Think by Simon Blackburn

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Think by Simon Blackburn Think by Simon Blackburn Chapter 4b Free Will/Self The unobservability of the self David Hume, the Scottish empiricist we met in connection with his critique of Descartes’ method of doubt, is very skeptical of the notion of a self. His argument (p.122) is just that the self is unobservable. When we introspect the only thing we can become aware of is some experience or other. We are never aware of some “I” that is some how the bearer of all those experiences. Empiricism Hume’s argument is typical of classical empiricism: if you can’t see (or, more generally, sense), it doesn’t exist. But this argument against the self is actually a very poor one for the 21st century. The reason is very simply that today we acknowledge all sort of things that are beyond sensation. If we only believed in what we can see in touch, then we would have to regard virtually of the phenomena of contemporary science (molecules, atoms, subatomic particles, charges, forces, electromagnetic radiation, dark matter, black holes, etc.) as fictions. David Hume did not believe in the soul because A. Hume was a rationalist and the soul can not be rationally proven. B. Hume was an empiricist, and he did not think that the soul was observable. C. Hume was a determinist and was skeptical that a soul could be free. D. Hume actually did believe in a soul. The self and morality Like free will, the idea of a persisting self is central to our moral intuitions. Basically, the idea here is that holding people responsible for things over time requires the assumption that they are the same people over time. In fact, we often do here arguments that someone should not be held responsible for something he did 20 years ago, because he is really not even the same person. The simplicity of the self Philosophers like Thomas Reid (a contemporary of Hume) have insisted that the self is not only real, but indivisible. (p.123). The point here is that we really can’t identify the self with our body or some part of our body, because our body can be theoretically chopped up into little pieces. And it’s silly to suggest that each little piece would be entitled to it’s share of the estate or be held responsible for it’s share of the harm done by the entire body. Simplicity and immortality As Blackburn points out (p.124) there is an interesting connection between the assumption of simplicity, and immortality. Dying, after all, is just a form of change. But the only kinds of things that can change are things that have parts. So if Reid is right that the self is simple, then it cannot change, which means that it must be immortal. Thomas Reid believed that the self is simple because A. simple things are easier to understand. B. the self is indivisible, and only simple things are indivisible. C. the self is immaterial and only immaterial things are indivisible. D. non simple things can not transfer their properties through epicyclic parameters. Locke’s on identity I John Locke had some of the most interesting insights into identity. He approached the question of personal identity for human beings by asking first what is the basis of identity for non human beings. His answer is interesting. Locke asks us to consider an oak tree from it’s ‘birth’ as an acorn to it’s death 350 years later when it topples in a storm. We are inclined to say that it is the same tree the entire time, but obviously it changes dramatically in physical terms. According to Locke, the oak is not the thing you see before you at any given time. The oak is that physical process through time. Locke says that it continues to be the same oak insofar as it “partakes in the same life.” Locke on identity II Locke’s view has relevance for our understanding of human beings as well. Even though science can not countenance the existence of souls, it is not thereby committed to the idea that your are merely an assemblage of particles. Like the oak you are a “functional unity”. At any given moment we see only a very small part of you. The “real you” is not an immaterial object, for the simple reason that you are not an object at all. Human beings, like oaks, are processes through time. This way of looking at living things gives Locke a nice way of saying what it means to be the same being over time. Specifically, to be the same being is simply to be participating in the same process. Growth and change do not undermine identity as long as the functional organization remains. Locke believed that since human beings are not made of the same physical stuff through time they are not self-identical through time. A. True B. False The Ship of Theseus The Ship of Theseus (or Neurath) is an excellent story for dialing in the problem of characterizing a functional entity in terms of what it’s made of. Imagine that Theseus (legendary King of Athens) sails his ship on a voyage so long that every part on the ship is replaced due to wear and tear. When he returns to port, is it the same ship? Now add to this the assumption that someone is following the ship throughout it’s voyage and gathering all the discarded parts. He assembles them into their original form. Now who has the Ship of Theseus? Locke’s answer is straightforward. The true Ship of Theseus is the one that Theseus returned on. This is not because Theseus