The Stoics on Nature and Truth

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Stoics on Nature and Truth Durham E-Theses The stoics on nature and truth Connor, Martin J How to cite: Connor, Martin J (2000) The stoics on nature and truth, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/4346/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk THE STOICS ON NATURE AND TRUTH MARTIN J CONNOR The copyright of this thesis rests with the author. No quotation from it should be published in any form, including Electronic and the Internet, without the author's prior written consent. All information derived from this thesis must be acknowledged appropriately. SUBMITTED IN FULFILMENT OF THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY 1 7 SEP 2001 DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF DURHAM 2000 ABSTRACT THE STOICS ON NATURE AND TRUTH MARTIN CONNOR First, this thesis outlines part of the thought of some pre-Socratic thinkers, particularly Heraclitus. In doing this, I explore the historical provenance of certain ideas which came to be important in Stoicism. It then moves on to look at the Stoic view of 'physics', including some comparison with Epicurus and Aristotle, and with a focus on the concept of the continuum. The third chapter attempts to synthesise a common problem arising from a belief in the continuum, namely a problem of indeterminacy. In the fourth chapter, certain characterisations of Stoic epistemology are considered, along with an overview of recent interpretations of the Stoic theory of impressions. It concludes with the thought that at certain crucial points - such as whether impressions themselves are to be thought of as true and false - the Stoic position is underdetermined with respect to the evidence. Pursuing this thought into the fifth chapter, we see the evidence as being equivalently consistent with a 'two-tier' theory of perception, where impressions themselves are understood as neither true nor false in any sense, but in which 'the true' arises as a result of the transformative effect of reason. This theory is shown to connect with verbalisation through the 'rational impression'. This leads to the suggestion that the Stoics had a linguistic diagnosis for some problems in philosophy, arrived at by their reflections on ambiguity and etymology. In the final chapter, an account of intersubjectivity is explored, which preserves for the Stoics the claim that their truth has an objective character and is thus appropriate for a 'dogmatic' philosophy. f FOR MY MOTHER AND FATHER TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER ONE : THE HISTORICAL BACKGROUND . 1 INTRODUCTION 1 THE PRE-SOCRATIC INHERITANCE 9 XENOPHANES 11 HERACLITUS 16 PYTHAGORAS 22 PARMENIDES 25 ANTISTHENES AND THE CYNICS 33 PLATO AND ARISTOTLE 40 CONCLUSION 42 CHAPTER TWO : THE CONTEXT OF KNOWLEDGE. 43 INTRODUCTION 43 HELLENISTIC SCIENCE 49 EPICUREAN ATOMISM AND ARGUMENTS AGAINST INFINITE DIVISIBILITY 53 THE FOUR ELEMENT THEORY: ARISTOTLE AND THE STOICS 57 PNEUMA, TONOS AND THE DYNAMIC CONTINUUM 66 CHRYSIPPUS' GLIMPSE OF THE INFINITE APPROACH TO A LIMIT 77 CONCLUSION 85 CHAPTER THREE : THE CONTINUUM AND INDETERMINACY. 87 INTRODUCTION 87 SPATIAL MAGNITUDES 88 RETRENCHABILITY AND TIME 98 CONCLUSION 107 CHAPTER FOUR : CHARACTERISING STOIC EPISTEMOLOGY. 108 INTRODUCTION 108 OLD CABBAGE AND ANCIENT THINKING: REALISM IN GREEK PHILOSOPHY 109 CONSIDERING THE EVIDENCE FOR A STOIC THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE 125 THE COHERENCE INTERPRETATION. 128 THE CORRESPONDENCE INTERPRETATION 143 SUMMING UP 147 WHAT ARE WE TO THINK OF WHEN ASKED TO THINK OF THE STOIC CRITERION OF TRUTH? - 149 MUST WE LIMIT THE STOICS TO A SINGLE CRITERION OF TRUTH? 153 STOIC IMPRESSIONS 161 TWO PROBLEMS ABOUT IMPRESSIONS: CAN THEY BE TRUE OR FALSE? WHAT CONTENT DO THEY HAVE? 168 EVIDENCE IN FAVOUR OF A RESTRICTED INTERPRETATION 171 EVIDENCE AGAINST A RESTRICTED INTERPRETATION 174 PRINCIPAL EVIDENCE UNDERLYING THE DEBATE ABOUT RATIONAL/ IRRATIONAL IMPRESSIONS IN STOICISM 195 CONCLUSION 214 CHAPTER FIVE : CONSTRUCTING A TWO-TIER VIEW 216 INTRODUCTION 216 INTERPRETING ZENO'S FIST - 219 CHRYSIPPUS AND CLEANTHES: SYMBOLISM vs. MIMESIS 233 BRUNSCHW1G AND NOOUMENA J 250 THE TRUTH AND THE TRUE 261 ISOMORPHISM AND THE LEKTA . 267 AMBIGUITY AND ETYMOLOGY 272 EVIDENCE FOR JNTERSUBJECTIVITY 279 CONCLUSION 283 CHAPTER SIX : INTERSUBJECTIVITY AND OBJECTIVITY. 