Reverse Mathematics on Lattice Ordered Groups

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Reverse Mathematics on Lattice Ordered Groups Reverse Mathematics on Lattice Ordered Groups Alexander S. Rogalski, Ph.D. University of Connecticut, 2007 Several theorems about lattice-ordered groups are analyzed. RCA0 is sufficient to prove the induced order on a quotient of `-groups and the Riesz Decomposition Theorem. WKL0 is equivalent to the statement “An abelian group G is torsion free if and only if it is lattice-orderable.” ACA0 is equivalent to the existence of various substructures: the join of two convex `-subgroups, the convex closure of an `-subgroup, the polar subgroup X⊥ of an `-subgroup X, and a sequence of values {V (g): g 6= e}. The standard proof of Holland’s Embedding Theorem uses ACA0. Holland’s Theorem is equivalent to the existence of a sequence of excluding prime subgroups {P (g): g 6= e}, and the existence of such a sequence is provable in WKL0 when G is abelian. Reverse Mathematics on Lattice Ordered Groups Alexander S. Rogalski B.S., Marlboro College, Marlboro, VT, 2002 M.S., University of Connecticut, Storrs, CT, 2004 A Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fullfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy at the University of Connecticut 2007 Copyright by Alexander S. Rogalski 2007 APPROVAL PAGE Doctor of Philosophy Dissertation Reverse Mathematics on Lattice Ordered Groups Presented by Alexander S. Rogalski, B.S., M.S. Major Advisor David Reed Solomon Associate Advisor Manuel Lerman Associate Advisor Joseph Miller University of Connecticut 2007 ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS First, I wish to acknowledge Old Joe, my banjo. I brought Old Joe to the annual Math Department picnic, where Reed excitedly introduced himself and suggested that we play music sometime. We managed to accomplish this a few times, despite the pressing obligations of academia and graduate studies. Reed truly deserves my thanks for being a superb advisor. Tricia, you are wonderful, and I thank you for believing in me when I feared it would take another year to finish. I also thank our daughter, Georgia, for being born and giving me, among other numerous joys, a considerable motivation to graduate. Last but not least, I wish to thank my family for their considerable and constant support. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS 1. Introduction ................................ 1 1.1 Background . 1 1.2 Notation . 6 1.3 Reverse Math . 6 1.4 Lattices, Lattice-ordered groups . 7 1.5 Fundamental Examples . 8 2. Preliminary Results ........................... 12 2.1 Definition of `-group . 13 2.2 Definition of an `-group for Reverse Math . 19 2.3 Basic computation in `-groups . 20 2.4 The Riesz Decomposition Theorem . 26 3. More Results ............................... 30 3.1 Identifying groups which are lattice-orderable . 30 3.2 Convex `-subgroups and Right Cosets . 34 4. Convexity Results and Reversals for Substructure Existences . 38 4.1 Closure Operations . 38 4.2 Existence of the subgroup generated by A, B. 44 4.3 Existence of the convex closure of an `-subgroup H . 45 iv 4.4 Existence of the convex `-subgroup generated by convex `-subgroups A, B................................... 47 4.4.1 Construction . 50 4.4.2 Verification . 52 4.5 Existence of the Polar X⊥......................... 54 5. Prime Subgroups and Values ..................... 62 5.1 Prime Subgroups . 62 5.2 Values . 65 5.3 Existence of a Sequence of Values . 67 5.4 Existence of a Sequence of Excluding Primes . 70 6. Holland’s Embedding Theorem .................... 78 6.1 Summary of Original Proof of Holland’s Theorem . 79 6.2 Proof of Holland’s Theorem using excluding primes . 81 6.3 A Reversal . 84 Bibliography 86 v LIST OF FIGURES 4.1 The Root System Γ . 56 5.1 Initial Subtree of T ∗ ........................... 77 vi Chapter 1 Introduction 1.1 Background It is a relatively common occurrence for a student of mathematics to read or write a proof which, at a key step, uses Zorn’s Lemma or an equivalent principle to prove the existence of a set with certain desired properties. Until one is used to doing so, it can seem odd to call on a result from set theory in the middle of a proof which otherwise only requires results in Algebra. One might wonder, “Does one really need something as strong as Zorn’s Lemma to build this set, or could it be done directly?” Reverse Mathematics is a subfield of logic which tries to answer questions like this by finding exactly which set-theoretic axioms are truly necessary to prove a theorem. The usual axioms of set theory, ZFC or ZF, are quite strong. We can make finer distinctions by restricting ourselves to “countable” mathematics and axiom systems which, though weaker, are still able to prove many classical theorems of mathematics. More formally, the setting for Reverse Math is the 1 2 language of second order arithmetic Z2. In this language, we have symbols +, ·, <, 0, and 1, and the usual axioms defining them in the natural numbers N, set membership ∈, and two types of variables: number variables which are intended to range over N and set variables which are intended to range over subsets X ⊂ N. A typical investigation in Reverse Math goes like this: 1. Pick a theorem T hm to study. 