returned on it, but because the ship is not what it is made of, but the entire temporal process by which it’s functional integrity is maintained. Locke’s critique of the immaterial soul Locke has established that ships, oaks, and animals can remain self-identical despite having all their matter replaced. This gives him an interesting basis for criticizing the view that human self-identity is due to a single, simple immaterial soul. His point is extremely interesting (p. 128) : Even if we accept the idea of an immaterial soul, how do we know that a single, simple self-identical substance persists through time? Locke’s question elaborated Remember, Locke has just shown us that a being can be identified with a physical process, where the actual matter is constantly in flux. So, why couldn’t a soul just be an analogous immaterial process, where the “soul stuff” is constantly in flux? Kant’s elastic balls The German philosopher Kant imagines a different possibility (p. 129) using an analogy with perfectly elastic balls. We know, he says, that when one rolling ball hits another stationery one, it imparts it’s momentum to it. How do we know that the self isn’t like this? Why couldn’t it be that during your lifetime a multiplicity of immaterial substances is simply transferring the contents of your consciousness from one to the other in the way that elastic balls transfer their momentum? Self 1 Self 2 Self 3 Self 4 Argument from ignorance redux Recall Schopenhauer’s powerful point that our belief in freedom is largely the result of our ignorance of the causes of our actions. Kant’s point is very similar. As Blackburn emphasizes, we assume that the self is simple because that’s the way it appears from within. But for all we know our immaterial substance (if there is any such thing) gets replaced every night with a new one that has all our memories and experiences recorded on it. Both Kant and Locke believed that the self is due to a single immaterial substance persisting through time. A. True B. False Human beings vs. persons. Interestingly, Locke held that the criteria of identity he developed for oaks and human beings (partaking in the same life) is not sufficient for persons. For Locke, a person is "...a thinking, intelligent being, that has reason and reflection, and can consider itself as itself, the same thinking thing, in different times and different places." In other words, a human being is a person to the extent that it is self-conscious, able to reflect on its memories and experiences. The prince and the cobbler Although Blackburn does not discuss it here, Locke arrives at his criterion of identity for persons through a thought experiment. He asks us to imagine a prince and a cobbler who exchange souls in their sleep. Hence, the body of the cobbler wakes up in a hovel with all the memories of a prince, and the body of a prince wakes up in castle with all the memories of a cobbler. Locke thinks it is obvious that the cobbler as human being is still in the hovel, but the cobbler as person is now living in a castle and in a prince’s body. Hence, Locke argues that the criterion of identity for persons is not a function of it’s physical nature, but of its consciousness. To be the same person through time is to possessed of the same memories. Locke’s motivation As a Christian, Locke believes in a soul that survives bodily death; but as a scientist and a philosopher he knew that there is no way to know the soul of another man. Hence, while he puts the thought experiment in terms of changing souls, he does not see personal identity in terms of the soul at all.
Recommended publications
  • 1 Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth and History, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1979). Henceforth 'RTH'. the Position Th
    [The Journal of Philosophical Research XVII (1992): 313-345] Brains in a Vat, Subjectivity, and the Causal Theory of Reference Kirk Ludwig Department of Philosophy University of Florida Gainesville, FL 32611-8545 1. Introduction In the first chapter of Reason, Truth and History,1 Putnam argued that it is not epistemically possible that we are brains in a vat (of a certain sort). If his argument is correct, and can be extended in certain ways, then it seems that we can lay to rest the traditional skeptical worry that most or all of our beliefs about the external world are false. Putnam’s argument has two parts. The first is an argument for a theory of reference2 according to which we cannot refer to an object or a type of object unless we have had a certain sort of causal interaction with it. The second part argues from this theory to the conclusion that we can know that we are not brains in a vat. In this paper I will argue that Putnam’s argument to show that we cannot be brains in a vat is unsuccessful. However, the flaw is not in the argument from the theory of reference to the conclusion 1 Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth and History, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1979). Henceforth ‘RTH’. The position that Putnam advances in this first chapter is one that in later chapters of RTH he abandons in favor of the position that he calls ‘internal realism’. He represents the arguments he gives in chapter 1 as a problem posed for the ‘external realist’, who assumes the possibility of a God’s eye point of view.
