Commonsense Psychology: Fodor, Dennett, Baker

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Commonsense Psychology: Fodor, Dennett, Baker COMMONSENSE PSYCHOLOGY: FODOR, DENNETT, BAKER DIANE REBECCA GALL A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY GRADUATE PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY YORK UNIVERSITY TORONTO, ONTARIO APRIL 2014 c DIANE REBECCA GALL, 2014 Abstract The predominant conception of our everyday understanding of other people’s actions is as a commonsense psychology that is a (proto-)scientific theory. A central version of this conception is that this theory takes propositional attitudes as mental states which are causally effective in the production of human purposive action. In this essay, I argue that this central version of our commonsense psychology is mistaken. I take Jerry Fodor’s Psychosemantics as a locus classicus of this view. I examine arguments from Daniel Dennett and Lynne Rudder Baker that Fodor (and others who argue along the same lines as Fodor) make serious errors in being committed to a hyper-realist (i.e., physicalist) conception of mental states and causality. I argue that Fodor does not provide an adequate exposition of how his candidate for a scientific theory that vindicates his version of commonsense psychology accounts for the meaning of a propositional attitude. I further argue that our everyday practices that deploy commonsense psychological concepts are inconsistent with characterising commonsense psychology as a (proto-)theory or as part of a (proto-)science. From this investigation, I conclude that Fodor’s conception of commonsense psychology ii psychology is untenable. Finally, I discuss briefly an alternative that is suggested by the rebuttals of Dennett and Baker that commonsense psychology is better conceived as an non-theoretical explanatory practice that deploys an alternative conception of psycholo- gical causality distinct from physical causality. iii For my wife, Andrea iv Acknowledgements I could not have completed this project, and I nearly did not, without the assistance, friendship, and love of those people who have chosen to associate with me. There are, frankly, far too many and in far too many roles for me to adequately represent how I feel about these people, so I shall only say that if you think that you recognise yourself in somewhere in these pages, then you are assuredly right. If you have been there for me these last years, then you are responsible for my success. I single out my committee—Judith Baker, Ian Hacking, and David Jopling— for the obvious reasons and for extraordinary reasons. I came to them in great need and they offered aid and guidance when they didn’t have to do so. Judith and Ian offered guidance in a time of great personal adversity for them, especially on Judith’s part, and I cannot express the depth of my appreciation to them. Tina Strasbourg supported me, without flag or fail, in far more than just my academic pursuits and she cannot be thanked enough. Speranza Dolgetta, my personal physician, gave me a sense of how to deal with the emotional toll that these academic projects v exact. My father-in-law, Bill McIntosh, has been a source of great strength, comfort, and friendship. Much of this was written under his roof and doing so made the work that much more enjoyable. I would be remiss if I did not thank Len Vandervaart and Terry Chapman for the opportunity to earn a living during the writing of this essay. For Karim Dharamsi, I reserve my utmost appreciation and love. He has been the kind of friend, scholar, and colleague I can only strive to be. The unflagging support and faith that this man can show is truly remarkable and this work would never have been completed without him. My respect for him is immeasurable. The kind of personal support and strength that a family provides cannot be adequately acknowledged. So, to my wife, Andi McIntosh and our daughter, Stephanie, I can only say you both mean the world to me. Diane R. Gall Medicine Hat, AB February 2014 vi Contents Abstract ii Acknowledgements v Preface ix 1 Commonsense Psychology 1 1.1 So, what are we talking about? . 1 1.2 So, what’s the problem? . 11 1.3 A Few Comments about Method . 16 1.4 The Central Commitments of Commonsense Psychology . 19 1.5 Why Fodor? Why now? . 23 2 Fodor: Intentional Realism 28 2.1 Great Theatre . 29 2.2 The Theory Contention . 45 2.3 Causal Power . 54 vii 2.4 Cause and Content . 57 2.5 Conclusion . 71 3 Dennett on Fodor 72 3.1 The Review . 73 3.2 ‘Industrial Strength’ Realism . 90 3.3 Theory versus Craft . 103 3.4 Facta Non Verba . 108 4 Baker: Practical Realism 118 4.1 The Standard View and Practical Realism . 119 4.2 Indeterminacy (Once Again) . 139 4.3 The Myth of Commonsense Psychology . 148 4.4 Conclusions . 156 Bibliography 168 viii Preface A very popular way of engaging with our everyday understanding of each others’ action is to take what might be called a psychological point of view. By this I mean that what people take as the important question is ‘what psychological theory best accounts for what we do when we predict and explain human purposive behaviour?’ My approach will not be by examining the empirical theories and evidence gathered by cognitive scientists, psy- chologists, and other social and computer scientists. It seems to me that the contribution that philosophers (qua philosopher) can have is in the careful examination of the concep- tual landscape of the empirical endeavour. My view is informed by Wittgenstein’s work in that I will be attempting to get a clear overview of just what is going on conceptually with an eye to ‘dissolving’ the problems (that can be so treated). By examining the pre- suppositions upon which the ‘standard’ account of our commonsense psychology is built and the ‘logic’ of those everyday psychological concepts, I seek to show that the central questions regarding our everyday psychological concepts and the way we use them have been misconstrued. I share Wittgenstein’s view that philosophical problems are not typ- ix ically solved by providing alternative theories but by characterising the problem in a way that suggests a dissolution. Philosophical problems can be compared to locks on safes, which can be opened by dialling a certain word or number, so that no force can open the door until just this word has been hit upon, and once it is hit upon any child can open it.1 Another way to put it it is to call my method ordinary language philosophy (OLP). OLP is characterised, by Baz, as “a particular form of Western philosophy—one that seeks to alleviate philo- sophical entanglements and obscurities by means of consideration of the or- dinary and normal uses of philosophers’ worlds, and the worldly conditions that make those uses possible and give them their specific significance [. ] OLP rests on the claim that philosophical difficulties arise when we take our words to express thoughts, or to otherwise carry commitments or implica- tions [. ] in virtue of something called ‘their meaning’, and irrespective of how we mean or may reasonably be found to mean them (which here just means irrespective of how we use or may reasonably found to use them).”2 There are a couple of things that this essay is not. It is not an attempt to vindicate Wittgenstein’s philosophy or metaphilosophy. I am very sympathetic to Wittgenstein’s methods and aims, but I do not directly rely upon his arguments. The most important reason I have chosen to avoid this way is that the interpretation of Wittgenstein’s work is itself a very difficult and often controversial task. 1. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Big Typescript: TS 213 (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2012) (hereafter cited as BT). 2. Avner Baz, When Words are Called for: A defense of ordinary language philosophy (Harvard University Press, 2012), 2. x This essay is also not a work in cognitive science or psychology. In that respect, I am following Wittgenstein’s adage that philosophy leaves everything as it is.3 I take Wittgenstein to be saying that our everyday understanding is left as it is. If something changes, it is our attitude towards that everyday understanding. I am going to argue by re-arranging what we already accept and will leave the empirical theory-building to those better disposed to do so. As such, I will not be evaluating the empirical evidence or reviewing the empirical experimental results of psychological or cognitive scientific theories. I am concerned with the conceptual presuppositions that inform the literature and those presuppositions are most readily seen in those very first arguments about the nature of common-sense psychology, so it is there I begin. I hope to be able to provide a few of the turns needed to unlock the safe. *** Our investigation is a grammatical one. Such an investigation sheds light on our problem by clearing misunderstandings away. Misunderstandings concerning the use of words, caused, among other things, by certain analogies between the forms of expression in different regions of language.4 3. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Revised 4th, ed. P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009), x120 (hereafter cited as PI). 4. PI, x90. xi 1 Commonsense Psychology How does the philosophical problem about mental processes and states and about behaviourism arise?—The first step is the one that altogether escapes notice. We talk of processes and states and leave their nature undecided. So we have to deny the yet uncompre- hended process in the yet uncomprehended medium. And now it looks as if we had denied mental processes.
Recommended publications
  • Mind and World: Beyond the Externalism/Internalism Debate
    Research Proposal Mind and World: Beyond the Externalism/Internalism Debate Sanjit Chakraborty Research Scholar Department of Philosophy Jadavpur University Background For the last few years the concept of the natural kind terms has haunted me. My main concern has been regarding the location of the meaning of these terms. Are meanings of the natural kind terms in the head or in the world? This question has been the most pressing in Philosophy of Mind and Philosophy of Language. I have realized that we cannot separate mind from the world. I had in the beginning only a layman‟s conception regarding mind, meaning and the world. When I entered the field of philosophy inspired by Hilary Putnam, I found that semantic externalism is a vexing issue involving a vast area. The location of content is at the core of the metaphysical debate regarding internalism and externalism in the sense that internalists believe that mental proprieties are intrinsic only if they preserve across world identity of internal replicas. Externalism is opposed to this thinking. For externalists, mental properties are in many cases dependent on physical or social environment. The linguistic strategy also maintains a difference between internalism and externalism regarding the mental content. Descriptivism focuses on general terms that consist in descriptive content and leads to mode of presentation of reference through sense. Besides, the causal theory of reference refutes descriptivism to ensure that there is a causal chain of reference between words and 1 objects that help us to identify agent‟s thought through an identification of its relation with external environment.
