Moral Responsibility in Professional Ethics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Moral Responsibility in Professional Ethics See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/264839520 Moral Responsibility in Professional Ethics ARTICLE · JANUARY 1980 CITATIONS READS 11 873 1 AUTHOR: Gerald Postema University of North Carolina at Cha… 52 PUBLICATIONS 148 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE Available from: Gerald Postema Retrieved on: 12 January 2016 MORAL RESPONSIBILITY IN PROFESSIONAL ETHICS 1 GERALD J. POSTEMA* Professor Postema argues for a new conception of professional ethics in wlhich lawyers must acknowledge personal responsibilityfor the consequences of their pro- fessional conduct. He suggests that a new code of professional responsibility is re- quired because the current Code allows lawyers to ignore the social and moral costs of their actions, and do as professionals what they would not do as indiciduals. Lawyers, like other professionals, acknowledge gravely that they shoulder special responsibilities, and believe that they should con- form to "higher" ethical standards than laypersons.2 Yet, lawyers also claim special warrant for engaging in some activities which, were they performed by others, would be likely to draw moral censure.3 Skepti- cal of this claim to special license, Macaulav asked "'[w]hether it be right that a man should, with a wig on his head, and a band round his neck, do for a guinea what, without these appendages, he would think it wicked and infamous to do for an empire."14 This conflict may trouble the layperson, but for the lawyer who must come to grips with his professional responsibilities it is especially problematic. Montaigne offered one solution, the complete separation of per- sonal and professional lives. "There's no reason why a lawyer ... should not recognize the knavery that is part of his vocation," he insisted. "An honest man is not responsible for the vices or the stupidity of his calling." 5 The key to maintaining both professional *Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill. A.B., 1970, Calvin College; A.M., 1973, Ph.D., 1976, Cornell University. 1 The concerns discussed in this essay were first suggested to me in discussions with sev- eral participants at the Institute on Law and Ethics sponsored by the Council for Philosophic Studies during the summer of 1977. Larry Alexander, Bernard Williams, and Gary Bellow were especially helpful. An earlier version of this essay w%-aswritten as a background paper for the Philosophical Perspectives on Public Policy Project of the Center for Philosophy and Public Policy, the University of Maryland, College Park. 2 "Lawyers, as guardians of the law, play a vital role in the preservation of society. The fulfillment of this role requires an understanding by lawyers of their relationship %vithand func- tion in our legal system. A consequent obligation of lawsyers is to maintain the highest standards of ethical conduct." ABA, Model Code of Professional Responsibility, Preamble, at 1 (1980) [hereinafter Code] (footnote omitted). 3 For examples, see text accompanying notes 11-15 infra. 4 T. Macaulay, Lord Bacon, in 2 Critical and Historical Essays 121. 152 (F. Montague ed. 1903). Quoted in Curtis, The Ethics of Advocacy, 4 Stan. L. Rev. 3. 20 (1951). 63 HeinOnline -- 55 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 63 1980 Imaged with the Permission of N.Y.U. Law Review NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol, 55:63 and personal integrity in the face of professionally required "knavery" was, Montaigne thought, scrupulously to keep the two personalities apart: "I have been able to concern myself with public affairs without moving the length of my nail from myself .... The mayor and Montaigne have always been two people, clearly separated."; Montaigne's solution is tempting. Maintaining a hermetically sealed professional personality promises to minimize internal con- flicts, to shift responsibility for professional "knavery" to broader in- stitutional shoulders, and to enable a person to act consistently within each role he assumes. But for this strategy to succeed, the underlying values and concerns of important professional roles, and the charac- teristic activities they require, must themselves be easily segregated and compartmentalized. However, since there is good reason to doubt they can be easily segregated, Montaigne's strategy risks a dangerous simplification of moral reality. Furthermore, in com- partmentalizing moral responses one blocks the cross-fertilization of moral experience necessary for personal and professional growth. This Article considers whether it is possible to follow Montaigne's sugges- tion and to separate one's private and professional personalities with- out jeopardizing one's ability to engage in professional activities in a morally and professionally responsible way. The central issue I ad- dress is not whether there is sufficient