285 INTRODUCTION 285 ARISTOTELIAN HAPPINESS AND OKEIOSIS 287 THE SUBJECTIVE AND THE NORMATIVE 290 THE STOICS AND SELF-REFLECTION 297 INTERSUBJECnVITY AND SELF-REFLECTION - 302 CONCLUSION 311 SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION. - 313 ABBREVIATIONS Long and Sedley LS The Hellenistic Philosophers, (2 vols) Diogenes Laertius D.L. Lives of the Philosophers Sextus Empiricus S.E.M Against the Professors S.E.PH Outlines of Pyrrhonism Cicero Acad. - Academica ND On the nature of the gods De Fin On ends Plutarch Comm. not. = On Common Conceptions St. rep. = On Stoic self-contradictions Galen Diff. Puis. On the differences in pidses Qual. inc. = On incorporeal qualities Plac. On Hippocrates' and Plato's doctrines Alexander of Aphrodisias In Ar. An. Pr. = On Aristotle's Prior Analytics Epicurus Ep. Hdt. = Letter to Herodotus i PREFACE Stoicism emerged as the Platonic vision of transcendent forms was fading, into a philosophical milieu powerfully clear about the possibilities of logic. Into this context, we can speculate, came Zeno - a fiery philosopher himself, advocating a fiery metaphysics. In placing fire at the foundation of his view of the world, he placed something flickering, uncertain, consuming and sustaining. In chapter three, we will look at Michael White's argument constructed around the notion that the Stoics believed surfaces were fuzzy, and subject to indeterminacy and artifice. If we need to imagine the 'fuzzy regions' he mentions, we need only think of the detailed, shimmering edge of a candle flame. Perhaps, by staring at a certain flame, it occurred to Zeno that hyle was flexible in a similar way to the flame. As we see in Chapter Four, there were unquestioned presuppositions in Greek thinking, and because of these Zeno was faced with the challenge of explaining how we could speak truly of something that was, at a crucial level, indeterminate. One solution to this problem is to locate determination within human conceptualisation, rather than as a property of the world. The philosophical task then becomes not to examine our relationship as individuals to the world, but to explain our relationship as individuals to each other, where we each have determinate conceptions, secured by causation and revealed in language. This is the picture I develop in Chapter Five. We are called by the Stoics to 'live in accordance with nature', with the underlying belief that the unfolding cosmos is sentient, rational and perfect. We can detect in this injunction an imperative to philosophise that goes as follows : "Since it is our folly that stands in the way of the universe's perfection, we must philosophise ii to perfect the universe." Ultimately, what we recognise after a period reflecting on Stoic doctrines is that an attractive and inclusive image of humanity emerges. We exist collectively, in our relation to the true. What is a rational animal? For the Stoics, it is the universe's consciousness of itself. We explore one account of the way in which the logos inspires self-reflection in Chapter Six. Once self-reflection is seen as complementary to the Stoic account of impressions, it is but a small step to the conviction that wise people speaking truly express infallible knowledge about the world. From such wise people, goes the Stoic hope, we could build a city, and from such a city a new world based on citizenship of the universe. In a certain sense - in this certain sense - Stoicism was a declaration of intrinsic human value. It used its intriguing epistemology (and whoever is closest to the truth, Stoic epistemology is intriguing), and staggering command of logic to claim a universality for its doctrines that less ambitious positions could not countenance. This thesis represents a certain stage in my thinking about Stoicism. Since I am neither a classicist (in any formal sense) nor a linguist, my interpretation is not based on a 'philological' level of analysis. Rather, my method has been that of a philosophical investigation based on the Stoic texts in translation. I have where possible studied these translations against the texts in the original language to develop my readings of them. The greatest danger for the student of these texts who is not steeped in Classical Studies is that elementary philological errors will lead to confusions at the level of philosophical interpretation. As a safeguard against this danger, I have tried where possible to couch my argument in the language of others, whose relationship to the Stoic texts is expert and direct. As a result of this, the reader will notice that I often quote extensively from the scholarly literature. In doing this I can claim two ancient precedents. First, it was said of Chrysippus' writings that iii if the quotations were removed, there would be hardly anything left (D.L. 7.81). Second, we are told of a Stoic injunction to 'follow the good authors' - those who used the rules of language correctly to succinctly frame a definition or argument (D.L.
