Kant's Proleptic Philosophy of History

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Kant's Proleptic Philosophy of History KANT’S PROLEPTIC PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY: THE WORLD WELL-HOPED A Dissertation Submitted to the Temple University Graduate Board In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY by José Luis Fernández May 2019 Examining Committee Members: Dr. Espen Hammer, Advisory Chair, Department of Philosophy Dr. Lara Ostaric, Department of Philosophy Dr. Joseph Margolis, Department of Philosophy Dr. Richard Eldridge, Outside Examiner, Department of Philosophy, Swarthmore College ABSTRACT The aim of this dissertation is to examine several proleptic bases running through Immanuel Kant’s philosophy of history. The approach that I take is broad and wide- ranging, and while I sacrifice concentrated focus on any one particular area of Kant’s philosophy, I cast my nets in ways that remain problem centered and exegetical by drawing from both the primary literature as well as classic and contemporary research. While I try to answer several worrisome concerns in the secondary literature pertaining to Kant’s proleptic philosophy of history, I also attempt to stay close to the primary texts by providing references and citations to key claims and passages which reinforce Kant’s forceful portrait of the poietic power of human reason to create a world hospitable to its rational ends. Consequently, rather than concentrating on any one aspect of Kant’s proleptic philosophy, I set out to (i) investigate seemingly untenable problems with his characterization of reason in history, (ii) to counter what I take as a misreading, if not a misattribution of Kant’s philosophy as being prophetic, rather than proleptic, (iii) to offer an original reflection on Kant’s use of a famous stoic phrase in two of his political essays, and (iv) to attempt a close exegesis toward tying notions of teleology and hope with that of need. ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I should like to give thanks for the support I have received during my career at Temple University beginning with acknowledging Professor Miriam Solomon, who initially welcomed me to Temple and worked to provide support and encouragement first as the graduate director, and then as the department chair. I wish to thank the Graduate School for two years of stipend support as a Future Faculty Fellow (2009 & 2012), and the philosophy department for two years of support in the form of a teaching assistantship (2010-2011). I also wish to thank Ms. Sonia Lawson for her invaluable help as the department coordinator. I also want to thank my advisor and internal and external examiners, Espen Hammer, Lara Ostaric, Joseph Margolis, and Richard Eldridge for sitting in on my defense and for proposing changes and improvements on my work. While I sincerely and gratefully acknowledge the instruction and support I have received from all of my professors on the philosophy faculty at Temple University, I wish to bring specific attention to professors at Temple who have contributed not only to my academic advancement and education, but also to my sense of well-being. I should very much like to acknowledge my gratitude to the late Professor Charles Dyke for his uplifting encouragement and generous support of my academic talents. I had the pleasure of taking three courses with Chuck, on literature, on science, and on history. This last course led me to produce a paper on Kant’s proleptic philosophy of history, which eventually became the basis for my dissertation. I had even more pleasure getting to know him a bit. Chuck was a ubiquitous presence in the department, seen teaching, working in his office, and roaming the halls on what seemed like every day of the week. I look back iii fondly at our encounters, which often led to delightful talks in his office to better shape our ideas on topics ranging from the literature of Borges, to the science of emergence, to the architecture of gothic cathedrals. Permeating all of these talks, however, I never lost sight of Chuck’s charitable spirit because he also offered personal reflections to help me understand a very complicated time in my life in trying to balance personal, professional, and academic responsibilities. Professor Lewis Gordon was a sight to behold: dynamic, passionate, and filled with an intellectual energy that, apropos to his expertise in existentialism, reminded me of Kierkegaard’s remark about Goethe’s take on Hamlet, namely, that the prince’s soul in relation to his body was like an acorn planted in a flower pot, with the result that it was bound burst out of its container. Such was Lewis’s soul in class, building up, pouring forth, unable to restrain its palpable concerns with human existence, the agon-y (struggle) of history, and, always, its willful defiance to acquiesce to mere historical facts. Lewis was also a very perceptive and sympathetic teacher, actively so in his mentorship of students. Many times did Lewis offer me his help, in and out of the classroom. He is, in my eyes, a gleaming mensch. Taking courses with Professor Joseph Margolis was like sitting