74 Anthony P. Andres

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

74 Anthony P. Andres lr' ~ i i,l I 'I , Anthony P. Andres Argument for the Handbook Tradition Before we take up our main business, we should briefly re­ THE PLACE OF CoNVERSION view the order of Aristotelian logic. The scholastic logicians divide and order the parts of logic according to the division IN ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC and order of three operations of the human intellect. There­ Anthony P. Andres fore they teach that the ftrst part of logic aids the intellect in understanding indivisibles, the second in composing and dividing them, and the third in reasoning discursively. On this basis they divide the treatises of the Organon into three: the From at least the time of John of St. Thomas, scholastic Categories belongs to the ftrst part oflogic, On Interpretation to philosophers have usually learned logic from scholastic hand­ the second, and the rest, beginning with the Prior Analytics, books. If there were no significant differences between the belongs to the third. 1 handbook tradition and Aristotle's Organon, that would not Aristotle gives the rules for the conversion of propositions be a problem. But since there are many differences, especially in the second and third chapters of the Prior Analytics. 2 For in the order and manner ofteaching, the careful Thomist must example, he states that the universal negative proposition is ask himself whether the changes proposed by handbooks are a converted universally, so that if it is true that 'No A is B,' it is development of the Aristotelian tradition in logic. By reflect­ also true that 'NoB is A.' Similarly, the particular affirmative ing on the place of propositional conversion in Aristotelian proposition is convertible, so that 'SoJ?e A is B' implies that logic, this essay takes a step toward a negative answer to that 'Some B is A.' Notice that in each case what is the subject question. of the first proposition becomes the predicate of the second, The handbooks, followingJohn of St. Thomas, teach con­ and what is the predicate likewise becomes the subject. From version in the second part of logic, but the Organon teaches such examples, St. Albert draws the following definition of it in the third. This essay argues that Aristotle teaches con­ conversion: "Conversion in terms is a transposition of terms, version in the right place and that in this respect the hand­ so that the subject becomes the predicate, and the predicate books corrupt the tradition. The ftrst part of this essay will the subject." 3 Thus Aristotle puts the transposition of the examine the implicit argument for the modern placement of parts of the proposition into the third part oflogic. conversion; the second part will argue in favor of its place­ As noted above, the handbook tradition moves the teach­ ment within the Organon; and the third will answer a serious ing of conversion out of the third part of logic and into the objection against Aristotle. second, which Aristotle expounds in On Interpretation. The handbooks do not explicitly justify this change, but from cer- 1 Cf St. Thomas Aquinas, I Peri Herm., proem., n. 2. 2 Aristotle, On Interpretation, zsar. Anthony Andres is a graduate ofThomas Aquinas College. He is now 3 St. Albert the Great, I Prior Anal., tract. 1, c. 8 (all translations are Associate Professor of Philosophy at Christendom College. my own). 74 75 ---------=== r '' THE PLACE OF CONVERSION IN ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC Anthony P. Andres tain passages in John of St. Thomas we can reconstruct a plau­ not overlook the fact; by his principles, as explained by St. sible argument for it. Thomas, the enunciation cannot be converted. Before we can In his Cursus Philosophicus John writes, "We take the propo­ understand why, however, we need to understand the parts sition and the enunciation as the same thing, since such a use of the enunciation. obtains even among the wise, just as happens in common dis­ putations."4 That is, although 'enunciation' and 'proposition' are two different words, John believes that they mean the The Noun and Verb same thing, as the usage of both the common run of schol­ In the second chapter of the Categories, while identifying its ars and of the wise attests. Three chapters later he begins to subject, Aristotle makes a distinction between two kinds of teach about conversion itself "The properties which follow "things said." 7 The first kind includes things said "with in­ the whole proposition are three: opposition, conversion, and tertwining," the complex expressions, examples of it being equivalence." 