2. Look at a textbook proof of T hm and find a set S of axioms for Z2 that are suitable for the proof of T hm. 3. See if it is possible to prove the axioms of S using T hm. (This is why it’s called Reverse Math.) We need some amount of set theory to do such a proof as in step 3, and we typically work in a weak base system called RCA0, which strikes a balance between being strong enough to allow basic proofs and weak enough to keep the set-theoretic impact reasonably minimal. Generally, one of two things happens. If we are able to prove S from T hm, this tells us that S is the weakest axiom system capable of proving T hm. (If a strictly weaker system S0 proved T hm, S0 would then imply S, an impossibility!) In this case we have a proof of T hm from S and a reversal of T hm to S, and we say the two are equivalent over RCA0. If, on the other hand, attempts to prove S from T hm aren’t working out, we look for a new proof of T hm that uses weaker axioms Sˆ and repeat the process, trying 3 to prove Sˆ using T hm. The “full-blown” set existence axiom scheme for Z2 consists of axioms ∃X∀n(n ∈ X ↔ ϕ(n)), where ϕ is any formula in the language Z2 not men- tioning X. This scheme basically says: if we have a formula in Z2, the set of numbers which satisfy it exists. This full collection is too strong to be interesting for Reverse Math, but it contains five particular subsystems (subcollections of axioms) and most theorems successfully analyzed are equivalent to one of them. 1 In order of increasing strength, they are: RCA0, WKL0, ACA0, ATR0, and Π1-CA0. In this dissertation, only the first three come into play. RCA0 is the usual base system over which we prove equivalences, and its set 0 comprehension scheme is limited to ∆1 formulas. (We also include axioms allow- 0 ing Σ1 induction.) The next strongest, WKL0, consists of all the axioms of RCA0 plus the Weak K¨onig’s Lemma axiom saying “If T is an infinite binary tree, then T has an infinite path”. WKL0 is sometimes sufficient where a standard proof uses Zorn’s Lemma, though there are notable cases where it does not suffice. For example, in the theory of commutative rings, the existence of a nontrivial prime ideal is equivalent to WKL0. The existence of a prime ideal is usually proved as a corollary to the existence of a maximal ideal. Since the existence of a maximal ideal requires ACA0, this is a case where a set-theoretically “simpler” existence proof for a prime ideal needed to be found. ACA0, or Arithmetical Comprehension, is the strongest subsystem used in this study, obtained by allowing set comprehen- 4 sion using arithmetical formulas – those which may have any number of number quantifiers in its definition but no set quantifiers. The subsystem of axioms to which a given theorem is equivalent is a measure of the set-theoretic complexity of the theorem. A theorem which requires only weak set existence axioms is considered less complex than one which requires a lot of complicated assumptions, i.e., a very strong axiom system. Knowing which axioms are necessary is particularly of interest to those working on related problems in Computable Algebra or Combinatorics. For instance, an effective analogue of a theorem is likely true if the theorem is provable in RCA0. As an example, RCA0 suffices to prove that the quotient of a commutative ring by a maximal ideal is a field. Thus, given such a ring and a maximal ideal in a computable presentation, one can effectively form the quotient field. In contrast, maximal ideals generally require ACA0 and it is not the case that, given a computable commutative ring, one can always effectively find a maximal ideal. Knowing that maximal and prime ideals respectively require ACA0 and WKL0 also enables one to make distinctions between the computational “difficulty” of obtaining a maximal or prime ideal in a computable ring. That is, it is both set-theoretically easier and computationally easier to obtain a prime ideal than a maximal one. This particular project in Reverse Math concerns theorems about lattice- ordered groups. These groups are not necessarily exotic. For example: an abelian 5 group G is lattice-orderable if and only if it is torsion-free.