in the presence of the mythical sphinx, spinning riddles, couching conundrums, and devouring philosophy. Joe opened my eyes to a way in which an historical orientation to philosophy can be profitably combined with analytic and argumentative precision. Joe is also extremely kindhearted, relating experiences that were somewhat similar to my own challenges in trying to improve my abilities in a discipline I loved while keeping to my promise of not doing so at the expense of my wife and young daughter. I am very proud and happy that a iv paper I wrote for Joe’s class on philosophy in literature, which examined the notion of truth in the literature of Jorge Luis Borges, is soon to be published in November as a chapter in a compendium being put out by Palgrave Macmillan. I owe to professor Professor Kristin Gjesdal, with whom I took two classes on the philosophy of history, great thanks for her always thorough instruction on modern German philosophy, and for introducing me to Yirmiyahu Yovel’s commentary on Kant’s philosophy of history. My interest in Yovel’s identification of Kant’s “historical antinomy” was stirred in preparing for her class, and grew to comprise the second chapter of my dissertation, which also made its way to publication in modified form in a 2017 issue of the Southwest Philosophy Review . I am also sincerely grateful to Kristin for extending to me in her capacity as the department’s graduate director repeated consideration when, for many external reasons, I was not able to keep to timely deadlines in my dissertation planning and writing. Most important to the completion of this dissertation and to the alleviation of stress and anxiety related to its production, I cannot fully convey my appreciation for the sustained support of my advisor, Professor Espen Hammer. Upon meeting Espen and taking two of his classes, I felt that we shared similar intellectual interests. As an undergrad, I was introduced to the thought of Hans Blumenberg by Frank Farrell, who took a famed graduate course on the German philosopher at Yale with Karsten Harries. The course was a revelation for me, and I was fortunate to produce an essay that would eventually be published in the Yale Philosophy Review , a select undergraduate publication which was sometimes cited in professional publications. My first class with Espen, as it would turn out, was on the topic of secularization and modernity, which focused heavily on v Blumenberg’s monumental The Legitimacy of the Modern Age . This instantly made me feel very at-home studying philosophy at Temple, and also convinced me to approach Espen to advise my dissertation work. Unfortunately, my production in this area met many obstacles and disappointments. Throughout all this, however, Espen has been nothing but forgiving to a such a compassionate degree that I am embarrassed to have tested its limits. I hope to incorporate Espen’s example in my own interaction with students, always recalling my failures with humility and working to encourage the ends of my students with similar patience and understanding. Outside of my graduate experience at Temple, I should like to thank my philosophy professors at Stony Brook University, from which I received my M.A., most notably Professors Allegra de Laurentiis, Edward Casey, and Eva Kittay, all of whom offered outstanding instruction and generosity. At Purchase College, I received a grounding in philosophy that keeps serving me to this day, especially, from Professors Frank B. Farrell and Casey Haskins. Both of whom still fill me with wonder and inspiration. On a closing note, I wish to thank my wife, Miraline, and daughter, Sofía, for their sustaining love. I recall writing a fourth-grade assignment in which I stated that I could never properly repay my parents for all they have done and sacrificed for me. My father was a construction laborer and my mother worked in a hospital kitchen. Individually and in unison, they would always implore, “José, think!” I find myself, so many years later, still inclined to obey. Hence, I wish to dedicate my dissertation to my mother, María Teresa Fernández, and to the memory of my father, José A. Fernández. Optimis Parentibus : Omnia mutantur, nihil interit . A Mis Padres Excelentes: Todo cambia, nada se pierde vi TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT…….………………………………………………………………………...ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS………………………………………………………………..iii TABLE OF CONTENTS…………………....…………………………………………..vii LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS….……………………………………………………….viii CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCING HOW HOPE IN KANT’S PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY REQUIRES BROAD EXPLICATION, AND PRÉCIS OF SUBSEQUENT CHAPTERS……..……………………………….……....1 CHAPTER 2: THE FACULTY OF REASON AS GROUND AND BRIDGE...……….27 CHAPTER 3: KANT’S PROLEPTIC PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY ............................ 73 CHAPTER 4: HOPE, HAPPINESS, AND HISTORY………………………………...101 CHAPTER 5: LEADING THE WILLING: KANT’S SENECAN PHRASE………….123 CHAPTER 6: HISTORICAL HOPE SUPPORTED BY TELEOLOGICAL REFLECTIONS…………………….