    [Show full text]
  • Kedwards CV Inprogress.Pages
    Philosophy Department 541 Hall of Languages Syracuse University Syracuse, NY 13244-1170 [email protected] Kevan Edwards 31 5-416-2700 (cell) ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS 2008 - Assistant Professor, Syracuse University 2006-2008 Assistant Professor, University of Kansas EDUCATION 2000-2006 Ph.D. in Philosophy, Rutgers University, October 2006 2000 B.A., Specialist in Philosophy, with high distinction, University of Toronto DISSERTATION Oct. 2006 Referentialism without Compromise: Semantics at the Intersection of Mind and Language Committee: Jerry Fodor, Barry Loewer, Stephen Neale, Georges Rey PUBLICATIONS 2014 "Keeping (Direct) Reference in Mind". Noûs 48(2), pp. 342-367. 2013 “Concepts”. Oxford Bibliographies (published online Sept. 30, 2013) http:// www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/ obo-9780195396577-0220.xml 2012 “Review of ‘The Extended Mind’, Edited by Richard Menary.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy: 1-3. 2011 “Higher-level Concepts and Their Heterogeneous Implementations: A Polemical Response to Edouard Machery’s Doing Without Concepts”. Philosophical Psychology, 24(1), 119-133. 2010 “Review of David Thompson, Daniel Dennett”. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=20167. 2010 “Unity Amidst Heterogeneity in Theories of Concepts”. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2-3), 210-211. [Commentary on Machery, Doing Without Concepts (OUP)] 2010 “Concept Referentialism and the Role of Empty Concepts”. Mind & Language, 25(1), 89-118. !1 of !6 2009 “Referring When Push Comes to Shove”. In New Waves in the Philosophy of Language (pp. 60-86). New York: Palgrave Macmillan. 2009 “What Concepts Do”. Synthese, 170(2), 289-310. PRESENTATIONS / COMMENTS / CHAIRED SESSIONS 2014 “The Concept of a Concept, in Philosophy, Psychology, and (Hopefully) Beyond.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Jerry Fodor, the Mind Doesn't Work That Way
    The Mind Doesn't Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology (review) Ray Jackendoff Language, Volume 78, Number 1, March 2002, pp. 164-170 (Review) Published by Linguistic Society of America DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2002.0024 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/19286 [ Access provided at 10 May 2020 20:12 GMT from Linguistic Society of America ] 164 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 78, NUMBER 1 (2002) malist studies as the brief summary of the chapters has hopefully shown. All articles complement the work of the festschrift’s honoree, are well-written, and contain interesting data as well as intriguing analyses, pushing the minimalist spirit further ahead. REFERENCES BOSˇKOVIC´,Zˇ ELJKO. 1994. D-structure, theta-criterion, and movement into theta-positions. Linguistic Analysis 24.247–86. MM. 1997. Superiority effects with multiple wh-fronting in Serbo-Croatian. Lingua 102.1–20. CHOMSKY,NOAM. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. MM. 2001. Derivation by phase. Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. by Michael Kenstowicz, 1–52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. GRIMSHAW,JANE, and ARMIN MESTER. 1988. Light verbs and ␪-marking. Linguistic Inquiry 19.205–32. HORNSTEIN,NORBERT. 1995. Logical form: From GB to minimalism. Oxford: Blackwell. KAYNE,RICHARD S. 1994. The antisymmetry of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ZAS Ja¨gerstr. 10–11 10117 Berlin Germany [[email protected]] The mind doesn’t work that way: Thescopeand limits of computational psychology. By JERRY FODOR. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2000. Pp. 126. Reviewed by RAY JACKENDOFF, Brandeis University* As has been his wont in recent years, Jerry Fodor offers here a statement of deepest pessimism about the possibility of doing cognitive science except in a very limited class of subdomains.
