers of identity such as accent, race, and gender impact the relationship between teach- ers and students, what is of far greater importance are the teachers’ pedagogical practices. This research suggests that language teaching is most effective when the teacher recognizes the multiple identities of students, and develops peda- gogical practices that enhance students’ investment in the language practices of the classroom. The author concludes that administrators and policy makers need to be supportive of language teachers as they seek to be more effective in linguistically diverse classrooms. Introduction One of the icons of language teaching in Canada, Mary Ashworth, was often heard to comment, “There is nothing as practical as a good theory.” As the United States struggles to adjust to the challenges and possibilities of linguistic diversity in American classrooms, and how research should inform educational policy mak- ing, I wish to bring theory back into the debate. -
Introduction to Applied Linguistics (3 Credit Hours) Spring 2015 Course
EDU 204A/B: Introduction to Applied Linguistics (3 Credit Hours) Spring 2015 Conceptual Framework: We believe that teachers are “Developers of Human Potential.” Like Martha Berry, we believe the role of excellent teachers is to help our candidates and the students they teach to reach their full potential by developing their head, heart and hands. Our philosophy and purposes are based on three dimensions to develop teachers and educational leaders who 1) Promote Reflection and Decision Making (head), 2) Facilitate Learning (hands), and (3) Enhance Self and Social Awareness (heart). Each of these dimensions is tied to one or more of the 10 program principals and is demonstrated by our candidates in the coursework, field and clinical experiences. Course Description: This course provides an introduction to the analysis and description of languages in general and English in particular. The major areas of linguistics (phonetics, phonology, morphology, syntax, semantics, and pragmatics) and English grammar in use are presented and discussed with an emphasis on applications, including first and second language acquisition. After an overview of the nature of language, we will study the sounds of language: how they are produced (phonetics), and how they are patterned into words (phonology). Next, we will look at different ways in which languages form words and sentences (morphology and syntax, respectively). Lastly, we will study how meaning is expressed in a language (semantics) and how context interacts with language (pragmatics). Student Learning Outcomes: 1. Appreciate the value and uniqueness in language (INTASC 4) 2. Identify patterns in the English language as a tool of analysis with which to examine language. -
BRIGHTEN: an Exploration of Where the Linguists Are Working Dr. Anna Marie Trester Career Linguist
BRIGHTEN: An exploration of where the linguists are working Dr. Anna Marie Trester Career Linguist Thinking about careers can tend to be quite linear. Such thinking would lead one to conclude that if one studied linguistics, one ought to be doing something recognizeably “linguistic” as part of one’s subsequent professional expression of that training. I tend to approach the question instead in terms of the kinds of challenges a linguist might be drawn to and then ask: which of her linguistic skills and training does she bring to this work? Often, these are the things that make her uniquely successful! In some fields, linguistic training is known and recognized as valuable. However, in most cases we linguists will need to more actively cultivate opportunities for using our skills. But in just about any work that we do, we will likely find ways to express things like cross-cultural awareness, our ability to abstract away from understanding and misunderstanding, and to apply an empirical orientation to understanding human behavior. Thus, one of my answers to “what can you do with a degree in linguistics?” is BRIGHTEN! This works to gently encourage optimism and serve as a command to gloomy would-be nay-sayers who only want to focus only on the challenges, difficulties, and anxieties of the job search process “hey, the future is BRIGHT!” but the acronym also serves as a handy “world of work” educational tool. BRIGHTEN stands for: Business, Research, Innovation/Industry, Government, Healthcare, Technology, Education/Entrepreneurship, and Non-Profits. These are some of the areas in which the linguists I know have found meaningful professional expression of their skills and training. -
Introduction to the Encyclopedia of Applied Linguistics CAROL A