5 Since, however, he has already said that the "man runs" and "man wins." The second includes things said proposition and enunciation are the same, we can conclude "without intertwining," simple expressions, examples being with John that conversion is also a property of the enuncia­ "man," "runs," and "wins." Since the Categories helps us to tion. understand indivisibles, it is concerned with the second kind We can now argue that conversion belongs in the second of "things said," not the first. And thus Aristotle goes on part oflogic. In the proemium to his commentary on Aristo­ in the Categories to divide simple "things said" according to tle's On Interpretation, St. Thomas notes that the enunciation what they signify. is the subject of the second part of logic. 6 And since every At the beginning of On Interpretation, however, he distin­ science discusses the properties of its subject, the second part guishes two kinds of simple "things said," not according to oflogic should discuss the properties of the enunciation. John what they signify, but according to how they signify. He calls of St. Thomas, however, teaches that conversion is a property them the noun and the verb. 8 The noun and verb are both sim­ of the enunciation. Therefore treatises on logic should teach ple expressions signifying something by convention, but the conversion in the second part, as indeed the handbooks do. former signifies something without implying any time, while The writers of the handbooks might have used such an the latter necessarily signifies something according to some argument to claim that they have developed the Aristotelian time. For example, 'man' is a noun and 'runs' is a verb, the tradition in logic. Their claim, however, rests on the con­ former not implying any time, the latter implying the present. tention that the conversion is a property of the enunciation, This initial distinction between the noun and verb, how- a fact they assume was overlooked by Aristotle. But he did ever, is rooted in a deeper one. St. Thomas notes: 4 John of St. Thomas, Cursus Philosophicus Thomisticus (Taurini: Ma­ Time itself, insofar as it is a certain thing, can be signified rietti, r82o), p. 23. John does acknowledge that St. Thomas draws a by a noun like any other thing. In another way, however, distinction between the enunciation and the proposition, but he ignores that which can be measured by time can be considered as it in his own treatment. 5 Ibid., p. 28. 7 Aristotle, Categories, rar6. 6 Cf St. Thomas Aquinas, I Peri Henri., proen1., n. 2. 8 Aristotle, On I11terpretation, r6a20 and r6b6. 77 1 I THE PLACE OF CONVERSION IN ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC Anthony P. Andres The Enunciation and Conversion such; and since what is first and chiefly measured by time is motion, in which action and suffering consist, then the verb, The handbooks place conversion in the second part of logic which signifies action and suffering, signifies with time. 9 as being a property of the enunciation, but here we will argue St. Thomas is here establishing a connection between 'signi­ the opposite, that enunciations cannot be converted. That ar­ fying with time' and 'signifying action and being acted upon.' gument depends upon our understanding that the noun and The verb signifies 'with time' because it in some way signifies verb are the essential parts of the enunciation. Thus our con­ what is measured by time, motion. But it signifies motion be­ sideration falls into three parts: first, we will determine and cause it signifies action and suffering, which are constituted clarify the definition of the enunciation; second, we will ar­ by motion. Thus the verb signifies with time because it sig­ gue that it must be composed of a noun and verb; and third, nifies an action or a suffering. we will argue that it cannot be converted. Of course, not only verbs proper, but also participles, infini­ In the fourth chapter of On Interpretation, Aristotle develops tives, and even some nouns signify actions and sufferings. In a definition of the enunciation by first establishing and defin­ order to distinguish the verb proper from these, St. Thomas ing its genus, speech ( oratio, logos). Speech, like the noun and draws a second distinction. He says that the verb not only verb, is vocal sound signifying something by convention, but signifies action and suffering, it "signiftes action through the it differs from the other two because it is complex, that is, its mode of action, the nature of which is that it inheres.'' 10 The parts signify something separately. Speech is among what Aris­ noun, however, "signifies something as existing by itself" 11 totle calls in the Categories "things said with intertwining," That is, the verb differs from the noun and similar expressions such as "man runs" and "man wins.'' The parts "man" and because the former signiftes something as inhering in another, "runs" signify something when taken by themselves in such while the latter signifies it as existing by itself. a way that their meaning as parts contributes to the meaning A consequence of the aforesaid distinction is that the noun of the whole speech.