    [Show full text]
  • Donald Davidson: Meaning, Truth, Language, and Reality, by Ernest Lepore and Kirk Ludwig
    446 Book Reviews claim that should be accepted independently of whatever moral fiction one accepts. At any rate, all those who accept any moral fiction whatsoever should also accept the impermissibility of intransigence. Now, this is starting to look Downloaded from suspiciously like a fiction-independent moral truth. And if there is one such, why not more? Indeed, if there are any substantive constraints on acceptable moral fictions then there will inevitably be substantive moral propositions that are true in all allowable fictions. But then fictionalism is starting to look a bit like good old-fashioned moral realism. http://mind.oxfordjournals.org/ Moral Fictionalism is not an easy read. This is partly, but not entirely, a function of the inherent difficulty of the subject matter and the novelty of Kal- deron’s position. But it is also a function of the fundamental tension implicit in fictionalism: of wanting to take morality seriously, but not being quite able to do so. In Kalderon’s hands, this plays out as the conflict between the imper- sonal and absolute authority of morality and the permissibility of a personal and recalcitrant moral intransigence. The book starts out by boldly affirming both and drawing some remarkable consequences, but it ends up, somewhat uneasily, affirming authority and retracting intransigence. In spite of this at Indiana University Libraries Technical Services/Serials Acquisitions on October 6, 2014 uneasy resting place, Kalderon advances the field in two important ways. Firstly, in combining factualism with non-cognitivism he carves out a radically new version of hermeneutic fictionalism. Secondly, his account focuses an interesting new light on the nature of non-cognitivism and that cluster of arguments directed against non-cognitivism known as the Frege-Geach objec- tion.
    [Show full text]
  • Generics Analysis Canberra Plan.Pdf
    Philosophical Perspectives, 26, Philosophy of Mind, 2012 CONCEPTS, ANALYSIS, GENERICS AND THE CANBERRA PLAN1 Mark Johnston Princeton University Sarah-Jane Leslie2 Princeton University My objection to meanings in the theory of meaning is not that they are abstract or that their identity conditions are obscure, but that they have no demonstrated use.3 —Donald Davidson “Truth and Meaning” From time to time it is said that defenders of conceptual analysis would do well to peruse the best empirically supported psychological theories of concepts, and then tailor their notions of conceptual analysis to those theories of what concepts are.4 As against this, there is an observation — traceable at least as far back to Gottlob Frege’s attack on psychologism in “The Thought” — that might well discourage philosophers from spending a week or two with the empirical psychological literature. The psychological literature is fundamentally concerned with mental representations, with the mental processes of using these in classification, characterization and inference, and with the sub-personal bases of these processes. The problem is that for many philosophers, concepts could not be mental items. (Jerry Fodor is a notable exception, we discuss him below.) We would like to set out this difference of focus in some detail and then propose a sort of translation manual, or at least a crucial translational hint, one which helps in moving between philosophical and psychological treatments of concepts. Then we will consider just how, given the translation, the relevant
    [Show full text]
  • Jerry Fodor · Why Pigs Don't Have Wings: the Case Against Natural Selection
    This site uses cookies. By continuing to browse this site you are agreeing to our use of cookies. (More Information) × LOG IN REGISTER FOR ONLINE ACCESS Search the LRB LATEST ARCHIVE BOOKSHOP CONTACT US ABOUT THE LRB SUBSCRIBE INTRODUCTION BACK ISSUES CONTRIBUTORS CATEGORIES LETTERS AUDIO VIDEO Vol. 29 No. 20 · 18 October 2007 facebook214 twitter 14 share email letter cite print pages 19-22 | 5138 words ‘We are larger | smaller now at our Why Pigs Don’t Have Wings most unequal Jerry Fodor since 1940’ You are invited to read this free essay from the London Review of Books. Ben Rawlence Register for free and enjoy 24 hours of access to the entire LRB archive @ LRB blog Jerry Fodor has of over 12,500 essays and reviews. almost finished a book, with Zenon Pylyshyn, Die Meistersinger is, by Wagner’s standards, quite a cheerful opera. The action turns on comedy’s staple, the marriage plot: get the hero and the heroine safely and truly wed about the semantics of with at least a presumption of happiness ever after. There are cross-currents and mental representation. undercurrents that make Meistersinger’s libretto subtle in ways that the librettos of He teaches at Rutgers. operas usually aren’t. But for once Nietzsche is nowhere in sight and nobody dies; the territory is closer to The Barber of Seville than to The Ring. Yet, in the first scene of Act 3, the avuncular Hans Sachs, whose benevolent interventions smooth the lovers’ MORE BY THIS CONTRIBUTOR course, delivers an aria of bitter reflection on the human condition.