Recommended publications
  • The Coherence of Stoic Ontology
    The Coherence of Stoic Ontology by Vanessa de Harven A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Prof. Dorothea Frede, Co-chair Prof. Klaus Corcilius, Co-chair Prof. A.A. Long Spring 2012 Abstract The Coherence of Stoic Ontology by Vanessa de Harven Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professors Dorothea Frede and Klaus Corcilius, Co-chairs Any thoroughgoing physicalist is challenged to give an account of immaterial entities such as thoughts and mathematical objects. The Stoics, who eagerly affirmed that only bodies exist, crafted an elegant solution to this challenge: not everything that is Something (ti) exists. Rather, some things have a derivative mode of reality they call subsistence: these entities are non-existent in that they are not themselves solid bodies, but they are nonetheless Something physical because they depend on bodies for their subsistence. My dissertation uncovers the unifying principles of Stoic subsistence, and shows how they can account for thoughts and other immaterial entities without running afoul of their physicalist commitments. While all commentators agree that the Stoics posited Something as the highest category of being, they have failed to find a coherent physicalist account of Stoic ontology. For instance, (1) a canonical set of incorporeals (time, place, void, and what is sayable (lekton)) is well attested, but there is little agreement as to what these entities have in common as incorporeals, which makes the category look like an ad hoc collection of left-over entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Platons Raumbegriff Verständlich, Desgleichen Der Umstand, Daß Timaios Grenzen Einer Erklärung Der Welt Und Schwierigkeiten Einer Konsistenten Darstellung Hervorhebt
    Der Begriff des Raumes im „Timaios“ im Zusammenhang mit der Naturphilosophie und der Metaphysik Platons Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung des Doktorgrades der Philosophie der Philosophischen Fakultät der Universität Konstanz vorgelegt von Kyung Jik Lee aus Seoul Referent: Prof. Dr. Jürgen Mittelstraß Korreferent: Prof. Dr. Gereon Wolters Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 19. Juli 1999 Diese Arbeit erscheint im Mai 2000 auch als Buchhandelsausgabe im Verlag Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg Meinen Eltern gewidmet Inhaltsverzeichnis Vorwort 9 I Die Erklärung der Welt als wahrscheinliche Erklärung (eikôs logos) 11 1 Einleitung 2 Die Synonymität von eikôs mythos und eikôs logos 3 Der eikôs logos als nicht-philosophische Erklärung 4 Der eikôs logos 4.1 Akribês logos? 4.2 Das Wahrscheinliche und das Historische 4.3 Das Wahrscheinliche und das Notwendige 4.4 Die wahrscheinliche Rede als inkonsistente Rede 4.5 Die wahrscheinliche Rede als hypothetische Anwendung einer exakten Erklärung auf sinnliche Gegenstände 4.6 Die wahrscheinliche Rede als Begrenzung der Anwendung einer exakten Erklärung auf sinnliche Gegenstände II Der Demiurg und der Logos der Welt 38 1 Einleitung 2 Wer ist der Demiurg im „Timaios“? 3 Demiurg und Gott 4 Demiurg und Weltseele 5 Demiurg und Idee des Guten 6 Demiurg und transzendente Vernunft 7 Schwierigkeiten der Rede vom Demiurgen 7.1 Zur Suche nach dem Demiurgen 7.2 Logos und Ergon 7.3 Demiurg und Timaios 7.3.1 Einleitung 7.3.2 Poiêtês 7.3.3 Weitere Parallelen zwischen Demiurg und Timaios 7.3.4 Gott und Götter 7.4 Der Demiurg
    [Show full text]