Recommended publications
  • God As Both Ideal and Real Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics
    God As Both Ideal and Real Being In the Aristotelian Metaphysics Martin J. Henn St. Mary College Aristotle asserts in Metaphysics r, 1003a21ff. that "there exists a science which theorizes on Being insofar as Being, and on those attributes which belong to it in virtue of its own nature."' In order that we may discover the nature of Being Aristotle tells us that we must first recognize that the term "Being" is spoken in many ways, but always in relation to a certain unitary nature, and not homonymously (cf. Met. r, 1003a33-4). Beings share the same name "eovta," yet they are not homonyms, for their Being is one and the same, not manifold and diverse. Nor are beings synonyms, for synonymy is sameness of name among things belonging to the same genus (as, say, a man and an ox are both called "animal"), and Being is no genus. Furthermore, synonyms are things sharing a common intrinsic nature. But things are called "beings" precisely because they share a common relation to some one extrinsic nature. Thus, beings are neither homonyms nor synonyms, yet their core essence, i.e. their Being as such, is one and the same. Thus, the unitary Being of beings must rest in some unifying nature extrinsic to their respective specific essences. Aristotle's dialectical investigations into Being eventually lead us to this extrinsic nature in Book A, i.e. to God, the primary Essence beyond all specific essences. In the pre-lambda books of the Metaphysics, however, this extrinsic nature remains very much up for grabs.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Assertoric Syllogistic and Modern Relevance Logic*
    Aristotle’s assertoric syllogistic and modern relevance logic* Abstract: This paper sets out to evaluate the claim that Aristotle’s Assertoric Syllogistic is a relevance logic or shows significant similarities with it. I prepare the grounds for a meaningful comparison by extracting the notion of relevance employed in the most influential work on modern relevance logic, Anderson and Belnap’s Entailment. This notion is characterized by two conditions imposed on the concept of validity: first, that some meaning content is shared between the premises and the conclusion, and second, that the premises of a proof are actually used to derive the conclusion. Turning to Aristotle’s Prior Analytics, I argue that there is evidence that Aristotle’s Assertoric Syllogistic satisfies both conditions. Moreover, Aristotle at one point explicitly addresses the potential harmfulness of syllogisms with unused premises. Here, I argue that Aristotle’s analysis allows for a rejection of such syllogisms on formal grounds established in the foregoing parts of the Prior Analytics. In a final section I consider the view that Aristotle distinguished between validity on the one hand and syllogistic validity on the other. Following this line of reasoning, Aristotle’s logic might not be a relevance logic, since relevance is part of syllogistic validity and not, as modern relevance logic demands, of general validity. I argue that the reasons to reject this view are more compelling than the reasons to accept it and that we can, cautiously, uphold the result that Aristotle’s logic is a relevance logic. Keywords: Aristotle, Syllogism, Relevance Logic, History of Logic, Logic, Relevance 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Jewish Averroists Between Two Expulsions (1306-1492): from Conflict to Reconciliation
    JEWISH AVERROISTS BETWEEN TWO EXPULSIONS (1306-1492): FROM CONFLICT TO RECONCILIATION Basem Mahmud Freie Universität Berlin ABSTRACT This article investigates the intellectual production of Jewish authors influenced by Averroes in the 14th and 15th Centuries in northern Spain and southern France. The primary objective is to determine the main features of Jewish Averroism in this period, and to understand it within its socio-historical context. The outcomes suggest that there was a relationship between the new social and political trends toward democratization and reconciliation in the heart of Jewish communities on one hand, and the growing interest in Averroes’ original works on the other. Original here means the works that are not commentaries or summaries of other works. Key words: Aristotelianism, Averroes, Averroism, Jewish philosophy, Kabbalah, Maimonides, Scripture. INTRODUCTION «There is nothing worse in social government than a policy that makes one single society into several, just as there is no greater good in communities than a policy that joins and unifies» (Averroes)1 The 14th Century was a very difficult time for Jewish communities in northern Spain and southern France, they faced great threats from outside as well as significant domestic division. The domestic conflict emerged not only because of religious and philosophical issues, but also due to economic and social matters related to the distribution of wealth and power within Jewish communities.2 In addition, these communities lived in delicate conditions due to threats from the Christians. This situation also had an effect on demographics. Since the last years of 13th Century, the Jewish community started to encounter sizeable obstacles in its demographic development.3 Under these conditions, Hebraic Averroism continued its development which had begun in XIII century.