    [Show full text]
  • Ronald Endicott, “Multiple Realizability” (Final Draft) Forthcoming in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2Nd Edition, Macmillan Press, 2005
    Ronald Endicott, “Multiple Realizability” (Final Draft) Forthcoming in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition, MacMillan Press, 2005 Multiple realizability is a key issue in debates over the nature of mind and reduction in the sciences. The subject consists of two parts: “multiplicity” and “realizability.” “Multiplicity” designates a kind of variability in the mechanism and materials from which a particular type of thing can be made. “Realizability” designates a specific relation that exists when there is the stated variability. Realizability Apart from the broad folk notion of realization meaning that a thing is “made real,” philosophers apply several technical notions to paradigm cases such computational states realized by engineering states, minds realized by brains, and persons realized by their bodies. The technical notions fall into three broad traditions: “mathematical,” “logico- semantic,” and “metaphysical.” The mathematical tradition equates realization with a form of mapping between objects. Generally speaking, x mathematically realizes y because elements of y map onto elements of x. The notion is useful for many purposes, for example, when constructing a formal model of a particular domain. However, since mapping extends to models as well as reality, it fails to distinguish between “simulated” versus “genuine” realizations. Heavenly stars can be mapped onto grains of sand, but grains of sand do not realize heavenly stars in any genuine sense. Similarly, the mental states described by a cognitive program can be mapped onto unthinking groups of things, but unthinking groups of things do not realize mental states in any genuine sense (Block, 1978). Hence, to capture what is essential to genuine realization, William Lycan (1987) adds ideas about evolutionary function, while David Chalmers (1994) emphasizes facts about causal structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Functionalism, Computationalism, and Mental States
    Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 35 (2004) 811–833 www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa Functionalism, computationalism, and mental states Gualtiero Piccinini Department of Philosophy, Washington University, Campus Box 1073, One Brookings Dr., St. Louis, MO 63130-4899, USA Received 25 November 2003; received in revised form 24 February 2004 Abstract Some philosophers have conflated functionalism and computationalism. I reconstruct how this came about and uncover two assumptions that made the conflation possible. They are the assumptions that (i) psychological functional analyses are computational descriptions and (ii) everything may be described as performing computations. I argue that, if we want to improve our understanding of both the metaphysics of mental states and the functional rela- tions between them, we should reject these assumptions. # 2004 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Keywords: Functionalism; Computationalism; Computational functionalism; Mental states; Computa- tional theory of mind; Functional analysis 1. Introduction Particularly striking in retrospect was the widespread failure to distinguish the computational program in psychology from the functionalist program in meta- physics . (For an instance where the two are run together, see Fodor 1968[b]). (Fodor, 2000, p. 105 n. 4) Fodor is right: some philosophers of mind have conflated functionalism and computationalism about mental states. To a first approximation, functionalism is the metaphysical view that mental states are individuated by their functional rela- tions with mental inputs, outputs, and other mental states. Functionalism per se is E-mail address: [email protected] (G. Piccinini). 0039-3681/$ - see front matter # 2004 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2004.02.003 812 G.Piccinini / Stud.Hist.Phil.Sci.35 (2004) 811–833 neutral on how those functional relations should be characterized.
    [Show full text]
  • A Diatribe on Jerry Fodor's the Mind Doesn't Work That Way1
    PSYCHE: http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/ Yes, It Does: A Diatribe on Jerry Fodor’s The Mind Doesn’t Work that Way1 Susan Schneider Department of Philosophy University of Pennsylvania 423 Logan Hall 249 S. 36th Street Philadelphia, PA 19104-6304 [email protected] © S. Schneider 2007 PSYCHE 13 (1), April 2007 REVIEW OF: J. Fodor, 2000. The Mind Doesn’t Work that Way. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 144 pages, ISBN-10: 0262062127 Abstract: The Mind Doesn’t Work That Way is an expose of certain theoretical problems in cognitive science, and in particular, problems that concern the Classical Computational Theory of Mind (CTM). The problems that Fodor worries plague CTM divide into two kinds, and both purport to show that the success of cognitive science will likely be limited to the modules. The first sort of problem concerns what Fodor has called “global properties”; features that a mental sentence has which depend on how the sentence interacts with a larger plan (i.e., set of sentences), rather than the type identity of the sentence alone. The second problem concerns what many have called, “The Relevance Problem”: the problem of whether and how humans determine what is relevant in a computational manner. However, I argue that the problem that Fodor believes global properties pose for CTM is a non-problem, and that further, while the relevance problem is a serious research issue, it does not justify the grim view that cognitive science, and CTM in particular, will likely fail to explain cognition. 1. Introduction The current project, it seems to me, is to understand what various sorts of theories of mind can and can't do, and what it is about them in virtue of which they can or can't do it.