Recommended publications
  • De Por Qué En La Filosofía Importan Los Ejemplos*
    ________________________________________________________________________________ ARETÉ Revista de Filosofía Vol. XVIII, N° 1, 2006 Vicente Santuc: El topo en su laberinto. Introducción a un filosofar posible hoy, Lima: Universidad Antonio Ruiz de Montoya, 2005, 510 pp. This is a book intended for teaching philosophy and, at the same time, defending both philosophical discourse and reasonable action. With- out pretending to build a system of true knowledge, philosophy continues its work like ‘the mole in its labyrinth,’ presented by Nietzsche in his pro- logue to Aurora, trying to find its way under the surface. In an attentive dialogue with Eric Weil, which extends throughout the book, Santuc shows that the philosophical effort towards meaning, intelligibility, coherence, and dialogue is not primarily opposed to ignorance and error, but to violence. Thus he presents a practical philosophical effort that turns the moral im- perative of universal and equal respect towards human beings into an im- perative of intellectual honesty, which forces us both to study history in all its harshness and to put the philosophical tradition into use. The book arises from the author’s college lectures. This fact is re- flected in its style, its present-time examples, and the occasional references made to events occurring in Peru. Therefore, the book is also a testimony of the practical and the intellectual commitments that Santuc has assumed in this country. In the introductory chapter, which concerns the nature of philosophy, he examines the problem of knowledge. Plato’s dialectics and Aristotle’s logic are studied, with a special focus on the various meanings of the word ‘truth.’ Where the frank and explicit ancient metaphysics ends – metaphys- ics which is, for this same reason, a fertile ground for criticism – a time filled with diverse worlds that claim to have no overall theories but rest on massive assumptions begins.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth, Rationality, and the Growth of Scientific Knowledge
    ....... CONJECTURES sense similar to that in which processes or things may be said to be parts of the world; that the world consists of facts in a sense in which it may be said to consist of (four dimensional) processes or of (three dimensional) things. They believe that, just as certain nouns are names of things, sentences are names of facts. And they sometimes even believe that sentences are some- thing like pictures of facts, or that they are projections of facts.7 But all this is mistaken. The fact that there is no elephant in this room is not one of the processes or parts ofthe world; nor is the fact that a hailstorm in Newfound- 10 land occurred exactIy I I I years after a tree collapsed in the New Zealand bush. Facts are something like a common product oflanguage and reality; they are reality pinned down by descriptive statements. They are like abstracts from TRUTH, RATIONALITY, AND THE a book, made in a language which is different from that of the original, and determined not only by the original book but nearly as much by the principles GROWTH OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE of selection and by other methods of abstracting, and by the means of which the new language disposes. New linguistic means not only help us to describe 1. THE GROWTH OF KNOWLEDGE: THEORIES AND PROBLEMS new kinds of facts; in a way, they even create new kinds of facts. In a certain sense, these facts obviously existed before the new means were created which I were indispensable for their description; I say, 'obviously' because a calcula- tion, for example, ofthe movements of the planet Mercury of 100 years ago, MY aim in this lecture is to stress the significance of one particular aspect of carried out today with the help of the calculus of the theory of relativity, may science-its need to grow, or, if you like, its need to progress.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relation of History of Science in the Structure of Scientific
    The Relation of History of Science to Philosophy of Science in The Structure of Scientiªc Revolutions and Kuhn’s later philosophical work Vasso Kindi University of Athens In this essay I argue that Kuhn’s account of science, as it was articulated in The Structure of Scientiªc Revolutions, was mainly defended on philosophical rather than historical grounds. I thus lend support to Kuhn’s later claim that his model can be derived from ªrst principles. I propose a transcendental reading of his work and I suggest that Kuhn uses historical examples as anti-essentialist Wittgensteinian “reminders” that expose a variegated land- scape in the development of science. T. S. Kuhn was a physicist who became a historian, but who also wrote a book, the Structure of Scientiªc Revolutions (1970),1 that proved seminal in philosophy of science. In that book, unlike what was typical in philosophy of science before the so-called historical turn, there are quite a few refer- ences to particular cases from the history of science. After the Structure, and all the praise and controversy that it evoked, Kuhn published Black- Body Theory and Quantum Discontinuity (1987), a book of history of science. The question that repeatedly arose was: what is the relation of Kuhn’s phi- losophy of science to the history of science? He was asked, for example, whether the Black-Body book exhibited the pattern of development that was elaborated in the Structure. His commentators wanted to know whether the facts pertaining to quantum theory provided conªrmation for his philosophical model, whether they could serve as a testing ground, but also, whether his account of these particular facts was shaped by his philo- sophical model.