Introduction to The Encyclopedia of Applied Linguistics CAROL A. CHAPELLE The Encyclopedia of Applied Linguistics is a reference work encompassing the range of research on language-related problems that arise in the real-world contexts where languages are learned and used. Because of the wide range of issues that applied linguists work on, a precise defi nition of the fi eld is diffi cult to articulate. In his 2007 Introduction to Applied Linguistics, Davies points out that one might be tempted to conclude that “because language is everywhere, applied linguistics is the science of everything,” but such a conclusion would be neither correct nor useful (Davies, 2007, p. 2). If applied linguistics is not the science of everything, how is it defi ned? Simpson, the editor of The Routledge Handbook of Applied Linguistics, defi nes applied linguistics as “the academic fi eld which connects knowledge about language to decision- making in the real world . In this sense applied linguistics mediates between theory and practice” (Simpson, 2011, p. 1). In The Oxford Handbook of Applied Linguistics, in place of a defi nition, Kaplan indicates that “Applied linguistics is a diffi cult notion to defi ne.” He goes on to say that the Handbook does not “provide a defi nitive defi nition of the fi eld,” and then explains the historical origin of the fi eld through the efforts of language teachers wanting to distance themselves from their colleagues teaching literature (Kaplan, 2010, p. vi). These two very recent books provide a wealth of examples of work in applied linguistics, which help to demonstrate the diffi culty the editors faced in constructing a usefully precise and inclusively accurate defi nition of the fi eld. -
Truth-Conditions
PLIN0009 Semantic Theory Spring 2020 Lecture Notes 1 1 What this module is about This module is an introduction to truth-conditional semantics with a focus on two impor- tant topics in this area: compositionality and quantiication. The framework adopted here is often called formal semantics and/or model-theoretical semantics, and it is characterized by its essential use of tools and concepts developed in mathematics and logic in order to study semantic properties of natural languages. Although no textbook is required, I list some introductory textbooks below for your refer- ence. • L. T. F. Gamut (1991) Logic, Language, and Meaning. The University of Chicago Press. • Irene Heim & Angelika Kratzer (1998) Semantics in Generative Grammar. Blackwell. • Thomas Ede Zimmermann & Wolfgang Sternefeld (2013) Introduction to Semantics: An Essential Guide to the Composition of Meaning. De Gruyter Mouton. • Pauline Jacobson (2014) Compositional Semantics: An Introduction to the Syntax/Semantics. Oxford University Press. • Daniel Altshuler, Terence Parsons & Roger Schwarzschild (2019) A Course in Semantics. MIT Press. There are also several overview articles of the ield by Barbara H. Partee, which I think are enjoyable. • Barbara H. Partee (2011) Formal semantics: origins, issues, early impact. In Barbara H. Partee, Michael Glanzberg & Jurģis Šķilters (eds.), Formal Semantics and Pragmatics: Discourse, Context, and Models. The Baltic Yearbook of Cognition, Logic, and Communica- tion, vol. 6. Manhattan, KS: New Prairie Press. • Barbara H. Partee (2014) A brief history of the syntax-semantics interface in Western Formal Linguistics. Semantics-Syntax Interface, 1(1): 1–21. • Barbara H. Partee (2016) Formal semantics. In Maria Aloni & Paul Dekker (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Formal Semantics, Chapter 1, pp. -
Sample Reading List in French Linguistics Général Sujets Particuliers
Sample reading list in French Linguistics Général Chapitres sélectionnés des ouvrages suivants : Bourdieu, Pierre. 1982. Ce que parler veut dire : l’économie des échanges linguistiques. Paris:Fayard. Lodge, R. Anthony. 1993. French: From dialect to standard. New York/London: Routledge. Fagyal, Z., Kibbee, D., Jenkins, F. 2006. French: A Linguistic Introduction. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Armstrong, N., Pooley, T. 2010. Social and Linguistic Change in European French. New York: Pallsgrave Macmillan. Sujets particuliers (based primarily on reading lists covered in courses taken by the candidate): Sociophonétique Articles and chapters: Armstrong, N. and Low, J. 2008. C’est encore plus jeuli, le Mareuc: some evidence for the spread of ‘o’-fronting in French. Transactions of the Philological Society, 106(3):432–455. Brousseau, A-M. 2005. The Sociolect of 17th and 18th Century French Settlers: Phonological Cues from French Creoles, U.Penn Working Papers in Linguistics, 10(2), 45-59. Carton, F. 1999. L'Epithèse vocalique en français contemporain: étude phonétique. Faits de langue, 13 : 35-45. Chalier, M. 2019. La norme de prononciation québécoise en changement (1970–2008) ? L'affrication de /t, d/ et l'antériorisation de /ɑ̃/ chez les présentateurs des journaux télévisés de Radio-Canada. La Revue Canadienne Chekin, P. 2018. Jean de Joinville and the Old French rhotic consonant. Zeitschrift für Romanische Philologie 134(4), 985-1007. Colantoni, L., & Steele, J. 2007. Acquiring /R/ in context. Studies in Second Language Acquisition, 29(3), 381-406. Dalola, A., Bridwell, K. 2019. The shape of [u]: Towards a Typology and Final Vowel Devoicing in Continental French. Proceedings of the 19th ICPhS, Melbourne, Australia, 106(3):432–455. -
Lecture 1: Tarski on Truth Philosophy of Logic and Language — HT 2016-17
