CHAPTER 3:__Defining Income And Growth

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

CHAPTER 3:__Defining Income And Growth

THE INCOME OF NATIONS: MEASUREMENT WITH (WHAT?) THEORY

Michael Harris Agricultural and Resource Economics University of Sydney [email protected]

Environmental Economics Network workshop Australian National University, May 2005

Abstract

Extensive activity is underway to revise the construction and measurement of national income statistics. This revision activity is largely motivated by concerns about environmental quality, resource use and the long run sustainability of development paths. However, the underlying definitions of income are not settled. At the broadest level, there is a conflict between income as an economic concept (consumption- related, intertemporal) and an accounting concept (output-related, atemporal). More specifically, the distinction between ex ante income (maintainable consumption) and ex post income (actual consumption plus capital accumulation) is often blurred, for example. This raises the issue of the rationale for including capital in measures of income, and the possible interpretations of such measures as “returns to wealth”.

In the paper, two distinct rationales for adding capital to consumption in an economically meaningful measure are identified—future consumption postponed versus current consumption foregone, which differ due to the effect of diminishing returns in production—and argue that they lead to two distinct interpretations of income: the stationary-equivalent of future consumption interpretation versus the stationary-state-equivalent interpretation. I argue that the choice of one or other of these interpretations has implications for a raft of national accounting issues, such as the treatment of capital gains, the concept of natural capital, the pricing of investment goods, and the treatment of technological change. Moreover, it is important to understand the different perspectives in order to properly resolve differences between recommendations for expanding the accounts as presented by national accountants and by economists. The conclusion, that there is not one overriding concept or measure of income, is emphasised.

1 Contents:

1. Introduction

2. Preliminaries

3. Income and Growth: Key Themes 3.1 National accounting themes 3.2 Economic themes 3.3 Growth themes

4. Income: A Confusion of Definitions 4.1 Terminology 4.2 From personal income to national income 4.3 Relating the themes of income to each other

5. Income and Capital Goods 5.1 Why include capital in income? 5.2 The growth-theoretic approach 5.3 The atemporal perspective 5.3.1 Examples of “Atemporal perspective” models with investment 5.3.2 Discussion 5.4 Summary

6. Empirical Implications 6.1 Capital theoretic controversies a) Technical change b) Capital gains c) Natural capital 6.2 Other controversies

7. Conclusions (followed by Appendix and References)

2 1. Introduction

“Income is a series of events.” Irving Fisher.1

When Adam Smith wrote the Wealth of Nations, long regarded as the starting point of modern economics, distinctions between wealth and income were not well understood. Only much more recently has there been a clear understanding and acceptance of the underlying stock/flow distinction that characterises modern discussions of income and wealth at both the personal and the social level. National income—the definition and systematic measurement thereof through organised national accounts—has been one of the great practical innovations of twentieth century economics.

This innovation is still in progress. Revising the national accounts, or discussing how they should be revised, is a major ongoing activity. The System of National Accounts, or SNA, has been revised from its 1968 standard and is undergoing further revision (United Nations 1993, 1998). Individual nations are engaging in accounting exercises designed to extend the scope and coverage of their accounting systems in line with the evolving SNA (Oakley 1996; Nordhaus 1999, 2000). Academic and other economists are engaged in conceptual work and case studies of particular countries, so as to compare time paths of standard economic growth measures with adjusted measures (Usher 1980, Eisner 1988, Scott 1989, Nordhaus 1995, and see the overview in Harris and Fraser 2002), and preparing detailed theoretical treatises on the meaning and computation of such adjustments (Aronsson, Johansen and Lofgren 1997, Brekke 1997, Hartwick 2000, Perrings and Vincent 2003, Weitzman 2003).

In the first half of the twentieth century, particularly during the decades of the Depression and Second World War, there was a similar degree of intensity in the debates and activity concerning national accounting and national income in particular. Key luminaries in the profession (including Fisher, Lindahl, Hicks, Pigou, and Hayek) debated the proper notion of income, and its relationship to capital.2 Keynes published

1 Fisher (1930), quoted in Parker and Harcourt (1969), p.33. 2 See the collection edited by Parker and Harcourt (1969).

3 his General Theory (Keynes 1936) exploring the link between aggregate demand and national income. Experts such as Meade, Stone and Clark began constructing the first recognisable national income and expenditure accounts (again, see Parker and Harcourt 1969). There were active debates on definitions, measurements and interpretations.

One might expect as a result of this pioneering work that the current activity and debates are essentially “at the margins”—that core ideas of national income are settled, and that what is still unsettled is how best to extend these core ideas into new areas: technological change, environmental damage, natural resource use, leisure time and so on.

This, however, turns out not to be the case. The purpose of this paper is to show that the area of extended accounting remains heavily contested terrain, as it was in the 1930s and 1940s. The difference now is that there is an expectation that the profession should know what it is talking about by now; this means that the controversies are confronted less explicitly than they once were. Key concepts are assumed to be clear even when, on inspection, it turns out they are not. Key differences in definitions and assumptions are not well appreciated. The neophyte scholar in the extended national accounting field would be well justified in feeling lost in a welter of competing approaches, making estimates hard to compare or interpret.

In this paper I outline the varying ways in which national income is defined, particularly contrasting the ways in which national accountants view it compared to economists. I identify how terminology and its connection to an underlying theoretical framework has become confused between various users, with different concepts of income being misleadingly conflated. I identify two different conceptual approaches to accounting for capital goods, one of which reflects the atemporal emphasis of national accounting practice and one of which reflects the intertemporal focus of economic theory. I explore the implications of each of these for extended accounting. I then examine how different authors have drawn on particular assumptions to reach conclusions about how income should be measured, and the empirical implications of these assumptions. I include some comments about the ongoing revisions of the System of National Accounts here too.

4 2. Preliminaries Before proceeding into a discussion of practicalities of national accounting and national income measurement, some groundwork needs to be covered. Firstly, what is the simplest static representation we can present of what is an inherently dynamic concept? Secondly, what interpretation, or interpretations, can be put on both this simple representation, and on more complex measures of national income, broadly defined?

To tackle the first problem, assume a simple one period, two good economy. It possesses a technology for producing each of the two goods, subject to the usual diminishing returns. We can represent this simple world in Figure 1. The bowed out curve represents production possibilities in a standard two good economy in a single accounting period. The diagonal line AD shows relative prices between the two goods

C1 and C2, given by the social optimum at the point of tangency. If the two goods are consumption goods then the interpretation is straightforward. Using C1 as the numeraire, OA gives national income in C1–equivalent units. We have derived a meaningful atemporal measure of social welfare (in this simple example at least).

5 C1

A

B

C1*

C2

C2* D

Figure 1

6 In fact, we can argue that the national income as measured by OA admits of two interpretations. First, on the “production” side, by adding up physical units using the common denominator of the market price ratio (shown here as the marginal rate of transformation), the magnitude OA equals the value of the economy’s output in this period. Second, on the “consumption” side, by adding up the units using the marginal rate of substitution (from the indifference curve, not shown, but assumed to be tangential to the production frontier BD, at the point (C1*, C2*)), OA gives the welfare interpretation already alluded to.

Why do the output and welfare interpretations coincide in this representation of the world? Because only two things matter (consumption of goods 1 and 2, respectively), and because rates of substitution and transformation are the same. In other words, this is a first-best world. Market prices are optimal, all utility-generating goods are included in the index, there are no externalities, and so on. Allow these assumptions to change to better reflect reality, and the interpretations part company. (This is distinct from the index number issues that arise in the measurement of economic growth where changes in productivity and in welfare, in the Fisherian “series of events” sense, will be measured differently: see the next section.)

There is something of a paradox here, in that it is partly the understanding that the world is not a first-best one, and that key assumptions that would make an output measure coincide with a welfare one are violated, that has motivated attempts to revise accounting procedures such as in the so-called “natural resource accounting” field. However, the more rigorous the investigation into how to construct and interpret an ideal index, the more difficult it is to work in a framework that does not rely on optimising foundations. (This has led to an odd situation in the technical literature on extended accounting, in which inherently first-best models are used to derive accounting procedures for applications in the nth-best real world. Models of this nature are discussed in Section 5.2.)

This static, consumption-only framework also does not allow us to investigate the inherently dynamic concept of income. In particular, while we can think about output and welfare in this context, we cannot systematically investigate questions about capital formation and sustainable consumption, because this model is not designed to

7 look at feasible consumption paths over time. Bringing in capital goods necessarily introduces dynamic considerations, but also necessarily complicates the analysis. Issues surrounding the inclusion of capital goods in an index of national income are the subject of Section 5.

However, while we cannot utilise this simple model to analyse some dynamic issues, we can use it to help define some key concepts. In particular, introducing dynamic considerations raises issues of “sustainability”. An obvious way to define sustainability here is to assume that consumption bundle (C1*, C2*) can be consumed in every subsequent period. This is, by assumption, a simple steady state model in which the capital stock, labour force and technology that generate output are assumed constant, so that the production possibility frontier BD does not change. (Implicitly, neither do preferences, since they define (C1*, C2*) to be the optimal consumption choice.)

This is a straightforward definition of sustainability—maintenance of consumption flows over time. A slightly broader condition might be that consumption bundles may change, but sustainability requires non-declining aggregate utility. In more complex growth models, sustainability may be defined in terms of either (restrictions on) changes in instantaneous utility, or, as we shall see, on more generalised present-value utility measures. But to be able to analyse sustainability issues more effectively, we will have to move to dynamic models that allow for capital accumulation.

However, this simple example of a static (or steady-state) economy has helped identify the key issues of interest. National income is firstly a measure of output. Other interpretations that might be put on an index of income is (i) a measure of welfare or well being, and (ii) an indicator of sustainable consumption. These three alternatives—output, welfare, sustainability—will be motivating themes of the foregoing discussion. In this simple framework, all three interpretations coincide. As the model becomes more complex, the definitions part company. How to deal with the fact that the definitions diverge is our task to follow.

3. Income and Growth: Key Themes

8 Having focussed on a simple atemporal representation of the world, what happens when one moves into more dynamic concepts of national income in which capital accumulation is taking place? Any discussion of national accounting procedures—and their appropriateness and adequacy for their stated purposes—should be based on a coherent and well-defined conception of income. One might expect that such a fundamental concept in economics as income would be well defined and well understood within the discipline. This is, however, not the case. Here we will present alternative views of income in terms of key “themes”: by themes we mean something more general than definitions, but as shall be seen later, starting with specific definitions would make things messier rather than clearer.

3.1 National Accounting Themes The first key theme we explore—national income as an accounting construct—is in fact the way most beginning economists are exposed to the idea of national income. That is, we usually first see national income as it arises within the model of the circular flow of income presented in introductory macroeconomics textbooks.

Viewing income in this way has certain implications. Income is that flow of money generated by current production of new final goods and services. It is a standard part of national accounting practice that income arises from current production: the notion of the circular flow is as an accounting identity that links the value of sales from production (and total value added associated with the generation of that output) to the total income earned as a result of generating that production.

The form that national income—gross domestic product (GDP)3—takes from the accounting perspective is the familiar GDP = C + I. This expression can be extended in obvious ways to separately account for the government sector and for trade, but in general we can think of income as the sum of current consumption and gross capital accumulation: appropriate adjustments to the investment term would leave us with an expression for net product (NDP) instead.

3 This is a measure based on the value of production, rather than incomes to factors (“Gross National Income”), but it is due to the accounting identities that the national accounts are constructed upon that measuring one is equivalent to measuring the other.

9 This notion of income as arising from production, and being defined in terms of an accounting identity, turns out to be of major significance when contemplating how it should be adjusted, particularly at the official SNA level. The components of income, in particular consumption and investment, must be appropriately defined so as to match the value of income as earned by the nation’s citizens. As a result, consumption and production “boundaries” are drawn around the appropriate flows so as to keep them consistent in accounting terms with the income being generated.

To sum up income from the accounting perspective:  National income reflects the value of current production;  The “circular flow” accounting identity is the basis for both classification and measurement in the national accounts;  The components of income must be appropriately defined in order to preserve the accounting identity upon which income is defined (in practice, this means that the measured components are restricted to those falling within the market sector);  Income is largely a historical, or atemporal, construct, looking at “what has just happened”. There is no explicit dynamic interpretation to be placed on the measure produced.