Recommended publications
  • On the Lattice Structure of Quantum Logic
    BULL. AUSTRAL. MATH. SOC. MOS 8106, *8IOI, 0242 VOL. I (1969), 333-340 On the lattice structure of quantum logic P. D. Finch A weak logical structure is defined as a set of boolean propositional logics in which one can define common operations of negation and implication. The set union of the boolean components of a weak logical structure is a logic of propositions which is an orthocomplemented poset, where orthocomplementation is interpreted as negation and the partial order as implication. It is shown that if one can define on this logic an operation of logical conjunction which has certain plausible properties, then the logic has the structure of an orthomodular lattice. Conversely, if the logic is an orthomodular lattice then the conjunction operation may be defined on it. 1. Introduction The axiomatic development of non-relativistic quantum mechanics leads to a quantum logic which has the structure of an orthomodular poset. Such a structure can be derived from physical considerations in a number of ways, for example, as in Gunson [7], Mackey [77], Piron [72], Varadarajan [73] and Zierler [74]. Mackey [77] has given heuristic arguments indicating that this quantum logic is, in fact, not just a poset but a lattice and that, in particular, it is isomorphic to the lattice of closed subspaces of a separable infinite dimensional Hilbert space. If one assumes that the quantum logic does have the structure of a lattice, and not just that of a poset, it is not difficult to ascertain what sort of further assumptions lead to a "coordinatisation" of the logic as the lattice of closed subspaces of Hilbert space, details will be found in Jauch [8], Piron [72], Varadarajan [73] and Zierler [74], Received 13 May 1969.
    [Show full text]
  • ORTHOGONAL GROUP of CERTAIN INDEFINITE LATTICE Chang Heon Kim* 1. Introduction Given an Even Lattice M in a Real Quadratic Space
    JOURNAL OF THE CHUNGCHEONG MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 20, No. 1, March 2007 ORTHOGONAL GROUP OF CERTAIN INDEFINITE LATTICE Chang Heon Kim* Abstract. We compute the special orthogonal group of certain lattice of signature (2; 1). 1. Introduction Given an even lattice M in a real quadratic space of signature (2; n), Borcherds lifting [1] gives a multiplicative correspondence between vec- tor valued modular forms F of weight 1¡n=2 with values in C[M 0=M] (= the group ring of M 0=M) and meromorphic modular forms on complex 0 varieties (O(2) £ O(n))nO(2; n)=Aut(M; F ). Here NM denotes the dual lattice of M, O(2; n) is the orthogonal group of M R and Aut(M; F ) is the subgroup of Aut(M) leaving the form F stable under the natural action of Aut(M) on M 0=M. In particular, if the signature of M is (2; 1), then O(2; 1) ¼ H: O(2) £ O(1) and Borcherds' theory gives a lifting of vector valued modular form of weight 1=2 to usual one variable modular form on Aut(M; F ). In this sense in order to work out Borcherds lifting it is important to ¯nd appropriate lattice on which our wanted modular group acts. In this article we will show: Theorem 1.1. Let M be a 3-dimensional even lattice of all 2 £ 2 integral symmetric matrices, that is, ½µ ¶ ¾ AB M = j A; B; C 2 Z BC Received December 30, 2006. 2000 Mathematics Subject Classi¯cation: Primary 11F03, 11H56.