  • Skepticism and Pluralism Ways of Living a Life Of
    SKEPTICISM AND PLURALISM WAYS OF LIVING A LIFE OF AWARENESS AS RECOMMENDED BY THE ZHUANGZI #±r A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2004 By John Trowbridge Dissertation Committee: Roger T. Ames, Chairperson Tamara Albertini Chung-ying Cheng James E. Tiles David R. McCraw © Copyright 2004 by John Trowbridge iii Dedicated to my wife, Jill iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS In completing this research, I would like to express my appreciation first and foremost to my wife, Jill, and our three children, James, Holly, and Henry for their support during this process. I would also like to express my gratitude to my entire dissertation committee for their insight and understanding ofthe topics at hand. Studying under Roger Ames has been a transformative experience. In particular, his commitment to taking the Chinese tradition on its own terms and avoiding the tendency among Western interpreters to overwrite traditional Chinese thought with the preoccupations ofWestern philosophy has enabled me to broaden my conception ofphilosophy itself. Roger's seminars on Confucianism and Daoism, and especially a seminar on writing a philosophical translation ofthe Zhongyong r:pJm (Achieving Equilibrium in the Everyday), have greatly influenced my own initial attempts to translate and interpret the seminal philosophical texts ofancient China. Tamara Albertini's expertise in ancient Greek philosophy was indispensable to this project, and a seminar I audited with her, comparing early Greek and ancient Chinese philosophy, was part ofthe inspiration for my choice ofresearch topic. I particularly valued the opportunity to study Daoism and the Yijing ~*~ with Chung-ying Cheng g\Gr:p~ and benefited greatly from his theory ofonto-cosmology as a means of understanding classical Chinese philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Squaring the Circle a Case Study in the History of Mathematics the Problem
    Squaring the Circle A Case Study in the History of Mathematics The Problem Using only a compass and straightedge, construct for any given circle, a square with the same area as the circle. The general problem of constructing a square with the same area as a given figure is known as the Quadrature of that figure. So, we seek a quadrature of the circle. The Answer It has been known since 1822 that the quadrature of a circle with straightedge and compass is impossible. Notes: First of all we are not saying that a square of equal area does not exist. If the circle has area A, then a square with side √A clearly has the same area. Secondly, we are not saying that a quadrature of a circle is impossible, since it is possible, but not under the restriction of using only a straightedge and compass. Precursors It has been written, in many places, that the quadrature problem appears in one of the earliest extant mathematical sources, the Rhind Papyrus (~ 1650 B.C.). This is not really an accurate statement. If one means by the “quadrature of the circle” simply a quadrature by any means, then one is just asking for the determination of the area of a circle. This problem does appear in the Rhind Papyrus, but I consider it as just a precursor to the construction problem we are examining. The Rhind Papyrus The papyrus was found in Thebes (Luxor) in the ruins of a small building near the Ramesseum.1 It was purchased in 1858 in Egypt by the Scottish Egyptologist A.