3.2 Economic Themes If national accountants think of income as being generated by production and defined in terms of an accounting identity, is there a contrasting way in which economists instinctively think of it? If there is one thing common in the economics literature it is the theme of income as a return to wealth: or, perhaps more precisely, to a stock of capital. Various definitions of income as a return to wealth are possible, but we will identify two key themes:  Income as the sum of consumption plus the change in wealth;  Income as a maintainable level of consumption.

The first of these derives from the public finance literature. Bradford (1990) labels it the Schanz-Haig-Simons (SHS) measure of income, and we shall as well (although we shall see that other labels may be applied).

10 What the SHS concept has in common with the accounting version of income is the structure they share: both involve adding actual consumption to changes in wealth or to capital accumulation. We expand on the detailed differences in a later section. For now we shall make the observation that the boundaries around the consumption and investment terms in the national accounts are defined to make them consistent with the overriding accounting identity. For economic interpretations the boundaries are drawn more to make the income measure consistent with some sort of return to wealth interpretation. To keep this distinction clear we denote the expression for this theme ˙ of income now as YSHS  C  K , where we use K˙ instead of I to make clear that the change in the capital stock we are interested here may not be the same as the output of investment goods counted in conventional GDP or NDP.

The key alternative theme of income that is explored here often appears in the economics literature associated with Fisher (1930) and Hicks (1946). Instead of treating income as an accounting concept, something to be constructed empirically, income is regarded as the answer to a thought experiment about how much can be consumed without future impoverishment. While there are variations on this theme, some of which will be explored below, the key point is that income is now synonymous with consumption rather than being a combination of consumption and investment (or wealth change).

Bradford (1990, p. 1183) distinguishes between these two themes of income by describing one as a backward-looking measure (SHS income)—asking “How much did we produce last year?”—and the other as a forward-looking measure (which we shall refer to as Hicksian income, as Bradford does)—asking “At what rate are we able to produce value?”4

4 Again, the SHS measure shares an empirical and historical approach with the national accounting circular flow construct. However, one of the key differences between the philosophy underlying national accounting calculations of GDP, and how economists use and interpret the SHS expression is that the accountants intend their measure to be historical—a measure of the economy’s productive capacity, and by extension, a measure of its income-generating capacity, with the income being what is generated by that production—while economists instinctively seek to generate a measure that is in some sense more broadly interpretable and more forward-looking. This tension that arises from using historical data to generate predictive measures is a feature of the economic literature on national income, and a key theme of this paper.

11 It is important to stress again that we are talking of themes rather than definitions of income. The subtleties of Hicksian definitions of income, for example, will be expanded upon in the following section. For now, within what Bradford calls “Hicksian” income above, two obvious sub-themes are prominent in the literature. One involves explicitly specifying income as that amount of consumption that does not diminish future consumption. In this sense, seeing income as a return to wealth involves defining wealth as the capitalised value of future consumption (Hicks talked of “receipts”). The second sub-theme involves trying to approximate the first by defining income as that amount of consumption that keeps wealth constant. In national accounting terms, wealth here refers to a measurable capital stock.

C˙ ˙ In formal notation, we can write the first of these as YHicks  maxC(t) s.t. C  0,t ,

K˙ ˙ and the second as YHicks  maxC(t) s.t. K  0,t . In Nordhausian terminology—see Nordhaus (1994)—these are, respectively, a “consumption annuity” measure of income and a “capital intact” measure.

In simple models there is a neat duality to these Hicksian sub-themes. Defining income as maximal non-declining consumption implies (in certain circumstances) constant wealth. Defining income as that consumption consistent with constant wealth, in turn, implies constant consumption. Income is precisely measured as a return to wealth. Complicate the model—or the world that is being represented by the model—and this duality breaks down. The first (the consumption annuity measure) is the conceptual ideal, while the second (the capital intact measure) is a measurable approximation, at least in principle.

As a result of this elegant duality, these two appear often in discussions of income; sometimes in ways that suggest they are interchangeable. But the second is an approximation to the first; in a national accounting context, a dictum to maintain wealth is really an admonition to not consume one’s capital. This may or may not be equivalent to maintaining consumption possibilities, an issue explored further below.

These economic income themes have obvious return-to-wealth interpretations. But how do they relate to the criteria of welfare and sustainability, which have been

12 highlighted as key criteria which extended accounting aggregates should better measure? Clearly, Hicks was motivated by issues of sustainability, and hence all the measures associated with what we have labelled Hicksian income themes are approximations to a measure of sustainability, or at least are intended to be. Can they also be interpreted as measures of welfare?

The Hicksian ex ante measures define income as consumption so they are welfare- related by definition. One case in which a precise welfare interpretation is admissible is the steady state case in which there is a consumption annuity flowing from a

C˙ K˙ constant stock of capital; that is, where YHicks  YHicks . In this situation, consumption (income) clearly measures maximum sustainable welfare. That is, it captures sustainability and welfare in a single measure. Once the economy moves from this steady state, we may be able to approximately measure sustainability by including capital accumulation, or else aim for a welfare measure by limiting the focus to consumption. But only in the strict constant consumption steady state do we get a measure that accurately captures both.

There is a literature in which income expressions of the YSHS form admit of an intertemporal welfare interpretation, and this will be covered in Section 5.2.

3.3 Growth Themes Things get yet more complex once the (sometimes) neglected issue of index numbers is raised. To seriously measure economic growth requires the comparison of income at various points in time. An approximate approach—one consistent with national accounting practice—is to measure the value of output at two points in time and adjust for price changes. This measures the value of output using (typically) base period prices. However, Usher (1980, 1994) reminds us that a meaningful measure of growth arises as the answer to a thought experiment, and the “change in real income” measure is at best a rough estimate of more precisely defined growth measures. This argument is, again, due to Hicks (1940).

What are the thought experiments of interest? There are also at least two distinct concepts of what is being measured by the concept of “growth”, even in a simple

13 model with only consumption—no saving or investment—and no inflation (but allowing for relative price changes). The first measure of growth is a measure of the welfare change arising from a different production/consumption bundle. The second measures the change in the economy’s productive capacity.5

The issue of multiple goods has not been explicitly dealt with in our discussions of dynamic measures of income thus far: once we allow for more than one consumption good, we are led to the important index number issues that require a detailed discussion of growth definition and measurement. As expounded by Hicks (1940), and by Usher (1980, 1994), statistics of real consumption track changes over time in the location of the production possibility curve (when measuring changes in productive capacity), or movements of the bundle of goods consumed through the space of assumedly invariant indifference curves (when measuring welfare).6

Figure 2 shows the two growth measures, in comparison to a “money growth” measure in which no normalisation of prices is undertaken. Between two consecutive periods “1” and “2”, technological change (or resource discoveries) result in a shift outward of the production possibilities boundary. Points of tangency with a social indifference curve indicate the social optimum in each accounting period. Using the relative price defined by that tangency, we derive money income in each period (YM1

7 and YM2) as per Figure 1.

5 This distinction was first made clearly by Hicks (1940), in his discussion of market-price vs factor- cost measures of income. 6 A whole host of index number and measurement issues regarding welfare, income and output are presented in Hill (2000), including the divergence between changes in real income and welfare over time when tastes are not assumed invariant. We do not pursue those issues further here. 7 Readers should note that the diagram indicates the importance of the choice of numeraire. In this example, money income increases notably when good 1 is chosen (as shown) but if good 2 were chosen, income in the scenario shown would not change.

14 C1 YP2

YU2

YM2

YM1=YU1 =YP1

U1 U2

C1*

PPF1 PPF2

C2

C2* D

Figure 2

15 However, as has been indicated, defining a meaningful measure of growth as opposed to income generally requires the specification of a set of reference prices. (Standard practice is to choose the relative price from the base year.) Given this, we construct the productivity measure YPi for any year i, to represent the largest value of goods that could be obtained with the technology in that year. Similarly, YUi in year i represents the value of the cheapest bundle of goods at the given reference prices that would leave the representative consumer as well off as s/he actually is in that year. The rate of growth of either measure is then simply the difference between the measured value in two periods divided by the value in the initial period, that is:

(YP2 – YP1)/ YP1 and (YU2 – YU1)/ YU1

Note also that the use of reference prices is not an issue of inflation adjustment, in which nominal magnitudes are converted to real ones for purposes of comparison. Here, attention is paid to a reference relative price, rather than a reference set of nominal prices. But inflation-adjustment—in which the period 1 relative-price line runs through through the actual consumption bundle chosen in period 2—is in fact the “approximate” real growth figure that would be measured in actuality.

What of introducing capital goods into the problem? This adds a whole set of extra measurement and interpretation issues that shall be covered in Section 5.

4. Income: A Confusion of Definitions In this section we examine how the themes of income presented in the previous section relate to specific definitions used in the literature. In particular, we identify a slipperiness in terminology, one that can be a barrier to constructive engagement between analysts. We highlight the important—but under-recognised—differences in perspective that result by considering income at the national rather than personal level. Then we attempt to carefully compare and contrast the particular definitions.

As already outlined in the previous section, multiple definitions of income and growth exist in the economics and national accounting literature. In this section we explore these definitions, and try and resolve some of the resulting confusion and ambiguity, and highlight both the differences, and the connections, between particular definitions.

16 4.1 Terminology It is hard for analysts to discuss and debate how to define and measure income when there is no agreed terminology to use for the various concepts. Two alternative but standard concepts or themes of income in the economics literature have already been stressed in the foregoing, one being the accounting-based measure labelled here as SHS income, and the other being the consumption-based Hicksian measure. But how do these themes relate to the definitions individual economists employ in their discussions of national income? The answers get a little complicated.

Hicks states that the “purpose of income calculations in practical affairs is to give people an indication of the amount which they can consume without impoverishing themselves” (p.172). Hence the use of this notion as a key common theme in Hicks’ discussion of income. But within this theme, if we ask what did Hicks actually define income to be, his definitions are numerous and context specific. For example, his Income No.1 is “thus the maximum amount which can be spent during a period if there is to be an expectation of maintaining intact the capital value of prospective receipts” (p.173); in other words, the keep-wealth-constant dictum, where wealth is explicitly forward-looking. Allowing for changing interest rates, Hicks’ Income No. 2 is “the maximum amount the individual can spend this week, and still expect to be able to spend the same amount in each ensuing week.” (p.174). Here, Hicks has moved from one “Hicksian sub-theme” (constant wealth) to the other (non-declining consumption). Consideration of price changes leads him to define Income No. 3, which “must be defined as the maximum amount of money which the individual can spend this week, and still expect to be able to spend the same amount in real terms in each ensuing week.” (p.174, emphasis in original.) Durable consumption goods add an extra degree of complication, forcing him “back on the central criterion”, of being as well off after as before. “By considering the approximations to this criterion, we have come to see how very complex it is, how unattractive it looks when subjected to detailed analysis.” (p.176.)

This negativity about accurate measurement of the central concept pervades Hicks’ writing.

17 “It seems to follow that any one who seeks to make a statistical calculation of social income is confronted with a dilemma. The income he can calculate is not the true income he seeks; the income he seeks cannot be calculated. From this dilemma there is only one way out; it is of course the way that has to be taken in practice.” (Hicks 1946, p.178.)

(Modern writers on the subject often seem, it must be said, rather more sanguine about these difficulties.)

Finally, he concludes by discussing “the way that has to be taken in practice”: he observes that these measures are conceptual ones, ex ante measures of income, unmeasurable in general circumstances. The compromise measure he presents, the ex post approximation to the desired measure (in this case, Income No. 1), is consumption plus capital accumulation: that is, a measure indistinguishable from the SHS measure defined above. And this accounting procedure “can only result in a statistical estimate; by its very nature, it is not the measurement of an economic quantity.” (p.179.)

The strong impression that can be drawn from Hicks’ discussion of income in Value and Capital is that he is at pains to distinguish between income as an economic concept, an answer to a question about how much can be consumed, and income as an accounting construct, a measured account of what has occurred that can only ever approximate the economic magnitude he refers to as the “central concept”. He goes to some lengths to identify different ways in the economic question and answer can be specified, depending on circumstances, and that different variants of the ex post formulation will correspond to the particular ex ante version.