    [Show full text]
  • ON the SHELLABILITY of the ORDER COMPLEX of the SUBGROUP LATTICE of a FINITE GROUP 1. Introduction We Will Show That the Order C
    TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 353, Number 7, Pages 2689{2703 S 0002-9947(01)02730-1 Article electronically published on March 12, 2001 ON THE SHELLABILITY OF THE ORDER COMPLEX OF THE SUBGROUP LATTICE OF A FINITE GROUP JOHN SHARESHIAN Abstract. We show that the order complex of the subgroup lattice of a finite group G is nonpure shellable if and only if G is solvable. A by-product of the proof that nonsolvable groups do not have shellable subgroup lattices is the determination of the homotopy types of the order complexes of the subgroup lattices of many minimal simple groups. 1. Introduction We will show that the order complex of the subgroup lattice of a finite group G is (nonpure) shellable if and only if G is solvable. The proof of nonshellability in the nonsolvable case involves the determination of the homotopy type of the order complexes of the subgroup lattices of many minimal simple groups. We begin with some history and basic definitions. It is assumed that the reader is familiar with some of the rudiments of algebraic topology and finite group theory. No distinction will be made between an abstract simplicial complex ∆ and an arbitrary geometric realization of ∆. Maximal faces of a simplicial complex ∆ will be called facets of ∆. Definition 1.1. A simplicial complex ∆ is shellable if the facets of ∆ can be ordered σ1;::: ,σn so that for all 1 ≤ i<k≤ n thereexistssome1≤ j<kand x 2 σk such that σi \ σk ⊆ σj \ σk = σk nfxg. The list σ1;::: ,σn is called a shelling of ∆.
    [Show full text]
  • 7 LATTICE POINTS and LATTICE POLYTOPES Alexander Barvinok
    7 LATTICE POINTS AND LATTICE POLYTOPES Alexander Barvinok INTRODUCTION Lattice polytopes arise naturally in algebraic geometry, analysis, combinatorics, computer science, number theory, optimization, probability and representation the- ory. They possess a rich structure arising from the interaction of algebraic, convex, analytic, and combinatorial properties. In this chapter, we concentrate on the the- ory of lattice polytopes and only sketch their numerous applications. We briefly discuss their role in optimization and polyhedral combinatorics (Section 7.1). In Section 7.2 we discuss the decision problem, the problem of finding whether a given polytope contains a lattice point. In Section 7.3 we address the counting problem, the problem of counting all lattice points in a given polytope. The asymptotic problem (Section 7.4) explores the behavior of the number of lattice points in a varying polytope (for example, if a dilation is applied to the polytope). Finally, in Section 7.5 we discuss problems with quantifiers. These problems are natural generalizations of the decision and counting problems. Whenever appropriate we address algorithmic issues. For general references in the area of computational complexity/algorithms see [AB09]. We summarize the computational complexity status of our problems in Table 7.0.1. TABLE 7.0.1 Computational complexity of basic problems. PROBLEM NAME BOUNDED DIMENSION UNBOUNDED DIMENSION Decision problem polynomial NP-hard Counting problem polynomial #P-hard Asymptotic problem polynomial #P-hard∗ Problems with quantifiers unknown; polynomial for ∀∃ ∗∗ NP-hard ∗ in bounded codimension, reduces polynomially to volume computation ∗∗ with no quantifier alternation, polynomial time 7.1 INTEGRAL POLYTOPES IN POLYHEDRAL COMBINATORICS We describe some combinatorial and computational properties of integral polytopes.