    [Show full text]
  • Marko Malink (NYU)
    Demonstration by reductio ad impossibile in Posterior Analytics 1.26 Marko Malink (New York University) Contents 1. Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 ................................................................................. 1 2. Direct negative demonstration vs. demonstration by reductio ................................................. 14 3. Aristotle’s argument from priority in nature .............................................................................. 25 4. Priority in nature for a-propositions ............................................................................................ 38 5. Priority in nature for e-, i-, and o-propositions .......................................................................... 55 6. Accounting for Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 ................................................... 65 7. Parts and wholes ............................................................................................................................. 77 References ............................................................................................................................................ 89 1. Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 At the beginning of the Analytics, Aristotle states that the subject of the treatise is demonstration (ἀπόδειξις). A demonstration, for Aristotle, is a kind of deductive argument. It is a deduction through which, when we possess it, we have scientific knowledge (ἐπιστήμη). While the Prior Analytics deals with deduction in
    [Show full text]
  • C.S. Peirce's Abduction from the Prior Analytics
    Providence College DigitalCommons@Providence Community Scholar Publications Providence College Community Scholars 7-1996 C.S. Peirce's Abduction from the Prior Analytics William Paul Haas Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.providence.edu/comm_scholar_pubs Haas, William Paul, "C.S. Peirce's Abduction from the Prior Analytics" (1996). Community Scholar Publications. 2. https://digitalcommons.providence.edu/comm_scholar_pubs/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Providence College Community Scholars at DigitalCommons@Providence. It has been accepted for inclusion in Community Scholar Publications by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Providence. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WILLIAM PAUL HAAS July 1996 C.S. PEIRCE'S ABDUCTION FROM THE PRIOR ANALYTICS In his Ancient Formal Logic. Professor Joseph Bochenski finds Aristotle's description of syllogisms based upon hypotheses to be "difficult to understand." Noting that we do not have the treatise which Aristotle promised to write, Bochenski laments the fact that the Prior Analytics, where it is treated most explicitly, "is either corrupted or (which is more probable) was hastily written and contains logical errors." (1) Charles Sanders Peirce wrestled with the same difficult text when he attempted to establish the Aristotelian roots of his theory of abductive or hypothetical reasoning. However, Peirce opted for the explanation that the fault was with the corrupted text, not with Aristotle's exposition. Peirce interpreted the text of Book II, Chapter 25 thus: Accordingly, when he opens the next chapter with the word ' Ajray (¿y-q a word evidently chosen to form a pendant to 'Errctyuyrj, we feel sure that this is what he is coming to.