Unfortunately, the result has not been a recognition that there is a series of Hicksian incomes, thematically linked but differing in details; instead there is an almost arbitrary use of the term “Hicksian income” in the literature to denote a number of different income concepts or measures, leading Bradford to refer to a “confusion in professional thinking on this subject” (Bradford, 1990, p.1183). This remark came in the context of an exchange between Eisner (1990), Scott (1990) and Bradford (1990) on extended accounting and the measures underlying the accounting exercises. Eisner

18 conflates the ex ante constant consumption definition with the ex post capital maintenance definition—he refers to it as the “Hicks-Haig-Simons” definition—a position both Bradford and Scott take issue with. However, Eisner is not alone: in fact, this mixing up of the two definitions is common practice in the economics profession. For example, Aronsson, Johansson and Lofgren (1997, pp. 95-6) state “(Hicks and Lindahl both) defined income as the maximum amount you can consume and still keep the capital intact (interest on the capital). Intuitively, it equals current consumption plus net capital accumulation since, as long as net investment is kept non-negative, the capital is held intact.”8

This tendency to blur the different income concepts is presumably attributable to the fact that all of these interpretations are variations on the concept of income as a return to wealth, the predominant theme in economic discussions of income. Yet they all part ways when the fine details are examined. Bringing them together as a singular concept, rather than related concepts, over-simplifies Hicks’ careful reasoning: he was interested, first and foremost, in maintaining consumption possibilities. This raises two caveats with respect to the above position. Firstly, keeping capital intact satisfies a non-declining consumption rule in particular circumstances but not universally, as Hicks recognised. Secondly, even assuming intact capital is sufficient, the “intuitive” step they then make is between Hicks’ ex ante ideal measure, and the ex post approximation. They are not identical: the relationship between these is followed up in subsection 4.3.9

Nordhaus (1995) adopts yet another terminological position. As with Eisner and Aronsson et al, his definition of the label “Hicksian” is a combination of Hicks’s ex ante Income No. 1 (maintaining capital intact) with his ex post approximation of this measure being the sum of consumption plus capital accumulation;10 in this regard he adopts a quite conventional position. But where these other authors argue (implicitly or otherwise) that this measure is designed to represent a constant consumption measure, or at least an approximation to one, Nordhaus takes a different view. For

8 See also the discussion of income in Hartwick and Hagemen (1993). 9 Further difficulties arise in their interpretation once heterogeneous capital and technological change are introduced. Some discussion of measurement and interpretive issues concerning technical change appear later in the paper. 10 See his quote on p.3 (Nordhaus 1995) in which he combines two different definitions of income from Hicks’ book.

19 him, this formulation of “Hicksian income” serves as a production-based measure of income, much in the way Bradford attributed this characteristic to SHS income. Nordhaus then describes an alternative utility-based or sustainable-consumption measure of income, and attributes it to Fisher rather than Hicks. (While Nordhaus acknowledges that Hicks’ Income No. 3 is similar, he maintains a labelling practice whereby he substitutes Hicksian for SHS, and Fisherian for Hicksian, in the above terminology.)

In other words, Nordhaus regards Hicks’ ex ante and ex post definitions regarding Income No. 1 as being essentially equivalent. In the terminology being used here, the

K˙ capital-intact Hicksian income YHicks is (i) interchangeable with the YSHS measure, and (ii) it is a productivity-oriented measure with its roots in national accounting practice and hence unrelated to sustainability measurement. This second component is an eclectic interpretation. Other authors explicitly write in these terms in order to address sustainability themes. For Nordhaus, it is what he calls Fisherian income—the

C˙ consumption-annuity measure we have labelled YHicks —that is of interest in the context of sustainability. How does he distinguish the two in practice, given Hicks’ scepticism regarding the measurement of true sustainable consumption? Nordhaus conceptually bases his Fisherian measure on a growth model presented by Weitzman (1976) (this model will be discussed in detail in Section 5.2, including its relevance as a sustainability measure); empirically it is distinguished by having a much broader measure of capital than the produced capital measure used in the national accounts, or some narrowly defined extensions to it. Most importantly in Nordhaus’s eyes is knowledge capital (capitalised technical change).

The end result of this selective review of labelling practices in the literature is, quite clearly, that there exists a confusion in terminology that exacerbates a confusion in conceptual clarity, and leads to inconsistent methods and interpretations. At one extreme is the strict national accounting measure GDP = C + I, and at the other extreme is an economic measure based on Hicks’ “central criterion”, which is

C˙ ˙ formally defined here as YHicks  maxC(t) s.t. C  0,t . The difficult and contested area is virtually everywhere in between. Economists writing on national income

20 definition and measurement move somewhat arbitrarily from these extremes to the

K˙ varieties of compromise measures we have labelled YHicks and YSHS , choosing their own labels and specific emphases on what should be included and how the resulting measures should be interpreted.

4.2 From Personal Income to National Income Definitions and concepts are affected by the degree of aggregation involved. The circular flow version of income is explicitly a measure of aggregate income. By contrast, the economic themes were explored initially as measures of income for an individual. This distinction has important implications. There are definitional issues and aggregation issues that arise once one moves from the individual level to the social level. Bos (1997) has argued forcefully that national accounting practice and economic principles operate in different directions: while they use similar terminology and what may look like similar conceptual apparatus, the interpretations and applications of these terms and tools can often be significantly different from one to the other. One reason he argues these discrepancies have arisen is that economists started out thinking about how to define income for an individual, then generalised this reasoning to the national level. In doing so, they impose their reasoning of what income should be a measure of, onto the national accountants’ conception of what national income is a measure of.

The Schanz-Haig-Simons formulation of income (consumption plus the change in wealth) is essentially a public finance concept in origin, with income being defined as a basis for taxation. The intuition here is that income is the accretion to a person’s wealth, regardless of how it is then used (Musgrave and Musgrave 1982, Ch.16). The intent, in this literature, is to define income as the base for personal taxation, and in that regard “All accretion should be included, whether it be regular or fluctuating, expected or unexpected, realized or unrealised.” (Musgrave and Musgrave 1982, p.344.)

While national income identities are structured along similar lines, being the sum of consumption items and investment items, national accounting practice draws boundaries around consumption and production activities that may not match how

21 they are drawn for personal taxation purposes. Moreover, while “all accretions should be included” in personal income as a tax base, what constitutes capital in the national accounts is considerably different. At the personal level, SHS income involves adding consumption to an individual’s change in wealth, while at the national level it refers to the change in a country’s capital stock. In the first instance, as already noted, the public finance principle is to include all accretions in income; at the national accounting level, it is orthodox practice to exclude all anticipated capital gains.11

Once we move into examining Hicksian themes, we find further difficulties in translating the concept(s) from the personal to the social level. In particular, the

K˙ relationship between the capital-constant version YHicks and the consumption-annuity

C˙ version YHicks changes with the level of analysis. There are several reasons for this. First, what is the “capital” being held constant in each case? Hicks writes of “the capital value of prospective receipts” as we saw in the discussion of terminology. This is essentially a partial equilibrium perspective, where the receipts themselves can be regarded in the first instance as essentially exogenous, with the total capital value only being influenced by consumption decisions. At the macro level, the value of capital is endogenous (at the margin as well as in the aggregate), as is the rate of return.

Nordhaus (1994) raises the issue of differing time horizons at each level, noting that with the finite time horizon of the individual (as opposed to the infinite time horizon that can be assumed in the first instance for a nation or society), the individual’s final period consumption (income) must just equal their wealth.12 However, that observation itself does not isolate the problem in switching perspectives.

11 In part, this reflects the shift to general equilibrium considerations implied by considering income at a national scale: a capital gain accruing to me can be realised by me acting in isolation in the year in which it occurs, and therefore represents a change in my immediate consumption possibilities (personal income). However, if the stock market booms during a year and personal incomes increase for all shareholders, they cannot all realise the capital gains simultaneously without driving the asset values back down. Thus, the capital gains do not represent an immediate increase in consumption possibilities to the nation. Moreover there are aggregation issues: in a closed economy, if gains to me come at the expense of someone else, gains at the individual level thus represent transfers at the national level. This is taken up in Section 6.1 (part b).

12 It can be thought of the following way. The final period’s consumption entails consumption of all remaining wealth. With consumption in all periods equal, this means that consumption in each period before the last will involve some combination of “pure harvest” and “capital consumption”, with capital consumption increasing over time and harvest reducing to zero in the final, but aggregate consumption for the individual remaining constant.

22 If we think of wealth as a stock to be drawn upon, and to which there is a given rate of return, the appropriate consumption-annuity income in this instance would involve a degree of capital consumption in each period. With constancy and complete certainty over the lifetime, a consumption annuity would be computed for the entire length of the individual’s life, with the final period’s income consisting entirely of capital consumption, as Nordhaus noted. But why this matters is that it breaks the symmetry

K˙ at every point in time between the capital-intact measure YHicks and the consumption-

C˙ 13 annuity measure YHicks .

4.3 Relating the Themes of Income to Each Other The previous subsection contained some suggestions as to how various measures of income may be related to one another, and how strong that relationship may be. We address the relationships between alternative measures more precisely here.

The initial definition of income introduced was the one arising from the circular flow of income construct. Here, income is equivalent (by construction) to the value of production. This is done by defining the components of national income (consumption and investment) in such a way as to correspond conceptually with aggregate factor incomes.

Constructing income as the sum of consumption and investment leads naturally to the next definition, the one we have referred to as YSHS . By construction, SHS income and circular-flow income appear identical. However, there has been a subtle but vital shifting in conceptual gears from one to the other. Firstly, as already noted, SHS income is a measure of personal income that then gets aggregated—with “person” being replaced by “economy” (albeit often only implicitly)—in discussions of national income, whereas the circular-flow constructs of GDP and NDP are explicitly aggregate, deliberately designed to measure activity in a national economy. The latter

13 Hicks, in writing of “maintaining intact the capital value of prospective receipts”, seems to have an infinite time horizon in mind. It may be that with the uncertainty of the end-date of a lifetime, or the possibility of a bequest motive, it is a sensible approximation to work on the basis of maintaining the capital value intact for an individual. The argument above presumed the final time period is known in advance, and no bequests are given.

23 accounting measures are constrained in their design and construction by accounting identities, whereas thinking in economic terms involves thinking of income as a return to wealth; not as an accounting construct designed to match the value of production. Because of these differences, each involves conceptually different measures of consumption and capital, in ways that have already been discussed.

Bos (1997) is a useful reference for readers wishing to examine this issue further. He points out, for example, that valuation at market prices by national accountants is purely descriptive: no normative content is assumed or implied by such valuation. Economists typically think in terms of shadow prices and net present values—that is, in optimising and forward-looking terms—that do not fit within the national accountants’ methodology. This distinction is crucial: prices of capital goods to national accountants are taken as exchange prices, not capitalised values of future streams of returns.

This does not mean national accountants do not want their constructions interpretable in economic terms. On the contrary, there is a general consensus that if depreciation can be measured accurately, something approaching a sensible economic magnitude has been calculated. Examples from the national accounting literature are not hard to find. Harrison (1993, pp.23-4), for example, notes that: “(National) Income in this case is not as Hicks defined it, namely, the amount that can be spent and still leave one as well off at the end of the period as one was at the beginning. …Hicks’s income can be approximated by deducting an allowance for the consumption of fixed capital from primary income. The resulting aggregate is known as net domestic product (NDP).”

Fraumeni (1997, p.9) in turn remarks on sustainable income “where depreciation is subtracted from GDP to derive net domestic product and net domestic income—a rough measure of that level of income or consumption that can be maintained while leaving capital intact.”

However it is clear that the accounting nature of conventional NDP—where capital and consumption are defined to conform to the requirements of the respective accounting identities and valued using market rather than shadow prices, etc.—

24 renders it only a crude approximation to the economic concept of Hicksian ex post income, or YSHS . This in turn is only an approximation of Hicks’ “central criterion”.

To which we now turn: how are the Hicksian consumption (or utility-based) themes of income related to YSHS ? Or, using different terminology, how is Hicksian ex ante income related to Hicksian ex post income? We base our discussion here on the premise that Hicksian income concepts are underpinned by concerns about sustainability. Both Scott (1990) and Eisner (1990), while disagreeing about how to define income, agree that sustainability is the core concern in their attempts to revise how it is measured. Moreover, the blurring of the distinction between Hicksian and SHS income, by, for example, Eisner and Aronsson et al., is (presumably) motivated by the view that the consumption-plus-capital-accumulation measure provides a suitable approximation to a sustainable consumption measure. That is, that ex post income, using Hicks’ labels, is a useful approximation to the desired ex ante income. At the very least, it provides an indication of whether capital is being accumulated, maintained, or consumed.