    [Show full text]
  • INTEGER POINTS and THEIR ORTHOGONAL LATTICES 2 to Remove the Congruence Condition
    INTEGER POINTS ON SPHERES AND THEIR ORTHOGONAL LATTICES MENNY AKA, MANFRED EINSIEDLER, AND URI SHAPIRA (WITH AN APPENDIX BY RUIXIANG ZHANG) Abstract. Linnik proved in the late 1950’s the equidistribution of in- teger points on large spheres under a congruence condition. The congru- ence condition was lifted in 1988 by Duke (building on a break-through by Iwaniec) using completely different techniques. We conjecture that this equidistribution result also extends to the pairs consisting of a vector on the sphere and the shape of the lattice in its orthogonal complement. We use a joining result for higher rank diagonalizable actions to obtain this conjecture under an additional congruence condition. 1. Introduction A theorem of Legendre, whose complete proof was given by Gauss in [Gau86], asserts that an integer D can be written as a sum of three squares if and only if D is not of the form 4m(8k + 7) for some m, k N. Let D = D N : D 0, 4, 7 mod8 and Z3 be the set of primitive∈ vectors { ∈ 6≡ } prim in Z3. Legendre’s Theorem also implies that the set 2 def 3 2 S (D) = v Zprim : v 2 = D n ∈ k k o is non-empty if and only if D D. This important result has been refined in many ways. We are interested∈ in the refinement known as Linnik’s problem. Let S2 def= x R3 : x = 1 . For a subset S of rational odd primes we ∈ k k2 set 2 D(S)= D D : for all p S, D mod p F× .
    [Show full text]
  • ORDERED GROUPS VM Kopytov UDC 512.545
    ORDERED GROUPS V. M. Kopytov UDC 512.545 In the paper "Ordered groups" there is given a survey of papers on ordered groups, reviewed in RZh Mathematika in 1975-1980. Starting in 1963 there occurred a qualitative jump in the theory of ordered groups, evoked by the inten- sive investigation of linerarly ordered (l. o. ) groups and the development of the theory of groups of automor- phisms of I.o. sets. As a result many sections of the theory of lattice ordered groups (l-groups) acquired an orderly and organized form, and profound classificationalresults were obtained in them. A natural con- sequence of this was the appearance in the recent past of several monographs on the theory of ordered groups, in particular, the books of Kokorin and Kopytov [26] (English translation [154]), Mura and Rhemtulla [182], Bigard, Keimel, and Wolfenstein [78]. The present survey is written on the materials of the Ref. Zh. "Matematika," mainly for the years 1975-1980, and reflects practicallyall directions of development of the theory of ordered groups with some accent on linearly and lattice ordered groups, which is explained by the intensivity and diversity of the inves- tigations in these domains. In the survey there are included some results reviewed in the years 1970-1974 and not reflected in previous surveys of the collection "Algebra. Topology. Geometry" of the annual 'Itogi Nauki i Tekhniki" [12, 13] or the book [26]. i. Linearly Ordered Groups Investigations on 1. o. groups were carried out mainly in the directions designated at the end of the six- ties and formulated in [26].
    [Show full text]
  • Lattice-Ordered Loops and Quasigroupsl
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector JOIJRNALOFALGEBRA 16, 218-226(1970) Lattice-Ordered Loops and Quasigroupsl TREVOREVANS Matkentatics Department, Emory University, Atlanta, Georgia 30322 Communicated by R. H, Brwk Received April 16, 1969 In studying the effect of an order on non-associativesystems such as loops or quasigroups, a natural question to ask is whether some order condition which implies commutativity in the group case implies associativity in the corresponding loop case. For example, a well-known theorem (Birkhoff, [1]) concerning lattice ordered groups statesthat if the descendingchain condition holds for the positive elements,then the 1.0. group is actually a direct product of infinite cyclic groups with its partial order induced in the usual way by the linear order in the factors. It is easy to show (Zelinski, [6]) that a fully- ordered loop satisfying the descendingchain condition on positive elements is actually an infinite cyclic group. In this paper we generalize this result and Birkhoff’s result, by showing that any lattice-ordered loop with descending chain condition on its positive elements is associative. Hence, any 1.0. loop with d.c.c. on its positive elements is a free abelian group. More generally, any lattice-ordered quasigroup in which bounded chains are finite, is isotopic to a free abelian group. These results solve a problem in Birkhoff’s Lattice Theory, 3rd ed. The proof uses only elementary properties of loops and lattices. 1. LATTICE ORDERED LOOPS We will write loops additively with neutral element0.