    [Show full text]
  • Language Logic and Reality: a Stoic Perspective (Spring 2013)
    Language Logic and Reality: A Stoic Perspective Aaron Tuor History of Lingustics WWU Spring 2013 1 Language, Logic, and Reality: A Stoic perspective Contents 1 Introduction: The Tripartite Division of Stoic Philosophy.............................3 2 Stoic Physics...................................................................................................4 3 Stoic Dialectic.................................................................................................4 3.1 A Stoic Theory of Mind: Logos and presentations..........................4 3.2 Stoic Philosophy of Language: Lekta versus linguistic forms.........6 3.3 Stoic Logic.......................................................................................7 3.3.1 Simple and Complex Axiomata........................................7 3.3.2 Truth Conditions and Sentence Connectives....................8 3.3.3 Inference Schemata and Truths of Logic..........................9 3.4 Stoic Theory of Knowledge.............................................................10 3.4.1 Truth..................................................................................10 3.4.2 Knowledge........................................................................11 4 Conclusion: Analysis of an eristic argument..................................................12 4.1 Hermogenes as the Measure of "Man is the measure."...................13 Appendix I: Truth Tables and Inference Schemata...........................................17 Appendix II: Diagram of Communication.........................................................18
    [Show full text]
  • Stoic Enlightenments
    Copyright © 2011 Margaret Felice Wald All rights reserved STOIC ENLIGHTENMENTS By MARGARET FELICE WALD A Dissertation submitted to the Graduate School-New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in English written under the direction of Michael McKeon and approved by ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ New Brunswick, New Jersey October 2011 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Stoic Enlightenments By MARGARET FELICE WALD Dissertation Director: Michael McKeon Stoic ideals infused seventeenth- and eighteenth-century thought, not only in the figure of the ascetic sage who grins and bears all, but also in a myriad of other constructions, shaping the way the period imagined ethical, political, linguistic, epistemological, and social reform. My dissertation examines the literary manifestation of Stoicism’s legacy, in particular regarding the institution and danger of autonomy, the foundation and limitation of virtue, the nature of the passions, the difference between good and evil, and the referentiality of language. Alongside the standard satirical responses to the ancient creed’s rigor and rationalism, seventeenth- and eighteenth-century poetry, drama, and prose developed Stoic formulations that made the most demanding of philosophical ideals tenable within the framework of common experience. Instead of serving as hallmarks for hypocrisy, the literary stoics I investigate uphold a brand of stoicism fit for the post-regicidal, post- Protestant Reformation, post-scientific revolutionary world. My project reveals how writers used Stoicism to determine the viability of philosophical precept and establish ways of compensating for human fallibility. The ambivalent status of the Stoic sage, staged and restaged in countless texts, exemplified the period’s anxiety about measuring up to its ideals, its efforts to discover the plenitude of ii natural laws and to live by them.
    [Show full text]
  • Mit Einer Logischen Kritik Der Mathematischen Logik Und Bibliographie Der Logik
    GRUNDRISS DER PYRAMIDALEN LOGIK mit einer logischen Kritik der mathematischen Logik und Bibliographie der Logik Lehrmaterialien aus dem Philosophischen Institut der HHU Düsseldorf Forschungsabteilung für Wissenschaftstheorie Prof. Dr. L. Geldsetzer A AB AC ABD Copyright 2000 vorbehalten Kopieren zum Studiengebrauch erlaubt 2 INHALTSVERZEICHNIS Vorbemerkung Zum Konzept der pyramidalen Logik 4 I. Einführung 4 II. Die logischen Elemente 20 1. Intensionen 20 2. Extensionen 21 3. Der Begriff 24 a. Die reguläreBegriffsstrukturDielogische a. 24 b. Negative Begriffe 25 c. Der widersprüchliche Begriff (contradictio in adiecto bzw. contradictio in terminis) 26 d. Der Dispositionsbegriff 30 e. Der Wahrscheinlichkeitsbegriff 32 f. Der Zahlbegriff 33 g. Sogenannte Relationsbegriffe, Ähnlichkeitsbegriffe und "Familienähnlichkeit" 44 h. Der Begriff des Begriffs in der stoischen Logik 47 i. Methoden der Begriffsbildung: Induktion, Deduktion, Analyse und Synthese 50 4. Die Junktoren 55 a. Die urteilsbildendenDie a.Junktoren 57 1. Die unbeschränkteDie (allgemeine)1.Implikation 57 2. Das unbeschränkte (allgemeine) "Zukommen" 58 3. Die korrelierende Implikation 58 4. Die Kopula bzw. die materiale Implikationmateriale 58Kopula die Diebzw. 4. 5. Das spezielle "Zukommen" bzw. die formale Implikation oder Inklusion 58 6. Die Negation 59 7. Der Existenz- bzw. Produktjunktorbzw.Existenz- Der 7. 59 b. Die ausdrucksbildendenDie b. Junktoren 61 1. Die QuantifikationDie 1. 62 2. Die ÄquivalenzDie 2. 63 3. Die unvollständigeDie Disjunktion3. 63 4. Die vollständige Disjunktion oder Alternative 63 5. Die AdjunktionDie 5. 64 c. Die mathematischenJunktorenDie c. 65 1. Die Summenbildung Die 1. (Additionsjunktor) 68 2. Die SubtraktionDie (Differenzenjunktor)2. 68 3. Die ProduktbildungDie 3. (Multiplikationsjunktor) 68 4. Die Division (Quotienten- oder Proportionsjunktor) 69 5. Die PotenzbildungDie (Potenzjunktor)5.