    [Show full text]
  • Empiricism, Cognitive Science, and the Novel
    Empiricism, Cognitive Science, and the Novel Jonathan Kramnick Rutgers University “I see into minds, you see,” the robot continued, “and you have no idea how complicated they are. I can’t begin to understand everything because my own mind has so little in common with them—but I try, and your novels help.” —Isaac Asimov, Liar! No one literary form has a proprietary stake in the mind, but as genres go the novel has since its inception taken remarkable interest in mental states. Among other things, eighteenth-century fiction is so much writing about the mind: about how thoughts represent things, cause other thoughts to happen, or lead to actions. The same might be said for empiricism. Seventeenth- and eighteenth-century philosophy paid unusual attention to the content of minds and the nature of ideas, to “human understanding” as Locke and Hume put it. While the connection between empiricism and the rise of the novel is a touch- stone of literary studies, with a venerable tradition of scholarship dating back to the beginnings of the profession, only recently have critics drawn upon phi- losophy of mind and cognitive science to talk about the way in which thinking takes shape in particular works from the period.1 This is of course not so much of a surprise, since criticism is as a rule skeptical of framing older texts with present-day models. The risk is one of anachronism or universalism, either shoehorning recalcitrant descriptions of the mind into our current language of cognition or locating both within a timeless and unchanging account of the psyche.
    [Show full text]
  • On Physical Multiple Realization
    ON PHYSICAL MULTIPLE REALIZATION BY RONALD P. ENDICOTT Perhaps no argument has done more to set the direction of contemporary philosophy of mind than the “multiple realizability argument.” First championed by Hilary Putnam and later reformulated by Jerry Fodor, the argument begins with the observation that a given psychological property can be realized by any number of diverse physical systems, and then ends with the conclusion that psychological properties are irreducible vis-à-vis the physical sciences.^ Its target, in other words, is type physicalism and the unity of science, as traditionally conceived. According to one popular criticism, however, the multiple realizability argument has been discredited by the fact that physical properties are also multiply realized} But this, I believe, is a mistake. While the criticism does serve to bring a number of important issues into better focus, it can be shown that the facts about physical multiple realization are perfectly consistent with the Putnam-Fodor style argument, and that, when such facts are rightly understood, they do not vitiate the original point about the irreducibility of psychological properties. /. Multiple Realization In spite of much talk about multiple realization, philosophers have generally been content to leave this central concept unanalyzed. I shall try to remedy this situation by indicating the two most salient features of the concept. First, there is the idea that a property is realized by a number of diverse states, which I take to mean that different state types can provide lawfully sufficient conditions for the instantiation of the multiply realized property. And second, there is the idea that among this range of diverse Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (1989) 212-224 0279-0750/89/0300-0212 $01.30 Copyright © 1989 University of Southern California ON PHYSICAL MULTIPLE REALIZATION 213 states, there are no lawfully necessary and sufficient conditions for the instantiation of that property.
    [Show full text]
  • Anti-Reductionism Slaps Back Author(S): Ned Block Source: Philosophical Perspectives , 1997, Vol
    Anti-Reductionism Slaps Back Author(s): Ned Block Source: Philosophical Perspectives , 1997, Vol. 11, Mind, Causation, and World (1997), pp. 107-132 Published by: Ridgeview Publishing Company Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2216126 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophical Perspectives This content downloaded from 128.122.149.96 on Wed, 07 Apr 2021 20:45:57 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Philosophical Perspectives, 11, Mind, Causation, and World, 1997 ANTI-REDUCTIONISM SLAPS BACK Ned Block New York University For nearly thirty years, there has been a consensus (at least in English- speaking countries) that reductionism is a mistake and that there are autonomous special sciences. This consensus has been based on an argument from multiple realizability. But Jaegwon Kim has argued persuasively that the multiple realiz- ability argument is flawed.' I will sketch the recent history of the debate, arguing that much-but not all-of the anti-reductionist consensus survives Kim's cri- tique. This paper was originally titled "Anti-Reductionism Strikes Back", but in the course of writing the paper, I came to think that the concepts used in the debate would not serve either position very well.
    [Show full text]