    [Show full text]
  • Noncommutative Unique Factorization Domainso
    NONCOMMUTATIVE UNIQUE FACTORIZATION DOMAINSO BY P. M. COHN 1. Introduction. By a (commutative) unique factorization domain (UFD) one usually understands an integral domain R (with a unit-element) satisfying the following three conditions (cf. e.g. Zariski-Samuel [16]): Al. Every element of R which is neither zero nor a unit is a product of primes. A2. Any two prime factorizations of a given element have the same number of factors. A3. The primes occurring in any factorization of a are completely deter- mined by a, except for their order and for multiplication by units. If R* denotes the semigroup of nonzero elements of R and U is the group of units, then the classes of associated elements form a semigroup R* / U, and A1-3 are equivalent to B. The semigroup R*jU is free commutative. One may generalize the notion of UFD to noncommutative rings by taking either A-l3 or B as starting point. It is obvious how to do this in case B, although the class of rings obtained is rather narrow and does not even include all the commutative UFD's. This is indicated briefly in §7, where examples are also given of noncommutative rings satisfying the definition. However, our principal aim is to give a definition of a noncommutative UFD which includes the commutative case. Here it is better to start from A1-3; in order to find the precise form which such a definition should take we consider the simplest case, that of noncommutative principal ideal domains. For these rings one obtains a unique factorization theorem simply by reinterpreting the Jordan- Holder theorem for right .R-modules on one generator (cf.
    [Show full text]
  • The Structure of Residuated Lattices
    The Structure of Residuated Lattices Kevin Blount and Constantine Tsinakis May 23, 2002 Abstract A residuated lattice is an ordered algebraic structure L = hL, ∧, ∨, · , e, \ , / i such that hL, ∧, ∨i is a lattice, hL, ·, ei is a monoid, and \ and / are binary operations for which the equivalences a · b ≤ c ⇐⇒ a ≤ c/b ⇐⇒ b ≤ a\c hold for all a, b, c ∈ L. It is helpful to think of the last two operations as left and right division and thus the equivalences can be seen as “di- viding” on the right by b and “dividing” on the left by a. The class of all residuated lattices is denoted by RL. The study of such objects originated in the context of the theory of ring ideals in the 1930’s. The collection of all two-sided ideals of a ring forms a lattice upon which one can impose a natural monoid structure making this object into a residuated lattice. Such ideas were investi- gated by Morgan Ward and R. P. Dilworth in a series of important papers [15], [16],[45], [46], [47] and [48] and also by Krull in [33]. Since that time, there has been substantial research regarding some specific classes of residuated structures, see for example [1], [9], [26] and [38], but we believe that this is the first time that a general structural the- ory has been established for the class RL as a whole. In particular, we develop the notion of a normal subalgebra and show that RL is an “ideal variety” in the sense that it is an equational class in which con- gruences correspond to “normal” subalgebras in the same way that ring congruences correspond to ring ideals.