Lecture 1: Tarski on Truth Philosophy of Logic and Language — HT 2016-17 Jonny McIntosh [email protected] Alfred Tarski (1901-1983) was a Polish (and later, American) mathematician, logician, and philosopher.1 In the 1930s, he published two classic papers: ‘The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages’ (1933) and ‘On the Concept of Logical Consequence’ (1936). He gives a definition of truth for formal languages of logic and mathematics in the first paper, and the essentials of the model-theoretic definition of logical consequence in the second. Over the course of the next few lectures, we’ll look at each of these in turn. 1 Background The notion of truth seems to lie at the centre of a range of other notions that are central to theorising about the formal languages of logic and mathematics: e.g. validity, con- sistency, and completeness. But the notion of truth seems to give rise to contradiction: Let sentence (1) = ‘sentence (1) is not true’. Then: 1. ‘sentence (1) is not true’ is true IFF sentence (1) is not true 2. sentence (1) = ‘sentence (1) is not true’ 3. So, sentence (1) is true IFF sentence (1) is not true 4. So, sentence (1) is true and sentence (1) is not true Tarski is worried that, unless the paradox can be resolved, metatheoretical results in- voking the notion of truth or other notions that depend on it will be remain suspect. But how can it be resolved? The second premise is undeniable, and the first premise is an instance of a schema that seems central to the concept of truth, namely the following: ‘S’ is true IFF S, 1The eventful story of Tarski’s life is told by Anita and Solomon Feferman in their wonderful biography, Alfred Tarski: Life and Logic (CUP, 2004). -
Conceptual Semantics and Natural Semantic Metalanguage Theory 413
1 Conceptual semantics and natural semantic 2 metalanguage theory have different goals 3 4 5 RAY JACKENDOFF 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 My interview with Istvan Kecskes, ‘‘On Conceptual Semantics (OCS),’’ 13 o¤ers some brief remarks on the relation of my approach to Anna Wierz- 14 bicka’s theory of semantic primitives, Natural Language Metalanguage 15 Theory (NSM). Wierzbicka’s response, ‘‘Theory and Empirical Findings: 16 A Response to Jackendo¤’’ (henceforth TEF) calls for some further 17 commentary. 18 My remarks began, ‘‘Although I think Wierzbicka has o¤ered many in- 19 sightful discussions of word meaning, I do not think that her approach 20 ultimately responds to the goals of Conceptual Semantics.’’ TEF makes 21 it clear that Conceptual Semantics does not respond to the goals of 22 NSM either. That is, the two theories, although they overlap on some 23 issues of word meaning, are ultimately asking di¤erent questions and set- 24 ting di¤erent standards for answers. 25 Conceptual Semantics is concerned not only with encoding word mean- 26 ings but also with accounting for (a) the combination of word meanings 27 into phrase and sentence meanings, (b) the character of inference, both 28 logical and heuristic, and (c) the relation of linguistic meaning to nonlin- 29 guistic understanding of the world, including the aspects of understanding 30 provided through the perceptual systems. Conceptual Semantics in turn 31 is embedded in a theory of the organization of language, the Parallel Ar- 32 chitecture (Jackendo¤ 2002, Culicover and Jackendo¤ 2005), which ad- 33 dresses the relation of semantics to syntax, phonology, and the lexicon. -
Metalanguage of Race”
608 y Symposium: “The Metalanguage of Race” Difference, Power, and Lived Experiences: Revisiting the “Metalanguage of Race” Dayo F. Gore first encountered Evelyn Brooks Higginbotham’s “African-American I Women’s History and the Metalanguage of Race” (1992) as a graduate student in a women’s history course in 1996, and the article has traveled with me ever since. I have assigned the article in at least one of my courses every year, even as I’ve taught across a number of fields, including African American history, feminist theory, and social movement history. Moreover, it has been one of the key theoretical texts I have employed to frame my own research and writing. Although I came to the article after it had been in circulation for four years, it resonated with me as a powerful and much- needed intervention in feminist theory and women’shistory.Indeed,“Meta- language” stands as one of those rare articles that continues to be relevant in ongoing debates about gender, sexuality, and race, and serves as a useful guidepost for my own scholarship. Higginbotham’s article provides an incisive response to debates among a broad spectrum of feminist scholars about how to be attentive to gender across difference and differently lived experiences, and it represented an im- portant addition to the theorization of what would become popularly known as intersectionality. Black feminist legal scholar Kimberlé Crenshaw is most often credited with coining the term “intersectionality” as she details it in two key articles, “Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race and Sex,” pub- lished in 1989, and “Mapping the Margins,” a law review article published in 1991. -
Why Major in Linguistics (And What Does a Linguist Do)? by Monica Macaulay and Kristen Syrett