In terms of the notation and terminology being employed here, recall the distinction

K˙ C˙ between YHicks and YHicks . A number of analysts seem to treat YSHS as a close

K˙ ˙ approximation to YHicks . The argument is that at the very least, the K term in YSHS

K˙ enables us to see whether we are above or below YHicks . From this, we can draw and inference regarding sustainability, based on whether we are “consuming our capital” or simply living off it.

However, the difficulties with taking too literal a sustainability interpretation of this approximate measure have already been identified. Hicks himself departed from the constant-wealth version (Income No. 1) to allow for the effects of changing interest rates and prices: only with these held constant will constant wealth necessarily imply a constant stream of consumption. And even then, for reasons discussed in the previous subsection, the capital must be defined, measured, and valued appropriately in order for the sustainability interpretation to be admissible. Not only does this not

25 reflect national accounting methodology, but convincingly achieving such a measure of national capital represents a major task for those proposing to amend the national accounts in order to strengthen their interpretation along sustainability lines.

In conclusion, if we can reliably convert GDP to NDP as per the existing national accounts—that is, if we can accurately calculate depreciation of the measured capital stock—we are still some distance from a measure of YSHS that economists would regard as meaningful. This in turn would only be an approximation to a constant

K˙ K˙ capital measure of income, YHicks . Finally, YHicks needs key assumptions to hold for it

C˙ to be equivalent to the consumption annuity measure YHicks .

In other words, the distance between the conventionally accepted accounting measures of GDP and NDP, and the economic “central criterion” of sustainable consumption, is potentially vast.

5. Income and Capital Goods 5.1 Why Include Capital in Income?

A key distinction between our two key themes of income (YHicks or ex ante, versus

YSHS or ex post) is between a consumption only measure, and one that includes capital accumulation. Whether we are interested in extending conventional GDP to be a better measure of welfare, or an improved indicator of sustainability, the key variable in either case is consumption. Capital accumulation is only ever a means to an end. “Repeatedly and unabashedly the national income statistician calculates a number he calls net national product by adding in the value of the nation’s net investment to its consumption. What does this single figure measure? The usual welfare interpretation of index numbers can perhaps be used to excuse combining apples and oranges, but it falls short of providing an adequate justification for NNP. Economic activity has as its ultimate end consumption, not capital formation.” (Weitzman 1976, p.156.)

There are really two main options in the interpretation of investment in terms of consumption opportunities. They are, in turn, treating investment goods as (i) consumption opportunities foregone today, or as (ii) consumption opportunities increased tomorrow. We shall investigate these in turn, and in a later section assess

26 their respective implications for particular accounting practices and interpretations of the results.

To appreciate this issue, refer again to Figure 1. The welfare interpretation in the case of two consumption goods has already been outlined. However, if C2 is a capital good

* ˙ * (so that C2  K ) that—by definition—is used to produce future consumption goods at the expense of being available for present consumption, this interpretation becomes problematic. The amount OA no longer measures current consumption equivalents using a single numeraire. OA only represents consumption possibilities if we could (i) devote all available resources to the production of consumption goods, and (ii) transform them at the rate at which they are transformed locally at the optimum.14 As Weitzman (1976) notes, diminishing returns imply that the lower amount OB measures the total amount of consumption goods that the economy can actually produce given its resource endowments and its technology.

The question then is, what is the justification for (and thus, the economic significance of) combining today’s capital accumulation with today’s consumption into a seemingly atemporal index called “national income”? How does capital investment today relate to current welfare and/or future welfare and/or the potential to maintain or increase consumption levels? In other words, what broader interpretation can be given to income expressed in its ex post (or SHS) form?

We present and contrast two alternatives, the intertemporal interpretation and the atemporal one. Presenting the former first, we turn to Weitzman (1976).

5.2 The Growth-Theoretic Approach One way of regarding Weitzman’s paper is as an attempt to reconcile the measured form of income that combines consumption and capital goods (YSHS ) with the

C˙ conceptual ideal, the consumption-annuity measure YHicks . (Strictly speaking, Weitzman refers to what the national accountant produces, implying conventional NDP/GDP aggregates, but his analysis and interpretation require a more extended

14 The transformation ratio given by the slope of AD.

27 economic measure of YSHS that goes beyond conventional accounting practice. In particular, all consumption must be attributable to an underlying capital stock and thus all changes in the capital stock must be appropriately defined and measured.)

In order to reconcile these measures, Weitzman in effect compares two hypothetical economies. One—“Growthland”—experiences consumption C G changing over time, driven by capital accumulation K˙ G (positive or negative), while the other

—“Hicksville”—maintains constant consumption C H over an infinite time horizon. Let both economies start at time zero with equal national income so that

Y G (0)  C G (0)  K˙ G (0)  Y H (0)  C H .15

Weitzman demonstrated that the present value of Hicksville’s constant consumption path C H over an infinite horizon was just equal to the present value of Growthland’s actual optimal consumption path C G (0),.....,C G (). NDP in a growing economy thus indicates the level of consumption which, if maintained at a constant level forever from “today”, would generate a present value of welfare equal to that of the competitive trajectory from today to the infinite future. Put another way, current income, expressed as the Hamiltonian function of the underlying dynamic optimisation problem, just represents the “return to wealth” of the economy, where wealth equals discounted future consumption, and investment can legitimately be added to consumption in its capacity as an exact measure of the present value of future consumption.

Other authors such as Hartwick (1990) and Maler (1991) have generalised Weitzman’s analysis. In particular these authors generalised the objective function and explicitly modeled the use and measurement of items outside the conventional national accounts such as natural resources and environmental amenities. Where Weitzman relied on a linear objective function U(C) = C, to show that the Hamiltonian of the intertemporal optimisation problem was equivalent to the return to

15 By income here, we refer to conventional GDP. However, by virtue of a series of simplifying assumptions, GDP, NDP and SHS income are all equivalent.

28 wealth, other authors present a more general utility function U(C), and then linearised using U(C) = UC.C.

The Hamiltonian of this problem is of the form H  U (C)  K˙ . (Here,  is the shadow value of capital. Note that the variables in this expression are functions of time, e.g. U C(t), but here the time notation has been suppressed.)

Using the linear approximation U (C)  U C .C and the first order condition   U C , we can see the “national income” form of the normalised Hamiltonian as follows.

H NDP   C  K˙ U C

While typically derived in the literature as NDP (or NNP) this is not a standard national accounting measure if the model includes elements in the consumption or capital terms that are not part of the standard definition of national income. In order to keep the distinction clear, we shall denote the Hamiltonian expression as

* * ˙ * 16 YWHM  C  K (where WHM refers to Weitzman/Hartwick/Maler , and the asterisk denotes optimal values of this variable according to the optimisation problem defined by the Hamiltonian). Note that in most current models of this nature, the return to wealth interpretation is now one in which today’s income is a return to future utility, rather than the value of future consumption.

The Hamiltonian approach has inspired an extensive literature in which issues of extended accounting have been explored, in particular in the field of natural resource accounting. Recent surveys and extensions of this literature, and its potential implications for revised national accounting procedures, are contained in Aronsson, Johansson and Lofgren (1997), Hamilton (1994), Atkinson, Dubourg, Hamilton, Munasinghe, Pearce and Young (1997) and Hartwick (2000).

16 The choice of these three authors to name this particular version of income is perhaps arbitrary. Solow (1986) arguably brought Weitzman’s result to the attention of authors who have since pursued this modelling strategy. But Hartwick and Maler both generalised Weitzman’s model and explored its implications for national accounting practice, which is our concern here, hence the choice of their names.

29 What is important to note about the Hamiltonian approach to income definition is that it admits a welfare interpretation, not a sustainability one. While it appears to provide a rigorous means by which income in its SHS form can be regarded in quite precise terms as a return to wealth (seemingly a very Hicksian interpretation), we note that the Hicksian themes discussed up to now concerned income as sustainable consumption, not income as consumption plus investment. As Aaheim and Nyborg (1995) point out, Weitzman’s result does not reveal a feasible consumption level that can be maintained in perpetuity; what it shows is the hypothetical constant consumption path that has equivalent present-value-of-welfare implications to the actual consumption path the economy is following.17 What this means is that in practice there is no guarantee that consumption will be sustained at current levels even by following the accounting revisions suggested by analysts using this framework. All that can be asserted is that current income is proportional to discounted future utility.

Of course, the potential for sustainability can be analysed within this framework; examples of this include Solow (1986), Asheim (1994, 1997), Hartwick (1994, 1996) and Pezzey and Withagen (1997). Such studies use the growth-theoretic framework of Weitzman but incorporate reinvestment rules and/or international trade in order to allow for capital maintenance; in this way they can examine how consumption is related to constant capital (national wealth). Summaries of results in this area are contained in Toman, Pezzey and Krautkraemer (1995) and Hanley (1999).

Weitzman (1997) positions himself in a terminological middle ground, referring to sustainability in the context of his model as concerning a “generalised power of the economy to consume”, as opposed to its ability to maintain a specific consumption flow. By referring to sustainability in this way, no a priori restrictions are imposed on changes in consumption over time. There is certainly no strong injunction to prevent

17 Several authors have presented Weitzman’s result as though it held in strict sustainable-consumption terms. This error appears for example in Musu and Sinisalco (1996, p.28, emphasis added) where they incorrectly assert that “if the NNP of each period is defined as the sum of the consumption and of the net investment value when the relative price is efficient … then the NNP thus defined can be interpreted as the maximum consumption which can be indefinitely maintained from each period onwards.” It also seems to be what Nordhaus (1999, p.47, emphasis added) is saying when he remarks “when population is constant, when the national accounts include all stocks of capital and other dynamic features that affect production, and when market prices accurately capture the social value of economic activity … the sum of total consumption and net capital formation is equal to the maximum sustainable level of per capita consumption that an economy can maintain indefinitely.”

30 consumption declining over time as features in the Rawlsian-based sustainability literature.

* Finally, how does the measure YWSHM compare to the measures previously presented?

K˙ K˙ The closest analogue is YHicks in that in ideal circumstances, YHicks is interpretable as a

* return on social wealth, defined as the national capital stock K, while YWSHM represents a return to social wealth defined as discounted consumption/utility. But the

K˙ K˙ circumstances where YHicks is a return to capital are precisely those where YHicks =

C˙ YHicks . Thus, in principle, the two “return to wealth” concepts differ by virtue of the different concepts of capital/wealth they refer to. In terms of practical implication they differ in that one is meant to yield an actual consumption annuity, while the other yields only the stationary equivalent of a consumption annuity.

5.3 The Atemporal Perspective Weitzman’s neat result creates something of a quandary that has gone almost entirely unremarked in the literature thus far. National accounting has already been argued to be a form of historical scorekeeping, unconcerned with what will happen in the future. Even Hicks, whose conceptual definitions were explicitly based on intertemporal reasoning, stressed that in measuring income what mattered was what had happened, not what would (or might) happen.

This emphasis on history has the effect of turning the conventional injunction in economics to ignore the past—“let bygones be bygones”—on its head. In the conventional approach to measuring income it is the future, or expectations of it, that should be ignored: the dictum seems to be to “let maybes be maybes”.18 In this atemporal view, how are we to justify the addition of capital goods to consumption goods in an aggregate index that is meant to capture more than simply the value of total output? A representative example is Scott (1990, p.1174, emphasis added) who writes (with no reference to the Hamiltonian literature): “Generally it would be a reasonable first approximation to assume that a dollar of investment thus switched

18 Or perhaps: “Whatever will be, will be.”

31 could provide a dollar of consumption. That, at any rate, must be the justification for estimating income as the sum of consumption and investment.” Using this justification, the dollar for dollar addition of consumption goods and investment goods is based on an “as if” argument: capital goods are treated as if they are equivalent to an equal amount of foregone consumption today. The diminishing returns argument presented in Figure 1 has to be assumed away in order for this interpretation to be admissible.

Weitzman’s (1976) analysis clearly breaks with this tradition. Building on Samuelson’s (1961) interpretation of income as a “wealth-like magnitude”—clearly a forward-looking interpretation—Weitzman spelt out the relationship between current income and future consumption, and in doing so inspired an explicitly forward- looking literature on national accounting. This distinction between the atemporal and intertemporal perspectives still resonates in the literature today. Its implications for income measurement will be followed up below.