    [Show full text]
  • Catalogue of Titles of Works Attributed to Aristotle
    Catalogue of Titles of works attributed by Aristotle 1 To enhance readability of the translations and usability of the catalogues, I have inserted the following bold headings into the lists. These have no authority in any manuscript, but are based on a theory about the composition of the lists described in chapter 3. The text and numbering follows that of O. Gigon, Librorum deperditorum fragmenta. PART ONE: Titles in Diogenes Laertius (D) I. Universal works (ta kathalou) A. The treatises (ta syntagmatika) 1. The dialogues or exoterica (ta dialogika ex terika) 2. The works in propria persona or lectures (ta autopros pa akroamatika) a. Instrumental works (ta organika) b. Practical works (ta praktika) c. Productive Works (ta poi tika) d. Theoretical works (ta the r tika) . Natural philosophy (ta physiologia) . Mathematics (ta math matika) B. Notebooks (ta hypomn matika) II. Intermediate works (ta metaxu) III. Particular works (ta merika) PART TWO: Titles in the Vita Hesychii (H) This list is organized in the same way as D, with two exceptions. First, IA2c “productive works” has dropped out. Second, there is an appendix, organized as follows: IV. Appendix A. Intermediate or Particular works B. Treatises C. Notebooks D. Falsely ascribed works PART THREE: Titles in Ptolemy al-Garib (A) This list is organized in the same way as D, except it contains none of the Intermediate or Particular works. It was written in Arabic, and later translated into Latin, and then reconstructed into Greek, which I here translate. PART FOUR: Titles in the order of Bekker (B) The modern edition contains works only in IA2 (“the works in propria persona”), and replaces the theoretical works before the practical and productive, as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • The Beginnings of Formal Logic: Deduction in Aristotle's Topics Vs
    Phronesis 60 (�0�5) �67-309 brill.com/phro The Beginnings of Formal Logic: Deduction in Aristotle’s Topics vs. Prior Analytics Marko Malink Department of Philosophy, New York University, 5 Washington Place, New York, NY 10003. USA [email protected] Abstract It is widely agreed that Aristotle’s Prior Analytics, but not the Topics, marks the begin- ning of formal logic. There is less agreement as to why this is so. What are the distinctive features in virtue of which Aristotle’s discussion of deductions (syllogismoi) qualifies as formal logic in the one treatise but not in the other? To answer this question, I argue that in the Prior Analytics—unlike in the Topics—Aristotle is concerned to make fully explicit all the premisses that are necessary to derive the conclusion in a given deduction. Keywords formal logic – deduction – syllogismos – premiss – Prior Analytics – Topics 1 Introduction It is widely agreed that Aristotle’s Prior Analytics marks the beginning of formal logic.1 Aristotle’s main concern in this treatise is with deductions (syllogismoi). Deductions also play an important role in the Topics, which was written before the Prior Analytics.2 The two treatises start from the same definition of what 1 See e.g. Cornford 1935, 264; Russell 1946, 219; Ross 1949, 29; Bocheński 1956, 74; Allen 2001, 13; Ebert and Nortmann 2007, 106-7; Striker 2009, p. xi. 2 While the chronological order of Aristotle’s works cannot be determined with any certainty, scholars agree that the Topics was written before the Prior Analytics; see Brandis 1835, 252-9; Ross 1939, 251-2; Bocheński 1956, 49-51; Kneale and Kneale 1962, 23-4; Brunschwig 1967, © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���5 | doi �0.��63/�5685�84-��34��86 268 Malink a deduction is (stated in the first chapter of each).