    [Show full text]
  • History from a Philosophic Perspective
    CANADIAN SOCIAL STUDIES VOLUME 41 NUMBER 1, Fall 2008 www.quasar.ualberta.ca/css History from a Philosophic Perspective Catherine Broom Simon Fraser University Return to Articles Abstract One of the key components of Social Studies has always been history, yet many of us seldom explore what we mean by history. This paper delves into the meaning of history through an examination of Collingwood’s work and a discussion of how we can incorporate twentieth century thought into his work. This paper aims, in Collingwood’s words, to “deepen understanding” of our craft. Philosophy of History: Collingwood The philosophies of history of Thucydides, Plato, Aristotle, Polybius, St Augustine, Bodin, Vico, Herder, and Hegel (selections in Tillinghast, 1963) and Collingwood (1956) make clear that understanding “history” is not easy. The questions that have to be answered, such as for and of whom is it written and why, are philosophical ones. Most of these philosophers saw history from a religious viewpoint: they viewed its events as illustrating the unfolding of “Providence,” or God’s purpose. However, Collingwood’s work (1956) illustrates the true meaning of history. Collingwood argues that certain early accounts, such as in pre­Greek societies, or certain modern accounts, like those based on dividing societies into a number of epochs, such as Marx’s, are not really history, as they shape facts to suit their larger theoretical frameworks. Rather, history is the re­enactment of past thought in the mind of a historian in order to answer a question about people in the past the historian has first articulated.
    [Show full text]
  • Contrastive Empiricism
    Elliott Sober Contrastive Empiricism I Despite what Hegel may have said, syntheses have not been very successful in philosophical theorizing. Typically, what happens when you combine a thesis and an antithesis is that you get a mishmash, or maybe just a contradiction. For example, in the philosophy of mathematics, formalism says that mathematical truths are true in virtue of the way we manipulate symbols. Mathematical Platonism, on the other hand, holds that mathematical statements are made true by abstract objects that exist outside of space and time. What would a synthesis of these positions look like? Marks on paper are one thing, Platonic forms an­ other. Compromise may be a good idea in politics, but it looks like a bad one in philosophy. With some trepidation, I propose in this paper to go against this sound advice. Realism and empiricism have always been contradictory tendencies in the philos­ ophy of science. The view I will sketch is a synthesis, which I call Contrastive Empiricism. Realism and empiricism are incompatible, so a synthesis that merely conjoined them would be a contradiction. Rather, I propose to isolate important elements in each and show that they combine harmoniously. I will leave behind what I regard as confusions and excesses. The result, I hope, will be neither con­ tradiction nor mishmash. II Empiricism is fundamentally a thesis about experience. It has two parts. First, there is the idea that experience is necessary. Second, there is the thesis that ex­ perience suffices. Necessary and sufficient for what? Usually this blank is filled in with something like: knowledge of the world outside the mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Francis Fukuyama the National Interest Summer 1989
    The End of History? Francis Fukuyama The National Interest Summer 1989 IN WATCHING the flow of events the intellectual climate of the world's over the past decade or so, it is hard to two largest communist countries, and avoid the feeling that something very the beginnings of significant reform fundamental has happened in world movements in both. But this history. The past year has seen a flood phenomenon extends beyond high of articles commemorating the end of politics and it can be seen also in the the Cold War, and the fact that "peace" ineluctable spread of consumerist seems to be breaking out in many Western culture in such diverse regions of the world. Most of these contexts as the peasants' markets and analyses lack any larger conceptual color television sets now omnipresent framework for distinguishing between throughout China, the cooperative what is essential and what is restaurants and clothing stores opened contingent or accidental in world in the past year in Moscow, the history, and are predictably Beethoven piped into Japanese superficial. If Mr. Gorbachev were department stores, and the rock music ousted from the Kremlin or a new enjoyed alike in Prague, Rangoon, and Ayatollah proclaimed the millennium Tehran. from a desolate Middle Eastern What we may be witnessing is not capital, these same commentators just the end of the Cold War, or the would scramble to announce the passing of a particular period of rebirth of a new era of conflict. postwar history, but the end of history And yet, all of these people sense as such: that is, the end point of dimly that there is some larger process mankind's ideological evolution and at work, a process that gives coherence the universalization of Western liberal and order to the daily headlines.