5.3.1 Examples of “Atemporal-Perspective” Growth Models With Investment Weitzman’s model and result has been used to motivate an intertemporal approach to national accounting. What model might be representative (or at least indicative) of an analysis within the atemporal accounting perspective? One useful example is that presented in Usher (1980). We have already noted that Usher stressed the index number issues originally raised by Hicks, and their practical implications. In particular, in a model with only consumption goods, there are several possible measures of growth, one measuring changes in productive capacity and one measuring changes in welfare.19

The introduction of capital goods into the picture unsurprisingly makes things even more complex when considering these alternatives. Usher argues that, in the context of growth, the introduction of savings and investment to the analysis leads to an added and important dimension (or distinction) in how we think about the change-in-welfare and the change-in-productive-capacity measures of growth. This is that for the

19 This seems to coincide with the general distinction we have been drawing between income measures that are production based versus those that are consumption or utility based. Note however that in the consumption-goods-only context, this distinction arises purely from index number considerations, not from the specification of a point in time income measure.

32 productive capacity measure, distinctions between the end-uses of goods are unimportant, whereas for the welfare measure such distinctions are crucial.

Given this, Usher advocates focussing on a welfare-based rather than a productivity- based concept of growth. In order to move his measurement in this direction, he carefully distinguishes various ways in which capital and investment can be defined: these include what he regards as welfare and productive capacity measures. From here he attempts to relate the various possibilities back to an underlying (Hicksian) income concept.

Usher (1980) raises four possible interpretations of investment from an accounting point of view. They are respectively the change in wealth; the output of new capital goods; the increase in the capital stock; and real saving. (For details on how Usher distinguishes between these measures, see Usher 1980, Ch. 3) In contrast to the Weitzman intertemporal model where measurement of capital is (in principle) straightforward, Usher’s model present various ways in which capital can be measured, with each measure corresponding to a different underlying measure of income. Thus a key feature of Usher’s approach is that the nature of the income measure depends on the capital measure used to underpin it.20

Usher’s preferred measure is the income measure based on the fourth interpretation of investment (real saving), and emphasises the sacrifice of current consumption goods involved in producing capital goods. This is precisely the atemporal view of investment as consumption foregone today rather than consumption postponed, and hence increased in the future.

Scott (1989) has also been cited as an advocate of the atemporal approach, and his approach, like Usher’s, emphasises the complexity of measuring (changes in) capital. He, like Usher, argues that we should proceed “as if” today’s investment could be converted to an equivalent value of consumption, and that the task of calculating income is to measure the “sustainable-consumption-equivalent” level of output (Scott 1990). Scott does this in two steps: first he divides conventional investment expenditures into what he calls “maintenance” expenditures—those devoted to

20 In the standard growth theory model, capital is assumed to be homogenous.

33 restoring and maintaining the productivity of the capital stock—and “investment” expenditures—those that increase the productivity of capital—and he classifies the former as intermediate spending. Second, he justifies adding the latter magnitude (investment) to consumption on the basis that with a fully maintained capital stock, we can treat the extra output of investment goods as if it were increased consumption, and regard the total as a yield on the capital stock. This does entail redefining what counts as investment expenditure and, as noted previously, deflating it using a consumption-goods price index. Scott is critical of the notion that exogenous technical change can add to consumption growth: in his view the conventional “residual” reflects a mis-definition or miscalculation of investment.21

5.3.2 Discussion Conventional one-sector growth models, often used in discussions of income measurement and economic growth, express output in growth in terms of consumption goods. Once differences between consumption goods—or between capital and consumption goods—are allowed, then index number issues arise that are often neglected in discussions of national income. Another problem that arises in a multi-good context is the issue of diminishing returns between capital and consumption goods. Acknowledging these issues—the index number problem, and the existence of diminishing returns—then forces the analyst to frame the specific question they think should be answered by the practice of national accounting: which question you would like answered will then drive the choice of the preferred measure to be used. These questions resolve around issues of output, welfare or sustainability (and appropriate measures of the changes in these magnitudes over time).

An examination of different approaches to measuring these magnitudes has revealed a tension between atemporal approaches—in which what happens this year is what counts—and intertemporal approaches—in which magnitudes representing capitalised values of things in future years can legitimately be added to consumption goods this year.

21 This is an important point because it conflicts with much of growth theory, and with the practice of analysts like Usher (1980) who use exogenous technical change as a litmus test to weigh the properties of different measures of income. See Section 6 (and the appendix) for further discussion of this.

34 How do these approaches relate to the objectives we highlighted earlier, namely welfare (which could be regarded as an atemporal concept) and sustainability (an explicitly intertemporal one)? It might be thought that the atemporal approach to income measurement was a welfare-oriented one while the intertemporal approach to income was aimed at being sustainability-oriented. This is a tempting conclusion to reach, but mistaken. As noted already, Weitzman’s model is avowedly intertemporal. In his view the very reason for adding consumption goods to capital goods in a measure of national income is the fact that (in his model) investment embodies the discounted value of increased future consumption. And yet, income in Weitzman’s analysis does not admit of a sustainability interpretation: it is intertemporal welfare that is the benchmark. In his words, “Net national product is what might be called the stationary equivalent of future consumption, and this is its primary welfare interpretation.” (Weitzman, 1976, p.160.)

Regarding the possible interpretation of an atemporal measure, both Scott and Usher appear to have a conventional Hicksian concept in mind. Usher’s stated interpretation of his own preferred “real savings” measure of income is as follows: income measures “the amount of consumption that could be obtained in the stationary state that would arise if technical change, net investment and population growth ceased today”. (Usher 1980, p.92.)

What are the significant elements of Usher’s definition? Firstly, it is explicitly a Hicksian (steady state) concept. Secondly, key variables are assumed constant. Population growth is the easiest to “assume away”, and it would also be easy to handle this variable differently; by, for example, recasting income in per capita terms and then assuming that population growth remained constant. The assumption that technical change has ceased represents the traditional, atemporal emphasis of Usher’s analysis. (In the next section, we shall see that allowing for capitalised technical change takes us into the realm of intertemporal measures.) Assuming net investment is zero in the steady state is equivalent to Scott’s rationale that investment is added to consumption “as if” it represented, dollar for dollar, the value of foregone consumption.

35 The fundamental issue to be resolved is revealed as being the conflict between economic concepts of income that are steady-state in nature (maintainable consumption), and the actual measurement of income in a growing economy, in which consumption flows and capital stocks are changing over time. Clearly, Weitzman and Usher, as two representative authors, have resolved this conflict in different ways.

The two approaches identified above, atemporal and intertemporal, essentially involve different ways of approximating steady states in dynamic contexts. Weitzman’s quote above identifies the intertemporal approach as measuring a stationary equivalent (present value) of future consumption. By contrast, Usher advocates what we might label a stationary state equivalent in which, by treating capital accumulation as present consumption foregone (thus making current investment a proxy for what could be additionally consumed), it is as if the economy is on a constant consumption path.

5.4 Summary In this paper we have seen that one single and central concept in economics, national income, is open to a variety of conceptual definitions. These definitions provide in turn a range of implications for the definition and measurement of the components of income (particularly consumption and investment) and the interpretations of the resulting aggregates. Moreover, conceptual confusion and idiosyncratic approaches to terminology have led to some disagreements being over-emphasised22, with others being perhaps underplayed or their significance under-appreciated.23

If the difference between the national accountants’ approach to income and the economists’ approach can be summarised succinctly, it is probably in the following way: national accountants view income as a measure of the value of production while economists view income as some form of return to wealth. In the latter view, the nature of national wealth, the connection between wealth and income, and the rationale for combining capital and consumption goods into a single index are topics for which there is as yet no consensus. For example, the standard SHS measure treats

22 For example, is adding capital gains into a forward-looking measure of income any more problematic than adding the net output of investment goods? 23 For example, the repeated blurring of the distinction between ex-post and ex-ante Hicksian income definitions.

36 wealth as current capital, and income is an approximation to the return to that wealth, depending on whether net investment is positive, negative or zero. Hicksian income, as defined thus far, is defined in consumption units as an exact return to wealth (which can be thought of as a capital stock or as capitalised future receipts). Income in Weitzman’s terms is the sum of consumption and investment, measured as a return to capitalised future utility.

The result of all these different perspectives is a confusion in the literature between those who advocate (or assume) a welfare emphasis or a sustainability emphasis in the interpretation of a proposed idealised measure; not to mention a difference— important but largely unrecognised—in possible conceptual frameworks, between an atemporal perspective in which income is strictly a “this-year” phenomenon, versus an intertemporal perspective in which “present value” magnitudes are legitimately added to magnitudes representing current output. Both of these frameworks represent ways that economists have tried to get “Hicksian” (or return to wealth) interpretations from accounting-derived measures of national income.

The interpretations of these two frameworks or perspectives in terms of the objectives (welfare and sustainability) is one key distinction. Two key authors in the atemporal tradition, Usher and Scott, seem to be intent on constructing measures that reflect the Hicksian “consumption annuity” measure presented earlier. If the economy was in such a steady state that consumption and the capital stock were both constant, then an

K˙ C accurate measure of income, defined as YHicks  YHicks , would represent a measure of maximum sustainable welfare, since in a pure Hicksian steady state welfare and sustainability are not distinct. This explains why some extended measures of income have been explicitly titled “measures of sustainable economic welfare” (see for example Stockhammer, Hochreiter, Obermayr and Steiner 1997). Given that the atemporal-perspective measures can only be approximations in a dynamic setting to the steady state consumption annuity measure, it is not clear how closely these measures approximate the underlying concepts they are intended to measure. And clearly, away from the steady state, one indicator cannot successfully measure both welfare and sustainability simultaneously.

37 The effect of this is that the atemporal (stationary-state equivalent) approach blurs welfare and sustainability by claiming to approximate a maximum-sustainable- economic-welfare program. By contrast, it becomes clear with the intertemporal approach that welfare and sustainability considerations need to be explicitly distinguished.24

TABLE 1 AROUND HERE

6. Empirical Implications 6.1 Capital Theoretic Controversies The two alternative theoretical perspectives we have identified in national income analysis have been shown to be differentiated by the role played by the future. Discounted future consumption is the exact measure of wealth (or capital) used in the “return to wealth” measure proposed by Weitzman, and (as we shall see) changes in future consumption prospects then have implications for current income. Usher, by contrast (as one example), follows national accounting practice by explicitly disavowing any effects of future changes on the current measure he is constructing. Clearly, different concepts of capital are at play here, and there are measurement consequences arising from which perspective one chooses to adopt.

As remarked already, the motivation for “atemporalists” like Usher and Scott for adding investment goods to consumption goods is that, diminishing returns notwithstanding, it is “as if” the economy had potential current consumption prospects available to it equivalent to the total output of current consumption and capital goods. One implication of this is that both these authors are critical of the standard practice of deflating the price of investment goods over time by a price deflator defined in terms

24 In the context of explicitly intertemporal models, Asheim (2000) and Pezzey (2004) have categorised a series of concepts of income based on sustainable consumption, on several versions of returns to wealth/welfare (as capitalised consumption, and as capitalised utility, with alternate approaches to discounting), and on net output. This “family” of income measures is distinguished for different reasons than (say) Usher’s alternatives, which were distinguished by different underlying concepts of capital and investment, and Pezzey shows clearly that the choice of measure used, even in simple deterministic settings, has empirical significance.

38 of investment goods. To promote the desired interpretation of investment as consumption foregone, they advocate using a consumption-goods price index to deflate the nominal value of investment.

This is not necessarily in conflict with the intertemporal perspective: the shadow price of capital in a Hamiltonian model is a relative price of capital and consumption goods. But the assumed homogeneity of capital in many of these stylised models has meant that such issues have received little attention by authors working in this area. Recent work in this vein with multiple capital goods requires complex restrictions on prices (using, say, Divisia price indices) to maintain the basic interpretation. a) Technical Change An area where differences become more marked is that of technical change. Usher opposes the incorporation of any effects of future technical change on a measure of current income, to the point of choosing one measure of capital (and hence income) over another based on the fact that it did not capitalise future technical change.25 Intertemporalists, by contrast, are much more enthusiastic about accounting for technical progress. As remarked previously, this is more consistent with economic principles than it is with standard national accounting. Nordhaus (1995) argues for its inclusion in his measure of “Fisherian income”. Weitzman (1997) does a back of the envelope calculation to compute the likely magnitude of technical change on social wealth (and hence potential consumption). Both Nordhaus and Weitzman draw the conclusion that the potential upside, in sustainability terms, of ongoing technical change can dwarf any sustainability threat resulting from resource depletion and environmental degradation.26 b) Capital Gains

25 Usher (1980, Ch. 3) notes the similarity between his “real saving” measure of income and the “change in real wealth” measure, which derive from slightly different interpretations of investment. He regards their main difference as being in their response to technical change; namely, the real wealth version capitalises (anticipated) technical change while the real saving version does not. Based on the presumption that we do not wish to say real income today is higher simply because we expect technical change tomorrow, Usher endorses the latter. 26 It should be noted that Scott, an atemporalist, takes a distinctly heterodox position with regard to the appropriate measurement of investment and the effects of technical change. He is particularly concerned with appropriate measurement of technological change ex post, arguing that the conventional “Solow residual” represents statistical mismeasurement, not the effects of technical change. Readers should consult Scott (1988) and subsequent writings for details.