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Principles As Elements
    Aristotle on Principles as Elements Marko Malink, New York University Draft, September 2016 Abstract: In his discussion of the four causes, Aristotle claims that ‘the hypotheses are material causes of the conclusion’ ( Physics 2.3, Metaphysics Δ 2). This claim has puzzled commentators since antiquity. It is usually taken to mean that the premises of any deduction are material causes of the conclusion. By contrast, I argue that the claim does not apply to deductions in general but only to scientific demonstrations. In Aristotle’s view, the theorems of a given science are composites composed of the indemonstrable premises from which they are demonstrated. Accordingly, these premises are elements, and hence material causes, of the theorems. Given this, Aristotle’s claim can be shown to be well-motivated and illuminating. 1. Hypotheses are material causes of the conclusion In Physics 2.3 and its doublet in Metaphysics Δ 2, Aristotle distinguishes the so-called four causes. The first of them is characterized as ‘that from which as a constituent something comes to be’. 1 Since antiquity, this type of cause is known as the ‘material cause’. 2 Aristotle illustrates it by a series of examples as follows: 1 τὸ ἐξ οὗ γίγνεταί τι ἐνυπάρχοντος, Phys. 2.3 194b24 (= Metaph. Δ 2 1013a24–5). 2 The ancient commentators refer to it as ὑλικὸν αἴτιον (Alex. Aphr. in Metaph. 349.2, 351.5, 353.20, Philop. in Phys. 243.21, 243.30, 246.25–247.11, 249.6, Simpl. in Phys. 314.27, 319.20, 320.13, Asclep. in Metaph. 305.22–4, 306.9–14).
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 302: Plato and Aristotle Course Description This Course
    Philosophy 302: Plato and Aristotle Course Description This course surveys the essential content of the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle and considers more briefly some of the earlier thinkers whose ideas form the immediate context for their works. We will begin with dialogues in which Plato's is thought to give a reasonable accurate depiction of his mentor Socrates, and will focus on the ethical theses defended in these works and on the standards for knowledge presupposed by them. We will then observe how these theses and standards, in combination with certain ideas and problems from pre-Socratic thought, lead Plato to develop the first philosophical system: an integrated set of ideas about the fundamental nature of reality, man, knowledge, and value. We will then turn to Aristotle’s formulation of the principles of logic and the structure of science. Finally, we will study Aristotle's own philosophical system, with a focus on the ways in which it is similar to and different from Plato's. Instructor and Course Information Instructor: Gregory Salmieri ([email protected], 412-576-2990) Meetings: Friday 11:30am – 2:30pm, Murray Hall 115 Required Books Reeve (tr.), Plato: Republic, Hackett (ISBN-10: 0872207366, ISBN-13: 978-0872207363). [Amazon] [Barnes and Noble] Irwin and Fine (tr.), Aristotle: Selections (ISBN-10: 0915145677, ISBN-13: 978-0915145676). [Amazon] [Barnes and Noble] Adamson, Classical Philosophy, Oxford University Press (ISBN-10: 0199674531, ISBN-13: 978- 0199674534). [Amazon] [Barnes and Noble] Additional readings available online. Grading There will be ten quizzes over the course of the semester, administered through Sakai, which will be collectively worth 20% of the grade, two papers each worth 30% of the grade, and a final exam worth 20%.
    [Show full text]
  • The Distinction of Essence and Existence in Avicenna's
    THE DISTINCTION OF ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE IN AVICENNA’S METAPHYSICS: THE TEXT AND ITS CONTEXT* Amos Bertolacci In his groundbreaking monograph Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition and in many other magisterial essays, Dimitri Gutas has underscored the key role that metaphysics plays in Avicenna’s phil- osophical system.1 Gutas’ account of metaphysics (as well as of the other main philosophical disciplines), in Avicenna’s œuvre is based on a full fledged methodology resulting from the critical evaluation of the assumptions of previous scholarship, an insightful analysis of the fundamental texts, and a thorough reconstruction of their doctrinal and historical context. All scholars interested in Avicenna’s metaphys- ics (not to say of his psychology, noetics and epistemology) and Arabic metaphysical speculation in general, can only be thankful to Gutas’ pioneering research for having explored and mapped what had been, to a large extent, virgin territory and for having provided a solid, bril- liant and comprehensive outline of the whole, thus paving the way to subsequent, more specific investigations. As a sign of personal heartfelt gratitude and in the footsteps of Gutas’ masterly approach outlined above, the present contribution wishes to provide the analysis of a crucial issue of Avicenna’s metaphysics. The * Earlier versions of the present article have been presented in the following mee- tings: the seminar “La Métaphysique d’Avicenne,” Centre d’histoire des sciences et de philosophies arabes et médiévales (CNRS-UMR 7062), Ecole Normale Supérieure- Ulm, Paris (November 2006); a research meeting organized at the Scuola Normale Superiore of Pisa in December 2006; and a Forschungskolloquium held at the Albert- Ludwigs-Universität of Freiburg in May 2007.