    [Show full text]
  • The Pragmatics of Explanation: Remarks on Van Fraassen's Theory of Why-Questions1
    The Pragmatics of explanation: Remarks on van Fraassen’s theory of why-questions1 A Pragmática da explicação: Comentários sobre a teoria das questões-por-quê de van Fraassen Renato Cesar Cani Universidade Federal do Paraná – UFPR/CAPES – Brasil [email protected] Abstract: In this article, my aim is to analyze Bas van Fraassen’s pragmatic solution to two of the traditional problems concerning scientific explanation, namely, rejection and asymmetry. According to his view, an explanation is an answer to some request for information. The emergence of a question, as well as the evaluation of the explanations adduced, depends on considerations about contextual factors. In addition, I will evaluate the pertinence of objections raised by Philip Kitcher and Wesley Salmon against van Fraassen’s account. I will argue that their charge is not sound, for it actually misunderstands the role played by context in van Fraassen’s account. Although Salmon’s and Kitcher’s realist commitments motivate the point made by them, I will hold that a pragmatic account of explanation does not commit one to an anti-realist approach to science. Keywords: Pragmatics of Explanation. Bas van Fraassen. Why-questions. Asymmetry. Realism. Resumo: Neste artigo, meu objetivo é analisar a solução pragmática oferecida por Bas van Fraassen a dois dos tradicionais problemas da explicação científica, quais sejam, o da rejeição e o da assimetria. Em sua visão, uma explicação é uma resposta a alguma demanda por informação. O surgimento de uma questão, bem como a avaliação das possíveis explicações, depende de fatores contextuais. Além disso, avaliarei a pertinência das objeções de Philip Kitcher e Wesley Salmon contra a concepção de van Fraassen.
    [Show full text]
  • An Argument Against the Unification Account of Explanation
    An Argument Against the Unification Account of Explanation Michael Strevens Draft of December 2009 Abstract Unification accounts of explanation equate unifying power with explanatory power; you might expect, then, that an increase in the known unifying power of a theory would be accompanied by an increase the perceived quality of its explanations. This paper presents examples suggesting that there is no such relationship: a theory’s increased unifying power means that it explains many new things, but it does not explain the old things any better just because it now explains the new things. It seems that the relationship between unifying and explanatory power is rather complex—or non-existent. The negative implications for the unification account are investigated. 1 1. The Unication Approach to Explanation According to a unification account of explanation, to explain a phenomenon— an event, a sequence of events, a law, an ongoing “effect” such as the aurora borealis—is to show that it belongs to a set of phenomena which can be unified by a relatively simple theory (Friedman 1974; Kitcher 1981, 1989). A generic form of the unification account might, then, require that an explana- tion of a phenomenon e do three things: 1. Present a sufficiently simple theory T, 2. Present a sufficiently large and perhaps diverse set of phenomena E to which e belongs, and 3. Show that (the phenomena in) E can be derived in the right sort of way from T. To flesh out the view, three things must be provided: an account of what counts as deriving E from T in the “right sort of way”, an account of what counts as a “sufficiently large” (or sufficiently diverse) set of phenomena, and an account of what counts as a “sufficiently simple” theory.
    [Show full text]
  • John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History. Seth J
    East Tennessee State University Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University Electronic Theses and Dissertations Student Works 5-2009 John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History. Seth J. Bartee East Tennessee State University Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.etsu.edu/etd Part of the Other History Commons Recommended Citation Bartee, Seth J., "John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History." (2009). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 1859. https://dc.etsu.edu/etd/1859 This Thesis - Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Works at Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History _____________________ A thesis presented to the faculty of the Department in History East Tennessee State University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Masters of Arts in History _____________________ by Seth J. Bartee May 2009 _____________________ Dr. Melvin E. Page, Chair Dr. Daniel Newcomer Dr. William Burgess Dr. Stephen Fritz Keywords: John Dewey, Pragmatism, Historiography, Personhood, Instrumentalism ABSTRACT John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History by Seth J. Bartee John Dewey was America‟s foremost authority on many of the critical issues in the twentieth century. Dewey dedicated his professional career as an expert on the major branches of philosophy. A neglected aspect of Dewey‟s philosophy is his writings on historiography, the philosophy of history, and his influence on American historians.