39 Another controversial issue involving capitalisation of expected changes in the future concerns capital gains. Conventional national accounting wisdom here is clear: capital gains do not represent income from current production and thus do not count in national income.27 Employing an intertemporal perspective, as Weitzman and others do, complicates this. However, the first authors in the Hamiltonian literature to explicitly address the issue of capital gains maintained a position consistent with national accounting orthodoxy. In considering depreciation of the (natural) capital stock, Maler (1991) for example draws clearly the distinction between measuring the value of the change in the stock as opposed to the full change in the value of the stock. The full change in value includes both depreciation and capital gains and is, Maler argues, an inappropriate measure of depreciation. Usher (1994), in an evaluation of the Hamiltonian approach to defining income, maintains that the inclusion of capital gains in income violates what he calls the “this yearness” of national income.

Yet the very nature of the intertemporal perspective brought to bear on the analysis of national income via the use of optimal control methods calls into question the traditional concept of national income in which “this yearness” is a defining characteristic of elements to be included. Bradford (1990) makes this clear when he presents the argument against the incorporation of capital gains in income as follows: “I think the traditional objection to inclusion of revaluations … in a measure of national output goes something like: ‘The extra value is not really “output” this year; it is the present value of “output” that will appear in the future.’” (Bradford 1990, p.1186)

In the intertemporal perspective, this reasoning applies similarly to the interpretation (and inclusion) of new capital goods, and to technical change as well. To make the point as obviously as possible, consider the argument against inclusion of capital gains, namely that aggregate capital gains cannot be converted to increases in aggregate consumption simultaneously. If the share market rises in value for instance, not all of these gains can be realised instantaneously—a mass decision by shareholders to sell all their higher-valued shares simultaneously will result in share 27 Note that this is another issue where the personal-versus-national perspective is an issue. Defining and measuring personal income, as per the public finance literature, typically involves measuring all changes in personal wealth including those arising from capital gains.

40 prices being driven back down again. This is simply another aspect of Bradford’s observation that revaluations represent capitalised changes in future consumption possibilities, not an equivalent amount of current consumption possibilities.

Yet this is exactly as true of capital goods as it is of capital gains, and it is precisely the motivation for Weitzman’s stationary-equivalent interpretation of a national income measure combining capital and consumption goods. One can no more turn the entire capital stock (or even the addition to it, the investment goods that are counted in this year’s income) into an equivalent value of consumption goods today than one can with, say, stock market gains. It was the problem of diminishing returns between current consumption and current investment that led Weitzman to take a forward- looking approach to defining and interpreting income. Investment in Weitzman’s formulation is regarded as the capitalised value of increases in consumption over the optimal path—yet this is precisely the argument raised against inclusion of gains as pointed out by Bradford. Bradford argues that capital gains might be validly included in a forward-looking measure of income: to the extent they represent a capitalised value of future consumption increases—that is, they cannot be converted into immediate increases in aggregate consumption but they can be converted into increased consumption over an optimal trajectory—they have as much legitimacy (in principle) in a forward-looking measure of income as do investment goods. Hartwick (2000) deals with capital gains explicitly in an optimal control context and also explores how they might be counted on the income, as opposed to the product, side of the accounts.

A neglected distinction thus far is between anticipated and unanticipated capital gains: the previous discussion is on the context of a deterministic economy where capital gains occur over some predictable (optimal?) path. Unexpected events cause unanticipated gains, and it tends to be argued that such gains should not be counted in income. As an example, small resource-rich economies can experience large fluctuations in national income, based on the outcomes of exploration or simply changes in world market conditions. Hill and Hill (2003) look at concepts of Hicksian

41 income in a stochastic setting to determine appropriate rules for treating capital gains in national accounting. 28 c) Natural Capital Clearly, capital-theoretic considerations loom large; different opinions on how to define and measure stocks and flows of capital are a critical element in debates on income. This is, of course, nothing new. The valuable collection of articles on income collected by Parker and Harcourt (1969) contains three papers from the 1940s, by Pigou, Hayek, and Hicks respectively, on the notion of the maintenance of the capital stock as part of the definition of income. The emphasis then was on the distinction between maintenance of physical versus economic capital, and in particular the impact of obsolescence. More recently, debates have turned to issues such as those discussed above—technical change, capital gains—as well as broadening the definition of capital to include elements of “natural capital” such as pools of oil or values for biodiversity.

The idea of natural capital raises its own controversies, from the particular to the general. A particular, and important, controversy involves the appropriate treatment of non-renewable resources, but before we explore the details, some background is worth outlining. The easiest (in principle), and most consistent (both with standard economic reasoning and the principles of national accounting), way of undertaking so-called natural resource accounting is to take a capital-theoretic approach: expand our category of capital so as to include resources such as timber, oil, fish stocks, and so on, and then adjust the accounts for changes in stocks and flows as would be done for produced capital. This produces an adjusted net product measure in the YSHS vein that

K˙ is (intended to be) a closer approximation to a capital-constantYHicks measure by virtue of incorporating a more complete measure of capital than traditional measures of net product.

Both theorists and practitioners have proceeded in this direction. Repetto (1988?), a leading advocate of natural resource accounting in developing countries, has argued

28 Hartwick (2000) also discusses unanticipated gains—windfalls—and suggests an appropriate treatment is to count only the interest on unanticipated gains as an addition to income.

42 that the overuse of natural resource endowments in such countries is directly attributable, at least in part, to depletion of resource stocks being measured as increases in income rather than reductions in wealth. Weitzman (1976) presents a model in which all growth is attributable to (changes in) an underlying capital stock. In both of these instances, the issue is one of defining capital appropriately and then correctly accounting for changes in the capital stock.

Thus it seems that a natural approach to accounting for non-renewable natural resources is by treating them as capital, and measuring resource depletion as depreciation or capital consumption. Practitioners like Repetto and colleagues, and theorists like Hartwick and Maler have all followed this depreciation approach, sometimes called the “net price” approach as it involves calculating a figure for price- less-marginal-extraction-cost to be used in computing the depreciation allowance.

But one striking implication of this approach is that a Kuwait-type economy that lives off a rich resource endowment would have, in the absence of trade, a net product of zero, in that gross income is just cancelled out by depreciation. A country with a meagre but renewable endowment will have positive income (net product) compared to a country with a generous but non-renewable endowment, which will in turn have the same income, being zero, as a country with virtually no endowment at all. In response to this, El Serafy (1989) has proposed an alternative method for accounting for exhaustible resources. He explicitly disavows the notion of treating such resources as capital for which a depreciation allowance can be calculated. Instead he advocates calculating the maintainable income stream that could be generated from the proceeds of the resource depletion. He also argues that, as this is not an adjustment to net capital, it does not represent an adjustment from gross product (GDP/GNP) to net product (NDP/NNP). Instead he argues that his method more correctly counts the value-added from resource depletion, which makes it part of the gross product measure itself, since gross product is a measure of value added in the economy.

Hartwick and Hagemen (1993) have argued that El Serafy’s measure is theoretically reconcilable with a capital-theoretic depreciation measure. Notwithstanding this, many empirical studies have calculated both a conventional depreciation-adjusted income measure, as well as a measure adjusted for El Serafy’s “user cost” method,

43 with the results often being starkly in contrast. Common and Sanyal (1998) make this point forcefully in regard to measurement of resource use in Australia; Neumeyer (2000) similarly contrasts the differences in results from each method in a critique of a sustainability study undertaken by the World Bank.

Butterfield (1992) criticises El Serafy for confusing product and income measures. The depreciation method, based on the adjustment of one product measure (gross product) to another (net product), is quite consistent in principle with basic ideas of national accounting. But El Serafy’s method grafts an adjustment based on sustainable income to an initial measure based on gross product, a position Butterfield argues is inconsistent. (This is an example of the accounting-identity concept of income clashing with the sustainable-consumption concept.)

One further point remains to be remarked upon. The nature-as-capital argument depends upon the idea of all capital being, fundamentally, fungible. The focus of a discussion in these terms can then turn to ends (consumption) rather than means or specific resources (maintenance of given levels of environmental amenity or resource stocks, for example). In policy terms, the implication is that maintenance of a total stock of capital is an appropriate focus for discussion of income (in particular, for the sustainability of income); the component elements of the capital stock are, in principle, irrelevant. This underlies the analytical approach of authors like Hartwick (1977) and Solow (1986), and the use of measures such as Genuine Savings (Hamilton and Clemens 1999).

David Pearce and colleagues (see e.g. Pearce, Markandya and Barbier 1989) have since distinguished two capital-stock maintenance rules that can serve (in principle) as operational guidelines for sustainability policy. The first is an aggregate capital maintenance condition, which they refer to as “weak sustainability”: this is a common underpinning, often implicit, to many neoclassical analyses of economic growth. The second, a stronger condition, requires maintenance of a given stock of natural capital; this is labelled “strong sustainability”. (For a critique of the capital-theoretic approach to ecological sustainability, see e.g. Stern 1997. For counterexamples of the proposition that non-declining wealth always implies non-declining consumption, see Asheim 1994 and Pezzey and Withagen 1997.)

44 6.2 Other Controversies Various other issues remain contentious in discussions of extended—particularly environmental and natural resource—accounting. Space precludes an extended discussion, but some points of controversy can be quickly touched on.

One such point is that environmental valuation techniques are typically designed for use in cost-benefit analyses. They measure values, not price-equivalents. Incorporating them into national accounting aggregates introduces elements of consumers’ surplus which are not components of any other parts of national income. (See Harris and Fraser 2002.)

Another area at issue relates to the clash between accounting and economic conceptions of income as outlined earlier. The United Nations, overseeing the revision of national accounting standards for international use, have been struggling to balance the desire to broaden the coverage of the accounts for elements that have hitherto been neglected, with the desire to maintain a comprehensible and easily comparable set of definitions of national income in the spirit of the original. The solution has been to maintain a set of “core” accounts, designed and constructed according to traditional national accounting principles, and then to construct satellite accounts that contain elements not within the market sector or otherwise not included in the core accounts. (See United Nations 1993, 1998.) The same philosophy has been applied to revisions of particular national systems of accounts such as the United States (see Nordhaus 1999, 2000).

The questions of what comparisons are intended to be made also looms as an issue of concern. The Hamiltonian approach is perhaps best suited to intertemporal comparisons, being based as it is on the solution to a dynamic optimisation problem. Another branch of the literature, specifically designed to generate international comparisons, is the index number approach typified by (for example) Dowrick and Quiggin (1998), and reviewed by Hill (2000). This literature takes an atemporal approach, providing point-in-time comparisons of standards of living across countries (rather than a time series indicator for a particular country), but has an implicitly

45 intertemporal element in that capital goods are typically included as proxies for discounted consumption.29

A final controversial area has been the estimation of much broader time-series indicators that include not only conventional indicators of national income or output, but measures of losses in environmental amenities and resource stocks, and (more controversially) broader measures of “social capital” such as changes in income distribution. Such measures of “gross national progress” or so-called “sustainable economic welfare” (e.g. Stockhammer et al 1997, or Hanley, Moffatt, Faichney, and Wilson 1999) are, compared to more conventional accounting aggregates, empirically broader and theoretically ad hoc. The sense in which they capture “sustainable economic welfare” is not exposited from first principles.