    [Show full text]
  • Meaning Ain't in the Head 1. Hilary Putnam (1926-2016)
    Louis deRosset { Spring 2019 Putnam: Meaning Ain't in the Head 1. Hilary Putnam (1926-2016): Philosopher, logician, mathematician. Putnam is famous for important and seminal work in just about every sub- field in philosophy. 2. Putnam's Target: . two unchallenged assumptions: (1) That knowing the meaning of a term is just a matter of being in a certain psychological state. (2) That the meaning of a term determines its extension. (700) DEFINITION: The extension of a term is its nominatum: • for names, definite descriptions: a certain person, place, or thing. EX.: `Obama', `The president of the U.S.' • for predicates: the set of things of which the predicate is true. EX.: `is a student', `is a person'. Putnam's Target is the Fregean theory of intentionality: The Fregean Triangle (yet again!): Sense 4< expresses determines #+ expression Nominatum Putnam (following Carnap) uses different terminology for the same ideas: Frege says... Putnam says... sense meaning, intension nominatum extension The Fregean Triangle (Putnam's terms): meaning 3; expresses determines expression extension"* Putnam adds the speaker to the picture [BLACKBOARD: draw the speaker with a speech balloon around the expression]. Louis deRosset { Spring 2019 In this situation, Putnam (following Frege), says that the speaker grasps the sense. [BLACKBOARD: draw the grasping relation between the speaker and the sense]. Putnam's target: (a) grasping a meaning is a psychological state; and (b) meaning determines extension, (i.e. if A and B grasp the same meaning, their expressions have the same extension.) 3. Putnam's Thesis: I shall argue that these two assumptions are not jointly sat- isfied by any notion, let alone any notion of meaning.
    [Show full text]
  • A Historical Survey of Sir Karl Popper's Contribution to Quantum
    A Historical Survey of Sir Karl Popper’s Contribution to Quantum Mechanics William M. Shields Worcester Polytechnic Institute, Worcester, Massachusetts, United States. E-mail: [email protected] Editors: Ion C. Baianu, Christoph Lehner, Debajyoti Gangopadhyay & Danko Georgiev Article history: Submitted on May 28, 2012; Accepted on July 28, 2012; Published on November 15, 2012. ir Karl Popper (1902–1994), though not 1 Popper in the physics journals trained as a physicist and embarrassed early Sin his career by a physics error pointed out by Sir Karl Popper, by any measure one of the preeminent Einstein and Bohr, ultimately made substantial con- philosophers of the twentieth century, died in 1994 at the tributions to the interpretation of quantum mechan- age of 92. He was productive to the end, publishing in ics. As was often the case, Popper initially formu- the year of his death a criticism of Kuhn’s incommensu- lated his position by criticizing the views of others – rability of paradigms [1]. That debate continues over his in this case Niels Bohr and Werner Heisenberg. Un- many and profound philosophical ideas and opinions is derlying Popper’s criticism was his belief that, first, hardly surprising, almost two decades after his death. The the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechan- proliferation of book-length biographies and scholarly ics abandoned scientific realism and second, the as- philosophical articles is testimony to Popper’s standing as sertion that quantum theory was complete (an asser- a philosopher [2–5]. Major conferences are also regularly tion rejected by Einstein among others) amounted held on the thought of Karl Popper [6, 7].