1 Why Major in Linguistics (and what does a linguist do)? by Monica Macaulay and Kristen Syrett What is linguistics? Speakers of all languages know a lot about their languages, usually without knowing that they know If you are considering becoming a linguistics it. For example, as a speaker of English, you major, you probably know something about the possess knowledge about English word order. field of linguistics already. However, you may find Perhaps without even knowing it, you understand it hard to answer people who ask you, "What that Sarah admires the teacher is grammatical, exactly is linguistics, and what does a linguist do?" while Admires Sarah teacher the is not, and also They might assume that it means you speak a lot of that The teacher admires Sarah means something languages. And they may be right: you may, in entirely different. You know that when you ask a fact, be a polyglot! But while many linguists do yes-no question, you may reverse the order of speak multiple languages—or at least know a fair words at the beginning of the sentence and that the bit about multiple languages—the study of pitch of your voice goes up at the end of the linguistics means much more than this. sentence (for example, in Are you going?). Linguistics is the scientific study of language, and However, if you speak French, you might add est- many topics are studied under this umbrella. At the ce que at the beginning, and if you know American heart of linguistics is the search for the unconscious knowledge that humans have about language and how it is that children acquire it, an understanding of the structure of language in general and of particular languages, knowledge about how languages vary, and how language influences the way in which we interact with each other and think about the world. -
Propositional Calculus
CSC 438F/2404F Notes Winter, 2014 S. Cook REFERENCES The first two references have especially influenced these notes and are cited from time to time: [Buss] Samuel Buss: Chapter I: An introduction to proof theory, in Handbook of Proof Theory, Samuel Buss Ed., Elsevier, 1998, pp1-78. [B&M] John Bell and Moshe Machover: A Course in Mathematical Logic. North- Holland, 1977. Other logic texts: The first is more elementary and readable. [Enderton] Herbert Enderton: A Mathematical Introduction to Logic. Academic Press, 1972. [Mendelson] E. Mendelson: Introduction to Mathematical Logic. Wadsworth & Brooks/Cole, 1987. Computability text: [Sipser] Michael Sipser: Introduction to the Theory of Computation. PWS, 1997. [DSW] M. Davis, R. Sigal, and E. Weyuker: Computability, Complexity and Lan- guages: Fundamentals of Theoretical Computer Science. Academic Press, 1994. Propositional Calculus Throughout our treatment of formal logic it is important to distinguish between syntax and semantics. Syntax is concerned with the structure of strings of symbols (e.g. formulas and formal proofs), and rules for manipulating them, without regard to their meaning. Semantics is concerned with their meaning. 1 Syntax Formulas are certain strings of symbols as specified below. In this chapter we use formula to mean propositional formula. Later the meaning of formula will be extended to first-order formula. (Propositional) formulas are built from atoms P1;P2;P3;:::, the unary connective :, the binary connectives ^; _; and parentheses (,). (The symbols :; ^ and _ are read \not", \and" and \or", respectively.) We use P; Q; R; ::: to stand for atoms. Formulas are defined recursively as follows: Definition of Propositional Formula 1) Any atom P is a formula. -
Applied Linguistics to Identify and Contrast Racist 'Hate Speech'
Applied Linguistics Research Journal Original Research ALR Journal 2018;2(3):1–16 doi: 10.14744/alrj.2018.36855 Applied Linguistics to Identify and Contrast Racist ‘Hate Speech’: Cases from the English and Italian Language Gabriella B. Klein ABSTRACT University of Perugia, Perugia, Applied linguistics makes use of analytical tools from many not only language-related disciplines. Purpose of the research was to show how Italy the methodological choices of analysis are driven by the nature of the object of analysis itself. The ‘hate speech’ phenomenon is particularly interesting for this, due to its complexity which is reflected in a series of definitions, none of which really grasps completely its multifaceted nature. Indeed, one needs to use a variety of analytical tools originating from different social and human disciplines to support and integrate an ‘applied linguistics’ approach. Current ‘hate speech’ research focuses mainly on a lexical-semantic level (verbal communication), adding in some cases also visual aspects (visual communication), but neglecting body language (non-verbal communication) and the use of the voice (paraverbal communication). The same restricted understanding of hate speech emerged from the analysis of legal texts and their language use talking about hate crime and hate speech. The empirical case studies presented here stem from a two-year European project named RADAR - Regulating AntiDiscrimination and AntiRacism (JUST/2013/FRAC/ AG/6271) and include the analysis of two advertising images from UK and one talk show extract from Italy. Given their different communicational configuration, the materials needed to be analyzed by means of different tools ranging, in our case, from Language Critique (Sprachkritik), Critical Discourse Analysis, Ethnomethodology, Ethnographic Conversation Analysis, Psychology of Color and Forms.