7. Conclusions 7.1 Economists and national accountants use different “default” conceptual frameworks to think about the concept of income. In national accounting, income is a static measure, defined as the value of current production and derived from the relevant accounting identities. Economists, by contrast, think of income in dynamic terms, being a flow from an underlying stock that may or may not be being held constant. (In the simplest benchmark or steady state case the stock is maintained, neither declining nor growing.) The two concepts are, of course, reconcilable in principle but they are not identical in their construction. The implication of this is that when proposing revisions to how income is defined and measured in practice, accountants and economists often come from quite different directions, with accountants concerned to maintain the integrity of the relevant identities, and economists attempting to broaden the definition of the capital base from which income is presumed to flow, sometimes in ways that violate the output/income identity. At the official level, this is reflected in the reluctance of the United Nations to tamper too much with the “core” market-sector accounts in their revisions of the System of National Accounts.

29 Arguably, this brings into question the significance of their point-in-time welfare comparisons based on consumption when not all of the output of the countries being compared is of consumption goods.

46 7.2 Income ex post (consumption plus capital accumulation) and income ex ante (maintainable consumption) are distinct concepts, but often conflated into a single one. Some statements of “Hicksian” income refer to a measure combining consumption plus capital accumulation as if it is also an indicator of that amount of consumption that can be had without future impoverishment. Hicks himself distinguished clearly between ex ante consumption measures—his central criterion—and ex post approximations to it. He was not confident in his assessment of how good an approximation these ex post measures would be. In fact, his pessimism shows in just clarifying what the central criterion ex ante was, given the complications due to price changes, interest rate changes, consumer durables and so on. Once it came to measuring these concepts in practice, his tone became even more gloomy. Yet many modern writers treat the ex ante measure as being well defined, and as being virtually interchangeable with the ex post measure. As recently as 1990, David Bradford reasserted the distinction between the two, referring to ongoing “professional confusion” on the subject.

7.3 Proposals to modify income measures are typically aimed at re-defining a measure constructed along ex post, or backward-looking, lines, into one that is interpretable in forward-looking terms. Standard national accounting is oriented to identifying “where we are” (or have recently been). The usual aim in revising the accounts is to re-orient the measures we produce into a more forward-looking direction. In particular, the motivation is often one of measuring the sustainability of our consumption; in other words, are we putting ourselves at future risk of declining living standards?

The problem turns on how one recasts an ex post measure (consumption plus capital accumulation) into a measure interpretable in terms of consumption. This requires measuring investment goods in terms of a “consumption counterfactual”, the implications of which lead us to the next conclusion.

7.4 There are two distinct ways in which ex post income measures have been presented in terms of a sustainable consumption measure, corresponding to two different ways in which investment goods are “converted” to consumption

47 units. Each way has different implications for defining, measuring and interpreting the income measure that results. As presented here, two approaches or traditions have emerged in getting “Hicksian income” measures from modified national income statistics. One—that I have labelled the stationary-state equivalent approach—treats investment goods as current consumption foregone, in line with the atemporal focus of standard national accounting that treats the appropriate focus of the national accounts as being what happened this year rather than what might happen in future. The other—labelled the stationary equivalent approach—takes the intertemporal (present value) perspective more familiar to economists, with investment being treated as future consumption postponed. This latter approach, prevalent since the 1990s, is popular with economists schooled in growth theory. The atemporal approach is perhaps more old-fashioned, and more closely associated with analysts schooled in national accounting principles as well as dynamic economics.

The problem of presenting an ex post measure as somehow equivalent to a consumption-only measure can be re-expressed as the problem of presenting the measurement of output in a dynamic economy as though the economy were in a steady state. The atemporal approach treats the economy as if it were in an actual steady state (hence, stationary-state equivalent), while the intertemporal approach treats the economy as being the present-value equivalent of a constant-consumption economy (hence, stationary equivalent).

7.5 The analysis of welfare and sustainability is often oversimplified (sometimes misleadingly) in the literature given the divergence of the actual economy from the steady-state proxy economy analysed in each of the concepts presented in 7.4 Note that another problem is presented by the fact that our key analytic construct (typically referred to as Hicksian income) is based on the idea of a steady state while the world may not actually be in such a state. In a steady state economy, with a constant income flow off an unchanging stock of wealth, current welfare is unchanging, and is sustainable. In fact, the situation is a textbook one of consumption (income) signifying maximum sustainable welfare.

48 Out of a steady state, however, current welfare (actual consumption) and sustainable consumption will typically take different values. Getting a measure of whether standards of living are changing, and by how much, becomes a different question than assessing whether current standards of living are maintainable. In the intertemporal Hamiltonian models this tends to be clearer: one must either define sustainability more weakly, such as Weitzman’s “generalized power to consume”, or be explicit about the consumption path that is being solved for and whether it is possible for consumption to decline given the parameters of the model.

In the vaguest (theoretically speaking) models, such as those that purport to present measures of “sustainable economic welfare”, it is not clear how the numbers presented relate to either welfare or to sustainability.

7.6 Both economic approaches to revising income—stationary equivalent and stationary-state equivalent—contain measurement error problems. Neither can be thought of as “exact”. The approach of treating investment as if it were equivalent to current consumption foregone has the problem that it ignores the diminishing returns that are evident in Figure 1. Weitzman’s development of the Hamiltonian-based model of national income with its associated (and novel) intertemporal interpretation was motivated by the observation that feasible present consumption and actual national income were two different magnitudes for that very reason. However, the intertemporal approach linearises the Hamiltonian to get a linear income measure and hence suffers some approximation error in turn. The Hamiltonian measure seeks to cast current income as being proportional to discounted future welfare: but to be able to add consumption to investment in dollar units requires a linearisation that removes any consumers’ surplus. This loss of consumers’ surplus is appropriate from a national accounting perspective, but the exact proportional correspondence with future welfare is lost.

7.7 The applied literature, such as the natural resource accounting studies proliferating in recent years, often do not proceed with clear reference to first- principles models. The examination of first-principles models in the first few sections of this paper showed them to be assumption-specific, with no one model that covered every

49 situation or allowed a robust and generally applicable interpretation. It suggests that any attempt to empirically recalculate a measure of national or regional income should proceed with regard to a particular model and interpret its results in that light.

This is not in fact what happens. Many studies appear to proceed with the intention of producing some modified version of a YSHS measure. This is turn seems motivated by the general notion that maintaining capital intact is a good idea—in other words that a modified measure of YSHS will be a good approximation to a constant capital measure

K˙ K˙ YHicks . In turn, the presumption must be that YHicks is a good approximation to the

C˙ ideal sustainable consumption measure, a.k.a. Hicks’ “central criterion”, YHicks . In some cases, when pressured to pay lip service to theory, authors may make a general appeal to the foundations provided by the Hamiltonian literature; the problem is that this implies a forward-looking interpretation in the vein of YWHM , which does not in

C˙ general serve as a proxy for the steady-state measure YHicks .

7.8 Income is not one concept to be defined in one single all-encompassing way. Following Hicks, various context specific measures, complete with approximation errors, are likely to be required. This requires analysts in the field of national income measurement and empirical economic growth to understand the limitations of their respective measures, and the limits to their interpretations. Welfare and sustainability interpretations arise from particular assumptions made about the “steady-stateness” of the economy, and being explicit about those assumptions is vital to drawing appropriate conclusions from empirical analyses. Two leading economists have both contended that interpreting national income figures depends on the purpose with which we have constructed them.

“Sharpening our conception of what we want the accounts to tell us seems a matter well worth further professional attention.” (Bradford, 1990, p.1186)

50 “Ultimately the meaning of national income is inherent in the purposes of the national accounts.” (Usher, 1994, p.124)

The problem faced by all attempts at measurement of economically meaningful magnitudes boils down to the fact that the key economic interpretations are intended to describe steady states, but the measurement is typically occurring in the context of a growing economy. The atemporal approach aims, in effect, to mimic a steady-state (consumption-annuity) economy; in doing so, the sustainability and welfare emphases coincide, in that the steady-state they purport to describe is one in which the economy is generating maximum sustainable economic welfare. The problem is that the link between welfare and sustainability here is an artificial and forced one, given that capital goods are included in the index. A sustainability interpretation may be admissible (for k˙  0 ) using these measures if we make appropriate capital-theoretic assumptions, but current welfare is mismeasured.

Alternatively, the intertemporal approach aims to provide a more general and rigorous welfare interpretation, in which income and welfare are expressed in present value rather than “instantaneous” terms. However, the trade-off is that sustainability is also only interpretable in such present value terms as well—what Weitzman (1997) refers to as the generalised capacity of the economy to consume.

The result of all these different perspectives is a confusion in the literature between those who advocate (or assume) a welfare emphasis or a sustainability emphasis in the interpretation of a proposed idealised measure (and whether the measure they may propose provides the interpretation they claim it does); not to mention a difference in an atemporal perspective in which income is strictly a “this-year” phenomenon, versus an intertemporal perspective in which “present value” magnitudes are legitimately added to magnitudes representing current output.

51 TABLE 1—DIFFERENT THEMES OF INCOME

Income Theme Form Interpretation National Accounting  Income is generated by production.  Historical perspective. GDP/NDP Y = C + I  Consumption and investment determined by “boundaries” (market sector) according to circular flow relationships. Schanz-  Return to wealth underpinning. Haig-  Historical but broadening it in principle Simons can make it more forward-looking. Y = C + K˙  C and I (denoted K˙ to highlight the capital stock K from which income is YSHS presumed to flow) may vary in definition (not only from national accounting measure, but between individual economic studies), depending on level of analysis and what is presumed to contribute to current and future utility.  Crude sustainability interpretation based on non-negative K˙ . Hicksian  Stricter return to wealth interpretation, with income now consumption only. K˙ Y = max C s.t. ˙ = 0  “Constant capital” measure generally YHicks K regarded as the measurable analogue of the (constant capital) “consumption annuity” measure. or  C and I can be defined similarly as for ˙ Y C YSHS, which is sometimes taken as an Hicks Y = max C s.t. ˙ = 0 approximation for the K˙ = 0 version. (consumption annuity) C

Hamiltonian  Income is now return to wealth (Weitzman-Hartwick- (sometimes strictly so) but is not Maler) consumption only!  Explicitly intertemporal interpretation, and derived from optimising model (* denotes * * ˙ * YWHM  C  K optimal value). YWHM  Wealth is taken to be PV of all consumption – in contrast with treating wealth as the value of the actual capital

stock in interpretation of YSHS for example.  Investment presumed to be PV of extra consumption.  Admits welfare rather than sustainability interpretation, in contrast to above definitions, and even that is conditional.

Appendix

52 On the treatment of depreciation, deterioration and obsolescence in Maurice Scott’s work on measuring economic growth.

Maurice Scott has proposed a radically different view from the “orthodox” view of national accounting and income measurement. It is worth covering it in a little bit of detail.

Scott (1989), like Usher, argues that we should proceed “as if” today’s investment could be converted to an equivalent value of consumption, and that the task of calculating income is to measure the “sustainable-consumption-equivalent” level of output (Scott 1990). Scott does this in two steps: first he divides conventional investment expenditures into what he calls “maintenance” expenditures—those devoted to restoring and maintaining the productivity of the capital stock—and “investment” expenditures—those that increase the productivity of capital—and he classifies the former as intermediate spending. Second, he justifies adding the latter magnitude (investment) to consumption on the basis that with a fully maintained capital stock, we can treat the extra output of investment goods as if it were increased consumption, and regard the total as a yield on the capital stock. This does entail redefining what counts as investment expenditure and, as noted previously, deflating it using a consumption-goods price index. Scott is critical of the notion that exogenous technical change can add to consumption growth: in his view the conventional “residual” reflects a mis-definition or miscalculation of investment

(He also questions whether diminishing returns empirically justify the rejection of the atemporal approach (pers. comm..))

Here is a summary of how key parts of his approach compare to the “orthodoxy”.

1. The conventional view of depreciation and productivity in economics: - depreciation is akin to physical deterioration (“reduction”) in the capital stock - as such it is associated with loss of productivity in the economy - economic growth is associated with (or determined by) the net change in the capital stock

53 - the income/product identity is maintained by deducting depreciation from profit on the income side, to match the loss on the product side - unexplained growth (not accounted for by conventional labour and capital) is the "residual" reflecting technical change.

2. Scott's view of depreciation-as-obsolescence: - most actual depreciation results from obsolescence, not physical decay - no loss of productivity is associated with obsolescent capital goods (only a loss of value) - depreciation thus not associated with a reduction in output - any "restorative" capital expenditure that offsets actual wear and tear should be labelled maintenance and not investment spending (conceptually different and should be classified and measured elsewhere) - economic growth associated with the total (or gross) rate of investment, not the net change in the capital stock - on the income side of the accounts (with product not declining based on obsolescent but still-productive capital equipment), losses to capital owners are offset by increases in income to labour - the conventional "residual" is a result of mismeasurement. If we assume obsolescence results in reduced productivity when it doesn't, then we underestimate growth, and mistakenly attribute the "excess" growth to an unmeasured activity. Correct accounting should eradicate the residual.