    [Show full text]
  • Explanatory Proofs and Beautiful Proofs
    Journal of Humanistic Mathematics Volume 6 | Issue 1 January 2016 Explanatory Proofs and Beautiful Proofs Marc Lange University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm Part of the Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons, Metaphysics Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Lange, M. "Explanatory Proofs and Beautiful Proofs," Journal of Humanistic Mathematics, Volume 6 Issue 1 (January 2016), pages 8-51. DOI: 10.5642/jhummath.201601.04 . Available at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/vol6/iss1/4 ©2016 by the authors. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons License. JHM is an open access bi-annual journal sponsored by the Claremont Center for the Mathematical Sciences and published by the Claremont Colleges Library | ISSN 2159-8118 | http://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/ The editorial staff of JHM works hard to make sure the scholarship disseminated in JHM is accurate and upholds professional ethical guidelines. However the views and opinions expressed in each published manuscript belong exclusively to the individual contributor(s). The publisher and the editors do not endorse or accept responsibility for them. See https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/policies.html for more information. Explanatory Proofs and Beautiful Proofs Cover Page Footnote My thanks to the organizers of and the participants at the Conference on Beauty and Explanation in Mathematics, University of Umea, Sweden, in March 2014, and to two referees for this journal. This work is available in Journal of Humanistic Mathematics: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/vol6/iss1/4 Explanatory Proofs and Beautiful Proofs1 Marc Lange Department of Philosophy, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, USA [email protected] Abstract This paper concerns the relation between a proof’s beauty and its explanatory power — that is, its capacity to go beyond proving a given theorem to explaining why that theorem holds.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of History
    THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY Georg Hegel THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY Table of Contents THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY................................................................................................................1 Georg Hegel.............................................................................................................................................1 I.Original History....................................................................................................................................1 II. Reflective History..............................................................................................................................2 III. Philosophic History............................................................................................................................5 iii. The course of the World's History..................................................................................................29 i THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY Georg Hegel This page copyright © 2001 Blackmask Online. http://www.blackmask.com • I.Original History • II. Reflective History • III. Philosophic History I.Original History ¤ 1 Of the first kind, the mention of one or two distinguished names will furnish a definite type. To this category belong Herodotus, Thucydides, and other historians of the same order, whose descriptions are for the most part limited to deeds, events, and states of society, which they had before their eyes, and whose spirit they shared. They simply transferred what was passing in the world
    [Show full text]
  • Condition of Creativity
    Scientific Board: Prof. Leonardo Amoroso (Università di Pisa), Prof. Christian Benne (University of Copenhagen), Prof. Andrew Benjamin (Monash University, Melbourne), Prof. Fabio Camilletti (Warwick University), Prof. Luca Crescenzi (Università di Pisa), Prof. Paul Crowther (NUI Galway), Prof. William Marx (Université Paris Ouest Nanterre), Prof. Alexander Nehamas (Princeton University), Prof. Antonio Prete (Università di Siena), Prof. David Roochnik (Boston University), Prof. Antonietta Sanna (Università di Pisa), Prof. Claus Zittel (Stuttgart Universität) Executive Board Matteo Bensi, Danilo Manca (coordinator), Lorenzo Serini, Valentina Serio, Marta Vero Review Board: Alessandra Aloisi, Ester Fuoco, Annamaria Lossi, Nikos Loukidelis, Cathrin Nielsen, Francesco Rossi ODRADEK. Studies in Philosophy of Literature, Aesthetics and New Media Theories. ISSN 2465-1060 [online] Edited by Associazione “Zetesis-Progetto di studi e Dialoghi Filosofici”, via Paoli, 15 - 56126 Pisa. Registered by Agenzia delle Entrate di Pisa, n. 3705, serie III, 23.10.2014 License Creative Commons Odradek. Studies in Philosophy of Literature, Aesthetics and New Media Theories di Zetesis is licensed under a Creative Commons attribution, non-commercial 4.0 International. Further authorization out of this license terms may be available at http://zetesisproject. com or writing to: [email protected]. Layout editor: Stella Ammaturo Volume Editors: Alessandra Aloisi, Danilo Manca Introduction Alessandra Aloisi and Danilo Manca 1. When in Book Ten of the Republic Plato proscribes poetry from the city and refers to a long- standing quarrel between poetry and philosophy, he raises an issue that has since made its mark on the history of Western thought. The aim of this volume is to delve deeper into the original meaning of this quarrel, to evaluate the implications it has had for the Western way of thinking and writing, and to explore the different forms the quarrel has assumed, between poetry and philosophy, between literature and philosophy.
    [Show full text]