    [Show full text]
  • Hilary Putnam: Mind, Meaning and Reality
    Hilary Putnam: On Mind, Meaning and Reality Interview by Josh Harlan HRP: What are the ultimate goals of the philosophy of mind? What distinguishes the philosophy of mind from such fields as neuroscience, cognitive science, and psychology? Putnam: Like all branches of philosophy, philosophy of mind is the dis- cussion of a loose cluster of problems, to which problems get added (and sometimes subtracted) in the course of time. To make things more com- plicated, the notion of the "mind" is itself one which has changed a great deal through the millenia. Aristotle, for example, has no notion which exactly corresponds to our notion of "mind". The psyche, or soul, in Aristotle's philosophy is not the same as our "mind" because its functions include such "non-mental" functions as digestion and reproduction. (This is so because the "sou1"'is simply the form of the organized living body in Aristotle's philosophy. Is this obviously a worse notion than our present- day notion of "mind"?) And the nous, or reason, in Aristotle's philosophy, excludes many functions which we regard as mental (some of which are taken over by the thumos, the integrative center which Aristotle locates in the heart). Even in my lifetime I have seen two very different ways of conceiving the mind: one, which descended from British empiricism, conceived of the mental as primarily composed of sensations. "Are sensations (or qualia, as philosophers sometimes say) identical with brain processes?" was the "mind-body problem" for this tradition. (The mind conceived of as a "bundle of sensations" might be called "the English mind".) The other way conceived of the mind as primarily characterized by reason and inten- tionality - by the ability to judge, and to refer.
    [Show full text]
  • MURPHY, Alice. Thought Experiments and the Scientific Imagination. Phd
    i Thought Experiments and the Scientific Imagination Alice Murphy Submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Leeds School of Philosophy, Religion, and History of Science September 2020 ii The candidate confirms that the work submitted is her own and that appropriate credit has been given where reference has been made to the work of others. This copy has been supplied on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. The right of Alice Murphy to be identified as Author of this work has been asserted by her in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. © 2020 The University of Leeds and Alice Murphy iii Acknowledgements Firstly, a huge thank you to my supervisors, Steven French and Aaron Meskin. It’s hard to do justice to the support and insights that you have each provided over the past four years. Steven has been endlessly generous, and has an open minded approach to research that is a constant source of inspiration. Aaron’s meticulous attention to detail has made me a more careful writer and thinker. You’ve both enabled me to form sketchy ideas into arguments, spurred me on when I’ve been lacking in confidence, and have made the whole process energising and, dare I say it, fun. At the risk of causing too high of expectations of the thesis that follows, I also want to say thank you to Milena Ivanova, Andrea Blomqvist, Mike Stuart, Max Jones, Fiora Salis, Karim Thébault and Adrian Currie for incredibly valuable conversations and feedback.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Imagination
    Philosophical Imagination Philosophical Imagination: Thought Experiments and Arguments in Antiquity Edited by Boris Vezjak Philosophical Imagination: Thought Experiments and Arguments in Antiquity Edited by Boris Vezjak This book first published 2021 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2021 by Boris Vezjak and contributors All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-5275-6975-6 ISBN (13): 978-1-5275-6975-1 TABLE OF CONTENTS Preface ...................................................................................................... vii List of Contributors ................................................................................... xi Part 1: Thought Experiments from Plato to Hume Chapter One ................................................................................................ 3 The Anatomy of Three Thought Experiments in Plato’s Republic, Apology, and in Alcibiades Minor Andre M. Archie Chapter Two ............................................................................................. 25 From Kallipolis to Utopia: The Metamorphoses of Ideal Theory Nenad Miščević Chapter Three ..........................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Fiction As Thought Experiment
    Fiction as Thought Experiment Catherine Z. Elgin Harvard University Although ªctions and thought experiments are not physical realizations of the phenomena they pertain to, like real experiments, they exemplify properties or patterns that they share with those phenomena. They thereby afford epistemic access to properties and patterns that are realized in fact. The Problem Jonathan Bennett (1974) maintains that Huckleberry Finn’s deliberations about whether to return Jim to slavery afford insight into the tension be- tween sympathy and moral judgment; Miranda Fricker (2007) argues that the trial scene in To Kill a Mockingbird affords insight into the nature of testimonial injustice. Neither claims merely that the works prompt an at- tentive reader to think something new or to change her mind. Rather, they consider the reader cognitively better off for her encounters with the novels. Nor is her cognitive improvement restricted to acquiring new justiªed true beliefs about the works themselves. What the reader gleans is supposed to enhance her knowledge or understanding of the extra- literary world. Fricker and Bennett are probably right. But their being right raises an epistemological problem. How can a work of ªction which is not and is known not to be true provide any measure of epistemic access to the way things actually are? Is it really possible to ªnd out about the world by making things up? One attractive answer is that works of ªction are thought experiments. Like literary ªctions, thought experiments neither are nor purport to be physically realized. Nevertheless, they evidently enhance understanding of the phenomena they pertain to.