READINGS IF INTERESTED:

Scott, M. (1989), A New View of Economic Growth, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

Scott, M. (1990), “Extended Accounts for National Income and Product: A Comment”, Journal of Economic Literature, 28, September, pp. 1172-1179.

Dension, E (1991), “Scott's A New View of Economic Growth: A Review Article”, Oxford Economic Papers; 43(2), pp.224-36.

54 Scott, M. (1991), “A Reply to Denison”, Oxford Economic Papers, 43(2), pp.237-44.

Scott, M. (1991), “A New Theory of Endogenous Economic Growth”, Oxford Review of Economic Policy; 8(4), Winter, pp.29-42.

Oulton, N. (1995), “Depreciation, Obsolescence and the Role of Capital in Growth Accounting”, Bulletin of Economic Research; 47(1), pp.21-33.

Scott, M, (1995a), “Depreciation, Obsolescence and the Role of Capital in Growth Accounting: A Reply”, Bulletin of Economic Research; 47(1), pp.35-38.

Scott, M, (1995b), “What Sustains Economic Development?”, in Goldin, Ian, Winters, L. Alan, eds. The Economics of Sustainable Development. Cambridge; New York and Melbourne: Cambridge University Press, pp. 83-105.

Scott, M, (1984), “Maintaining Capital Intact”, Oxford Economic Papers, N. S.; 36(0), Supp. Nov. 1984, pages 59-73, reprinted in Collard, D. A., et al., eds. Economic Theory and Hicksian Themes. Oxford; New York; Toronto and Delhi: Oxford University Press Clarendon Press, 1984, pp.59-73.

55 References

Aaheim, A., and K. Nyborg (1995), “On the Interpretation and Applicability of a ‘Green National Product’”, Review of Income and Wealth, 41 (1), pp 57-71. Aronsson, T., P.-O. Johansson, and K.-G. Lofgren (1996), Welfare Measurement, Sustainability and Green National Accounting: A Growth Theoretical Approach, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham. Asheim, G. (1994), “Net National Product as an Indicator of Sustainability”, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 96 (2), pp 257-265. Asheim, G.B. (1997). “Adjusting Green NNP to Measure Sustainability”, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, Vol 99, pp 355-370. Asheim, G.B. (2000), “Green National Accounting: Why and How?”, Environment and Development Economics, 5(1), reprinted in Perrings and Vincent (eds.) (2003). Atkinson, G., R. Dubourg, K. Hamilton, M. Munasinghe, D. Pearce and C. Young (1997), Measuring Sustainable Development: Macroeconomics and the Environment, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, United Kingdom. Australian Bureau of Statistics (ABS) (1995), “National Balance Sheet for Australia Issues and Experimental Estimates 1989 to 1992”, Occasional Paper, 5241, Australian Bureau of Statistics, Canberra. Bartelmus, P. (1995), “Toward a System of Integrated Environmental and Economic Accounts (SEEA)”, in Milon and Shogren, (1995). Bos, F. (1997), “Value and Income in the National Accounts and Economic Theory”, Review of Income and Wealth, 43 (2), pp. 173-190. Bradford, D. (1990), “Comment on Scott and Eisner”, Journal of Economic Literature, 28, September, pp 1183-1186. Brekke, K.A. (1996), Economic Growth and the Environment: On the Measurement of Income and Welfare, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham. Butterfield, D.W. (1992). “Natural Resources in National Accounts: Some Suggestions for the Mining Industries”, QSEP Research Report Number 293, McMaster University, Faculty of Social Sciences, Hamilton, Ontario, Canada. Common, M, and K. Sanyal (1998), “Measuring the Depreciation of Australia’s Non- Renewable Resources: A Cautionary Tale”, Ecological Economics, Volume 26, Number 1, pp 23-30. Dowrick, S. and J. Quiggin (1998) “Measures of Economic Activity and Welfare: The Uses and Abuses of GDP”, in Eckersley, R. (ed.) (1998) Measuring Progress: Is Life Getting Better?, CSIRO Publishing, Collingwood. Eisner, R. (1988), “Extended Accounts for National Income and Product”, Journal of Economic Literature, 26, December, pp. 1611-1684. Eisner, R. (1990), “Reply (to Scott)”, Journal of Economic Literature, 28, September, pp 1179-1183. El Serafy, S. (1989), “The Proper Calculation of Income from Depletable Natural Resources”, in Ahmad, Y.J., S. El Serafy and E. Lutz (eds.) (1989),

56 Environmental Accounting for Sustainable Development, Washington DC, World Bank. Fisher, I. (1930), “Income and Capital”, reprinted in Parker, R.H. and G.C Harcourt, (eds.) (1969), Readings in the Concept and Measurement of Income, Cambridge U.P., Cambridge. Fraumeni, B.M. (1997), “The Measurement of Depreciation in the National Income and Product Accounts”, Survey of Current Business, July, 7-23. Hamilton, K. (1994), “Green Adjustments to GDP”, Resources Policy, 20 (3), 155- 168. Hamilton, K. and M. Clemens (1999), “Genuine Savings Rates in Developing Countries”, World Bank Economic Review, 13(2), 333-356. Hanley, N. (2000), “Macroeconomic Measures of Sustainability”, Journal of Economic Surveys, 14 (1), pp. 1-30. Hanley, N., I. Moffatt, R. Faichney, and M. Wilson (1999), “Measuring Sustainability: A Time Series of Alternative Indicators for Scotland”, Ecological Economics, Vol 28, pp 55-73. Harris, M. and I. Fraser (2002), “Natural Resource Accounting in Theory and Practice: A Critical Assessment”, Australian Journal of Agricultural and Resource Economics, June. Harrison, A. (1993), “National Assets and National Accounting”, in Lutz (1993).

Hartwick, J.M. (1977), “Intergenerational Equity and the Investing of Rents from Exhaustible Resources”, American Economic Review, 67, 972-4. Hartwick, J.M. (1990), “Natural Resources, National Accounting, and Economic Depreciation”, Journal of Public Economics, 43, pp 291-304. Hartwick, J.M. (1994), “National Wealth and Net National Product”, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 96 (2), 253-256. Hartwick, J.M. (1996), “Constant Consumption as Interest on Capital”, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 98 (3), 439-443. Hartwick, J.M. (2000), National Accounting and Capital, Edward Elgar, UK.

Hartwick, J.M., and A.P. Hageman (1993), “Economic Depreciation of Mineral Stocks and the Contribution of El Serafy”, in Lutz (1993).

Hecht, J.E. (2000), “Lessons Learned from Environmental Accounting: Findings from Nine Case Studies”, IUCN/The World Conservation Union, Washington D.C. (http://www.iucn.org/places/usa/greenacct.html). Hicks, J.R. (1940), “The Valuation of the Social Income”, Economica, 7, 105-24. Hicks, J.R. (1946), Value and Capital: An Inquiry into Some Fundamental Principles of Economic Theory, 2nd ed., Clarendon Press, Oxford. Hill, R. (2000), “How Best to Measure Welfare, Real Income and Output?”, Review of Income and Wealth, 46 (1), 117-127. Hill, R.J. and T.P. Hill (2003), “Expectations, Capital Gains and Income”, Economic Inquiry, 41(4), pp.607-619.

57 Holub, H.W., G. Tappenier and U. Tappeiner (1999), “Some Remarks on the ‘System of Integrated Environmental and Economic Accounting’ of the United Nations”, Ecological Economics, Vol 29, pp 329-336. Keynes, J.M. (1936), The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money, Macmillan: Cambridge University Press for the Royal Economic Society, Cambridge. Maler, K-G. (1991), “National Accounts and Environmental Resources”, Environmental and Resource Economics, 1 (1), pp. 1-15. Musgrave, R.A., and P.B. Musgrave (1982), Public Finance in Theory and Practice, McGraw-Hill, United States. Musu, I., and D. Sinisalco, (1996), “Environmental Accounting: Introductory Remarks”, in Musu, I., and D. Sinisalco, (eds.), National Accounts and the Environment, Kluwer Academic Publishing, the Netherlands. Neumayer, E. (2000,a), “Resource Accounting in Measures of Unsustainability: Challenging the World Bank’s Conclusions”, Environmental and Resource Economics, Vol 15, pp 257-278. Nordhaus, W. (1994), “Reflections on the Concept of Sustainable Economic Growth”, in Pasinetti, L., and R. Solow (eds.) (1994), Economic Growth and the Structure of Long-Term Development, Macmillan Press, Hampshire. Nordhaus, W. (1995), “How Should We Measure Sustainable Income?”, Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper No. 1101, Yale University. Nordhaus, W.D. (1999), “The Future of Environmental and Augmented National Accounts. An Overview”, Survey of Current Business, November, pp 45-49. Nordhaus, W.D. (2000), “New Directions in National Economic Accounting”, American Economic Review, Vol 90, No. 2, pp 259-263. Oakley, G. (1996), “Linking Environment and Economy Through Environmental Accounts: An ABS Project”, in Australian Academy of Science (1996), Tracking Progress Linking Environment and Economy Through Indicators and Accounting Systems, Fenner Conference on the Environment, University of New South Wales, September 30 to October 3. Oulton, N (2002), “Productivity versus Welfare: or, GDP versus Weitzman’s NDP”, Bank of England Working Paper. Parker, R.H. and G.C Harcourt, (eds.) (1969), Readings in the Concept and Measurement of Income, Cambridge U.P., Cambridge. Pearce, D., A. Markandya and E. Barbier (1989), Blueprint for a Green Economy, Earthscan, London. Perrings, C. and J. Vincent (eds.) (2003), Natural Resource Accounting and Economic Development: Theory and Practice, Edward Elgar, UK. Pezzey, J. and C. Withagen (1997), “The Rise, Fall and Sustainability of Capital- Resource Economies”, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 100 (2) 513-527. Pezzey, J.C.V. (2004), “Exact Measures of Income in a Hyperbolic Economy”, Environment and Development Economics, 9, pp.473-484. Repetto, R., W. Magrath, M. Wells, C. Beer, and F. Rossini (1989), “Wasting Assets: Natural Resources in the National Income Accounts”, World Resources

58 Institute, reprinted in The Earthscan Reader in Environmental Economics (eds. A. Markandya and J. Richardson, 1992), Earthscan, London. Samuelson, P. (1961), “The Evaluation of ‘Social Income’: Capital Formation and Wealth”, in Lutz, F., and D. Hague (eds.), The Theory of Capital, Macmillan, London. Scott, M. (1989), A New View of Economic Growth, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

Scott, M. (1990), “Extended Accounts for National Income and Product: A Comment”, Journal of Economic Literature, 28, September, pp. 1172-1179. Solow, R. (1986), “On The Intergenerational Allocation of Natural Resources”, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 88 (1), pp. 141-149. Stockhammer, E., H. Hochreiter, B. Obermayr and K. Steiner (1997), “The Index of Sustainable Economic Welfare (ISEW) as an Alternative to GDP in Measuring Economic Welfare. The Results of the Austrian (Revised) ISEW Calculation 1955-1992”, Ecological Economics, 21 (1), 19-34. Toman, M., J. Pezzey and J. Krautkraemer (1995), “Neoclassical Economic Growth Theory and ‘Sustainability’”, in The Handbook of Environmental Economics, ed. D.W. Bromley, Blackwell, Bristol. United Nations (1993), “Integrated Environmental and National Accounting”, Interim Version, Handbook of National Accounting, Series F, No. 61, Department of Economic and Social Development, Statistical Division, New York. United Nations (1998), Integrated Environmental and Economic Accounting: An Operational Manual, Draft Version, Statistics Division, New York. Usher, D. (1980), The Measurement of Economic Growth, Basil Blackwell, London. Usher, D. (1994), “Income and the Hamiltonian”, Review of Income and Wealth, 40 (2), pp 123-141. Weitzman, M. (1976), “On the Welfare Significance of National Product in a Dynamic Economy”, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 90 (1), pp 156-162. Weitzman, M. (1997), “Sustainability and Technical Progress”, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 99 (1), 1-13. Weitzman, M. (2003), Income, Wealth and the Maximum Principle, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, USA.

59

Recommended publications