    [Show full text]
  • Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy. Volume 31, Winter 2006
    LIVING IN DOUBT: CARNEADES’ PITHANON RECONSIDERED SUZANNE OBDRZALEK I though the interpretation of ancient texts is inevitably di¶cult, Carneades presents what one might call a worst-case scenario. In the first place, he wrote nothing. To complicate matters, Carneades’ views were so obscure that his faithful disciple Clitomachus con- fessed that he could never figure out what Carneades actually be- lieved (Cic. Acad. 2. 139). Showing remarkable fortitude in the face of such an obstacle, Clitomachus, attempting to play Plato to Carneades’ Socrates, reportedly recorded Carneades’ teachings in 400 books (D.L. 4. 67). Not one remains. None the less, Clito- machus’ attempt to make a philosophy of Carneades’ anti-theoreti- cal stance was not a complete failure; Carneades had a tremendous influence on the later Academy as well as the Stoa, and his views (or lack thereof) have been handed down to us by both Sextus Em- piricus and Cicero. These sources are, however, problematic. As a Pyrrhonist, Sextus was critical of the Academy and may have ex- aggerated what he took to be Carneades’ dogmatism. Cicero, on the other hand, a student of Philo, was undoubtedly influenced in his interpretation of Carneades by his teacher’s dogmatic scepti- cism. Carneades is perhaps best known for proposing the pithan»e phantasia (probable impression) as a criterion for life. However, the status of his theory of the pithanon (probable) is completely unclear.1 Was it merely a dialectical move against the Stoic charge of apraxia (inaction)? Was it a theory that Carneades himself en- ã Suzanne Obdrzalek 2006 I would like to thank Alan Code, Tony Long, Julius Moravcsik, and David Sedley for their comments on this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Humor As Philosophical Subversion, Especially in the Skeptics
    Humor as Philosophical Subversion, Especially in the Skeptics Richard Bett 1. Introduction Aristotle is not exactly a comedian. He wrote about comedy in the lost second book of the Poetics, and, as discussed in another paper in this volume, he wrote about wittiness (εὐτραπελία) in his ethical works. But he does not exhibit much of either. What humor there is in Aristotle seems to fall into two main varieties. First, there is word-play that engages the reader’s attention, which can perhaps be seen as an instance of a technique he describes in Rhetoric 3.10, that of saying “smart things and things that create a good impression” (τὰ ἀστεῖα καὶ τὰ εὐδοκιµοῦντα, 1410b6).1 Early in the Nicomachean Ethics, he says that in endeavoring to determine the principles (ἀρχαί) of ethics, we should begin (ἀρκτέον) with things known to us (1095b2-4). A little later, introducing the idea of the function (ἔργον) of a human being, he asks whether we can seriously consider that a human being as such (as opposed to people in various occupations) is ἀργόν (1097b28- 30) – which is intentionally ambiguous between “without function” and “lazy.” In De Caelo, introducing the topic of minimal magnitudes, he says that positing such a minimal magnitude (τοὐλάχιστον) will make the biggest difference (τὰ µέγιστα) in mathematics (271b10-11). And in De Interpretatione, discussing names, he says that “non-human 1 Unless otherwise noted, translations are my own. In the case of Timon, I sometimes draw on translations in Bett 2000 and Bett 2015. In the case of Sextus I generally draw on Bett 1997, Bett 2005, and Bett 2012.