    [Show full text]
  • Nozick (1974, 1989)
    The Experience Machine by Robert Nozick (1974, 1989) Excerpt from Anarchy, State, and Utopia (1974) What matters other than how people's experiences feel "from the inside"? Suppose there were an experience machine that would Give you any experience that you desired. Superduper neuropsycholoGists could stimulate your brain so that you would think and feel you were writinG a Great novel, or makinG a friend, or readinG an interestinG book. All the time you would be floatinG in a tank, with electrodes attached to your brain. Should you pluG into this machine for life, preproGramminG your life's experiences? If you are worried about missinG out on desirable experiences, we can suppose that business enterprises have researched thorouGhly the lives of many others. You can pick and choose from their large library or smorgasbord of such experiences, selectinG your life's experiences for, say, the next two years. After two years have passed, you will have ten minutes or ten hours out of the tank, to select the experiences of your next two years. Of course, while in the tank you won't know that you're there; you'll think it's all actually happeninG. Others can also pluG in to have the experiences they want, so there's no need to stay unpluGGed to serve them. (IGnore problems such as who will service the machines if everyone pluGs in.) Would you pluG in? What else can matter to us, other than how our lives feel from the inside? Nor should you refrain because of the few moments of distress between the moment you've decided and the moment you're pluGGed.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume's Missing Shade of Blue Reexamined
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Student Theses Baruch College 1-1-2014 Hume's Missing Shade of Blue reexamined Vyacheslav Faylayev Baruch College How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/bb_etds/18 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] Hume’s Missing Shade of Blue Reexamined By Vyacheslav Faylayev Submitted to the Committee of Undergraduate Honors at Baruch College of the City University of New York on May 5th, 2014 in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts in Philosophy with Honors. ___________________________ Professor Thomas Teufel Faculty Supervisor ___________________________ ___________________________ Professor Douglas Lackey Professor Charlotte Brooks Page | 1 HUME’S MISSING SHADE OF BLUE REEXAMINED By Vyacheslav Faylayev Table of Contents I. Introduction……………………………………………………….........................2 II. Breaking Down the Missing Shade of Blue……………………………………....6 III. The Missing Shade of Blue: Exception, Not a Threat…………………………....9 IV. Hume’s Copy Principle & Causality………………………………………...…..15 V. Hume’s Self-Criticism………………………………………………...……...…17 VI. Possible Arguments against Hume’s Missing Shade of Blue Defused……….....20 VII. Conclusion………………………………………………...………………….…31 VIII. References………………………………………………………………………34 Page | 2 Hume’s Missing Shade of Blue Reexamined Abstract David Hume, known as a strict empiricist, posits that all perceptions are divided into impressions and ideas. Except for a lower degree of vivacity, ideas directly resemble their corresponding impressions. This is the core of Hume’s ‘copy principle,’ which claims that all ideas are simply copies of their corresponding more lively impressions.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Leibniz Thought Experiment
    Notes on Leibniz thought experiment Markos Maniatis Departamento de Ciencias B´asicas, Universidad del B´ıo-B´ıo Avda. Andr´es Bello s/n, Casilla 447 Chill´an, Chile email: [email protected] Leibniz thought experiment of perception, sensing, and thinking is reconsidered. We try to understand Leibniz picture in view of our knowledge of basic neuroscience. In particular we can see how the emergence of consciousness could in principle be understood. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Monadology (1714), §17 [1]: “Besides, it must be admitted that perception, and anything that depends on it, cannot be explained in terms of mechanistic causation – that is, in terms of shapes and motions. Let us pretend that there was a machine, which was constructed in such a way as to give rise to thinking, sensing, and having perceptions. You could imagine it expanded in size (while retaining the same proportions), so that you could go inside it, like going into a mill. On this assumption, your tour inside it would show you the working parts pushing each other, but never anything which would explain a perception. So perception is to be sought, not in compounds (or machines), but in simple substances. Furthermore, there is nothing to be arXiv:1309.0846v1 [q-bio.NC] 3 Sep 2013 found in simple substances, apart from perceptions and their changes. Again, all the internal actions of simple substances can consist in nothing other than perceptions and their changes.” We would like to reconsider Leibniz thought experiment, presented about three centuries ago. Today we know, that at a tour inside the elementary working parts are the neurons, which push each other by means of electrical activity.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cognitive Value of Fiction: Two Models
    teorema Vol. XXXV/3, 2016, pp. 149-164 ISSN: 0210-1602 [BIBLID 0210-1602 (2016) 35:3; pp. 149-164] The Cognitive Value of Fiction: Two Models Frank Boardman RESUMEN Un buen número de controversias actuales incluyen cuestiones sobre el valor cog- nitivo de la ficción. En cada uno de esos contextos encontramos un cierto escepticismo sobre lo que podría llamarse la “tesis fuerte”: que podemos alcanzar determinado cono- cimiento proposicional no-trivial a partir de la ficción en virtud del contenido narrativo de esta. Presento dos maneras en las que las ficciones pueden proporcionarnos (y a menudo lo proporcionan de forma efectiva) conocimiento proposicional precisamente de ese modo. Defiendo que esos modelos ayudar a dar una respuesta a gran parte del escepticismo que se ha mencionado. Concluyo considerando algunas implicaciones de todo el proyecto y algunas objeciones al mismo. PALABRAS CLAVE: valor cognitivo de la ficción, aprender de la ficción, Aristóteles. ABSTRACT A number of current controversies involve questions about the cognitive value of fiction. In each of these contexts, we find skepticism about what might be called the “strong thesis,” that we can non-trivially gain determinate propositional knowledge from fictions by virtue of their narrative contents. I offer two ways in which fictions can (and often do) provide us with propositional knowledge in just this way. I make the case that these models help answer much of the skepticism mentioned above. I conclude by considering a number of implications of and objections to the entire project. KEYWORDS: Cognitive Value of Fiction, Learning from Fiction, Aristotle. A number of recent and current controversies involve questions about the cognitive value of fiction.
    [Show full text]
  • Article Evaluating the Cognitive Success of Thought Experiments
    Evaluating the Cognitive Success of Thought Experiments Damián Islas Mondragón Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science, 3 (2017) 68-76 ISSN 2526-2270 www.historiographyofscience.org © The Author 2017 – This is an open access article Article Evaluating the Cognitive Success of Thought Experiments Damián Islas Mondragón1 Abstract: Thought experiments are widely used in natural science research. Nonetheless, their reliabil- ity to produce cognitive results has been a disputable matter. This study is conducted to pre- sent some rules of confirmation for evaluating the cognitive outcome of thought experi- ments. I begin given an example of a “paradigmatic” thought experiment from Galileo Galilei: the falling bodies. Afterwards, I briefly surveying two different accounts of thought experi- ments: James R. Brown’s rationalism and John D. Norton’s empiricism. Then, I discuss their positions and I show that none of them may tip the balance towards the rationalism or em- piricism they try to defend. Finally, I put forward that the notion of confirmation, connected to the notion of increasing plausibility, can be used to develop some confirmation rules to compare the explanatory power of thought experiments in competition, regardless of their 68 rational or empirical nature in which the discussion of this type of experiment has been en- gaged in recent years. Keywords: Thought Experiments; Back Ground knowledge; Confirmation; Plausibility; Success Received: 05 August 2017. Reviewed 31 October 2017. Accepted: 30 November 2017. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.24117/2526-2270.2017.i3.06 _____________________________________________________________________________ Introduction Thought experiments are “unexecuted experiments” devised to support or refute a scientific theory – or part of it.
    [Show full text]