    [Show full text]
  • Groups with Identical Subgroup Lattices in All Powers
    GROUPS WITH IDENTICAL SUBGROUP LATTICES IN ALL POWERS KEITH A. KEARNES AND AGNES´ SZENDREI Abstract. Suppose that G and H are groups with cyclic Sylow subgroups. We show that if there is an isomorphism λ2 : Sub (G × G) ! Sub (H × H), then there k k are isomorphisms λk : Sub (G ) ! Sub (H ) for all k. But this is not enough to force G to be isomorphic to H, for we also show that for any positive integer N there are pairwise nonisomorphic groups G1; : : : ; GN defined on the same finite set, k k all with cyclic Sylow subgroups, such that Sub (Gi ) = Sub (Gj ) for all i; j; k. 1. Introduction To what extent is a finite group determined by the subgroup lattices of its finite direct powers? Reinhold Baer proved results in 1939 implying that an abelian group G is determined up to isomorphism by Sub (G3) (cf. [1]). Michio Suzuki proved in 1951 that a finite simple group G is determined up to isomorphism by Sub (G2) (cf. [10]). Roland Schmidt proved in 1981 that if G is a finite, perfect, centerless group, then it is determined up to isomorphism by Sub (G2) (cf. [6]). Later, Schmidt proved in [7] that if G has an elementary abelian Hall normal subgroup that equals its own centralizer, then G is determined up to isomorphism by Sub (G3). It has long been open whether every finite group G is determined up to isomorphism by Sub (G3). (For more information on this problem, see the books [8, 11].) One may ask more generally to what extent a finite algebraic structure (or algebra) is determined by the subalgebra lattices of its finite direct powers.
    [Show full text]
  • Thermodynamic Properties of Coupled Map Lattices 1 Introduction
    Thermodynamic properties of coupled map lattices J´erˆome Losson and Michael C. Mackey Abstract This chapter presents an overview of the literature which deals with appli- cations of models framed as coupled map lattices (CML’s), and some recent results on the spectral properties of the transfer operators induced by various deterministic and stochastic CML’s. These operators (one of which is the well- known Perron-Frobenius operator) govern the temporal evolution of ensemble statistics. As such, they lie at the heart of any thermodynamic description of CML’s, and they provide some interesting insight into the origins of nontrivial collective behavior in these models. 1 Introduction This chapter describes the statistical properties of networks of chaotic, interacting el- ements, whose evolution in time is discrete. Such systems can be profitably modeled by networks of coupled iterative maps, usually referred to as coupled map lattices (CML’s for short). The description of CML’s has been the subject of intense scrutiny in the past decade, and most (though by no means all) investigations have been pri- marily numerical rather than analytical. Investigators have often been concerned with the statistical properties of CML’s, because a deterministic description of the motion of all the individual elements of the lattice is either out of reach or uninteresting, un- less the behavior can somehow be described with a few degrees of freedom. However there is still no consistent framework, analogous to equilibrium statistical mechanics, within which one can describe the probabilistic properties of CML’s possessing a large but finite number of elements.
    [Show full text]
  • Cayley's and Holland's Theorems for Idempotent Semirings and Their
    Cayley's and Holland's Theorems for Idempotent Semirings and Their Applications to Residuated Lattices Nikolaos Galatos Department of Mathematics University of Denver [email protected] Rostislav Horˇc´ık Institute of Computer Sciences Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic [email protected] Abstract We extend Cayley's and Holland's representation theorems to idempotent semirings and residuated lattices, and provide both functional and relational versions. Our analysis allows for extensions of the results to situations where conditions are imposed on the order relation of the representing structures. Moreover, we give a new proof of the finite embeddability property for the variety of integral residuated lattices and many of its subvarieties. 1 Introduction Cayley's theorem states that every group can be embedded in the (symmetric) group of permutations on a set. Likewise, every monoid can be embedded into the (transformation) monoid of self-maps on a set. C. Holland [10] showed that every lattice-ordered group can be embedded into the lattice-ordered group of order-preserving permutations on a totally-ordered set. Recall that a lattice-ordered group (`-group) is a structure G = hG; _; ^; ·;−1 ; 1i, where hG; ·;−1 ; 1i is group and hG; _; ^i is a lattice, such that multiplication preserves the order (equivalently, it distributes over joins and/or meets). An analogous representation was proved also for distributive lattice-ordered monoids in [2, 11]. We will prove similar theorems for resid- uated lattices and idempotent semirings in Sections 2 and 3. Section 4 focuses on the finite embeddability property (FEP) for various classes of idempotent semirings and residuated lat- tices.
    [Show full text]