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Chicago Aristotle on the Necessity
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO ARISTOTLE ON THE NECESSITY OF WHAT WE KNOW A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVISION OF THE HUMANITIES IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY JOSHUA MENDELSOHN CHICAGO, ILLINOIS JUNE 2019 TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS . iv ABSTRACT . v 1 INTRODUCTION . 1 1.1 Aristotle on what we know ........................... 1 1.2 Previous approaches ............................... 7 1.3 Some first steps toward an answer ....................... 25 1.4 Chapter breakdown ................................ 34 2 ARISTOTLE’S DURABILITY ARGUMENTS . 36 2.1 Knowledge in the Categories ........................... 36 2.1.1 Knowledge as a relative: Categories 7 . 36 2.1.2 Knowledge as a state: Categories 8 ................... 51 2.1.3 The tension between the two principles . 59 2.2 When what is changeable goes out of view: Nicomachean Ethics VI.3 . 66 2.2.1 The sense of “necessity” ......................... 74 2.2.2 A Platonic precursor: Theaetetus 163c–164b . 75 2.3 Durability and demonstration: Posterior Analytics I.6 . 79 2.4 Knowledge of sensible particulars: Metaphysics Ζ.15 . 86 2.5 Taking stock ................................... 88 3 THE OBJECT OF KNOWLEDGE . 90 3.1 The introduction of the Forms ......................... 93 3.2 The irrelevance of the Forms .......................... 96 3.3 Essentiality and necessity: Posterior Analytics I.4 . 102 3.3.1 “Of all” and “per se” . 103 3.3.2 Per se predications and necessity . 108 3.3.3 “Universal” ................................112 3.3.4 Demonstrative necessities concerning individuals . 115 3.4 Per se necessity in natural science . 120 3.4.1 Per se necessity in biology: Parts of Animals II.3 .
    [Show full text]
  • Al-Farabi's Short Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics
    Al-Farabi’s Short Commentary on Aristotle’s Prior Analytics Translated, with an Introduction and Notes, by Nicholas Rescher University of Pittsburgh Press AL-FARABI’S SHORT COMMENTARY ON ARISTOTLE’S PRIOR ANALYTICS AL-FARABI’S SHORT COMMENTARY ON ARISTOTLE’S PRIOR ANALYTICS Translated from the Original Arabic with Introduction and Notes BY NICHOLAS RESCHER Professor of Philosophy in the University of Pittsburgh UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH PRESS 1963 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 63-10581 Printed in Great Britain by Butler & ‘Tanner Ltd, Frome and London This book is dedicated, with gratitude and with love, to my mother and to the memory of my father. PREFACE This English version of al-Farabi’s “Short Commentary on Prior Analytics”, made from Mlle Mubahat Tirker’s recent edition of the Arabic text (Revue de la Faculté des Langues, d Histoire, et de Géographie de? Université d Ankara, vol. 16 [1958]), is the first appearanceof this treatise in a European language. It is hoped that this addition to the dozen or so Arabic logical texts now accessible to the non- Orientalist will contribute to a wider appreciation of the great mass of work constituting the Arabic contribution to logic, which remains so largely terra incognita. I wish to thank Mrs. Shukrieh Kassis and especially Mr. Seostoris Khalil for help with the translation. I am in- debted to Mr. Storrs McCall, Dr. J. Ackrill, and particu- larly to Professor D. M. Dunlop for reading my typescript and suggesting needed improvements. Although some strengths of this work owetheir existence to others, all of its weaknesses and errors must be laid at my own door.
    [Show full text]