    [Show full text]
  • Lucan's Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek a Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulf
    Lucan’s Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Washington 2014 Reading Committee: Catherine Connors, Chair Alain Gowing Stephen Hinds Program Authorized to Offer Degree: Classics © Copyright 2014 Laura Zientek University of Washington Abstract Lucan’s Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek Chair of the Supervisory Committee: Professor Catherine Connors Department of Classics This dissertation is an analysis of the role of landscape and the natural world in Lucan’s Bellum Civile. I investigate digressions and excurses on mountains, rivers, and certain myths associated aetiologically with the land, and demonstrate how Stoic physics and cosmology – in particular the concepts of cosmic (dis)order, collapse, and conflagration – play a role in the way Lucan writes about the landscape in the context of a civil war poem. Building on previous analyses of the Bellum Civile that provide background on its literary context (Ahl, 1976), on Lucan’s poetic technique (Masters, 1992), and on landscape in Roman literature (Spencer, 2010), I approach Lucan’s depiction of the natural world by focusing on the mutual effect of humanity and landscape on each other. Thus, hardships posed by the land against characters like Caesar and Cato, gloomy and threatening atmospheres, and dangerous or unusual weather phenomena all have places in my study. I also explore how Lucan’s landscapes engage with the tropes of the locus amoenus or horridus (Schiesaro, 2006) and elements of the sublime (Day, 2013).
    [Show full text]
  • Simplicius on the Reality of Relations and Relational Change
    Created on 24 June 2009 at 9.31 hours page 245 SIMPLICIUS ON THE REALITY OF RELATIONS AND RELATIONAL CHANGE ORNA HARARI the ancient commentators’ approach to Aristotle’s account of relatives in Categories 7 is shaped by the conception that prevailed in later antiquity, in which relatives are composites of a substrate, i.e. an attribute that belongs to the other categories, and a relation.1 Simplicius shares this conception with the other commentators, but he formulates it in di·erent terms. He calls the substrate on which relational attributes supervene a di·erence (διαφορ) or a character (χαρακτρ) and the supervening relational attribute an inclination (πνευσις).2 In this study I attempt to clarify the significance of this terminology, arguing that through the notion of inclination Simplicius answers the question of the unity of Aristotle’s category of relatives, as formulated in Plotinus’ Ennead 6. 1. 6–9. To ex- ã Orna Harari 2009 1 Porph. In Cat. 114. 13–14; Ammon. In Cat. 69. 24–6; Olymp. In Cat. 98. 21–2; and Elias, In Cat. 205. 9–11 (all references to these commentators are to Busse’s edition in CAG 4/1–3, 4/4, 12/1, and 18/1 respectively). This view goes back to Aristotle (Metaph. 1088A21–B4) and is held by other thinkers, such as Andronicus of Rhodes (ap. Elias, In Cat. 201. 18–23) and Galen (Di·. puls. 2. 6, viii. 594. 10–17 Kuhn).• 2 Simpl. In Cat. 167. 29–35 Kalbfleisch (all further references are to Kalbfleisch’s edition in CAG 8).
    [Show full text]
  • Mythologies and Partisan Constructions of the Good Philosopher in Plato
    Article Hic Sunt Leones: Mythologies and Partisan Constructions of the Good Philosopher in Plato Sergio Alloggio https://orcid.org/0000-0002-7273-3954 University of Pretoria [email protected] Abstract Plato constructs the philosopher in contrast to the sophist. Both sophistical and rhetorical logos, in their epistemic closeness to philosophical logos, require a constant act of demarcation throughout Plato’s works. The challenge posed by the sophists creates a structural, instable tension in several Platonic dialogues. Why is the Athenian philosopher obsessed by a different yet comparable approach to virtue, knowledge and social order? Why does the Athenian philosopher need and, at the same time, reject the sophist when it comes to shaping his own self-image? To try to answer these questions, I will go back to a foundational moment where the Platonic philosopher is theoretically constructed and conceptually produced against the sophist, namely, Plato’s Sophist, Statesman, Protagoras, Gorgias and Phaedrus. The aim of the article is to show how the Platonic philosopher is conveniently defined through a series of partisan demarcations grounded on ontological privilege, epistemic exclusion, ethical circularity and, ultimately, political delegitimation. Keywords: Plato; dialectic; demarcation; partisanship; sophistics; agonistics; delegitimation Decolonization was the preoccupation of two [T]he unconscious has first and foremost to do with groups that propelled the nationalist movement: the grammar … This also has a bit to do, or much to intelligentsia and the political class. They set out to do, or everything to do, with repetition, that is, create the nation, the former to give the with the aspect that is entirely the opposite of what independent state a history and the latter to create a a dictionary is used for … Grammar and repetition common citizenship as the basis of national constitute a completely different aspect from what sovereignty.
    [Show full text]