justification for a distinct pro- fessional code for lawyers, but whether, given the need for such a code, it is possible to preserve one's sense of responsibility. I argue that such preservation is not possible when a professional must adopt Montaigne's strategy in order to function well in his professional role. I contend that a sense of responsibility and sound practical judgment depend not only on the quality of one's professional training, but also on one's ability to draw on the resources of a broader moral experi- ence. This, in turn, requires that one seek to achieve a fully inte- grated moral personality. Because this is not possible under the pres- ent conception of the lawyer's role, as exemplified by the Code of Professional Responsibility, that conception must be abandoned, to be replaced by a conception that better allows the lawyer to bring his full moral sensibilities to play in his professional role. I MORAL DISTANCE AND THE PERSPECTIVE OF THE RESPONSIBLE PERSON It is not uncommon for lawyers to face dilemmas caused by the clash of important principles implicit within the professional code. 6 Id. HeinOnline -- 55 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 64 1980 Imaged with the Permission of N.Y.U. Law Review April 1980] MORAL RESPONSIBILITY A good example of this is the problem posed for a criminal defense lawyer by a client who announces a firm intention to perjure himself at trial. 7 Here, the deeply embedded principle of confidentiality 8 conflicts sharply with the equally important duty of candor before the court. 9 But this is not the sort of clash Montaigne had in mind. Indeed, similar moral quandaries and conflicts are common outside of pro- fessional contexts. Rather, Montaigne draws attention to the conflict between principles of professional ethics and concerns of private mor- ality. The requirements of professional ethics can sometimes move some distance from the concerns of private or ordinary morality, a phenomenon we might call moral distance. The range of practical considerations which alone are relevant to a proper ethical decision in a professional role is the moral universe of that role.10 For many professional roles the moral universe of the role is considerably nar- rower than that of ordinary morality, and, when the two overlap, they often assign different weights to the same set of considerations. This often gives rise to conflicts, as the following cases illustrate. The first example involves the duty of the criminal defense attor- ney to maintain client confidentiality. In the course of preparing a defense for a criminal trial in Lake Pleasant, New York, the client told his attorneys that he was responsible for three other murders unrelated to the pending case. The lawyers visited the location where one of the bodies had been hidden and confirmed the client's story. Nevertheless, .they maintained silence for six months and refrained from disclosing the whereabouts of the body to the authorities or to the family of one of the victims, which had sought their help in locat- ing the missing victim." The duty of confidentiality, which here pro- tects the client against self-incrimination, clearly forbade disclosure in this case,12 even though the attorneys' personal inclinations were to disclose. 7 See M. Freedman, Lawyers" Ethics in an Adversary System 27-42 (1975). 8 See Code, supra note 2, Canon 4, especially EC 4-1, EC 4-5, DR 4-101(A). DR 4-101(B). DR 4-101(C)(3). 9 See id. Canon 7, especially EC 7-27, DR 7-102(A)(4). (5). DR 7-IO2tBhlI). Also see ABA Project on Standards Relating to the Prosecution Function and the Defense Function § 7.7 (Approved Draft 1971). 1o I borrow this term from Wasserstrom, Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues. 5 Human Rights 1, 2-8 (1975). 11 People v. Beige, 83 Misc. 2d 186, 372 N.Y.S.2d 798 (Onondaga County Ct.), afd mem., 50 A.D.2d 1088, 376 N.Y.S.2d 771 (1975), affd per curiam, 41 N.Y.2d 60. 359 N.E.2d 377, 390 N.Y.S.2d 867 (1976). 12 See Code, supra note 2, EC 4-1, EC 4-4. Also see Callan & David, Professional Respon- sibility and the Duty of Confidentiality: Disclosure of Client Misconduct in an Adversary Sys- tern, 29 Rutgers L. Rev. 332 (1976). The prosecution argued that failure to report the deaths amounted to a criminal violation of the New York State Public Health Law. 83 Misc. 2d at 187, HeinOnline -- 55 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 65 1980 Imaged with the Permission of N.Y.U. Law Review NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55:63 The second example, illustrated by the case of Zabella v. Pakel, 13 concerns the lawyer's use of legally available defenses to cir- cumvent enforcement of his client's moral obligations. At the time of suit, defendant Pakel was president and manager of the Chicago Sav- ings and Loan Association. In earlier and less fortunate cir- cumstances, he had borrowed heavily from his employee, Zabella.
Recommended publications
  • Moral Obligations to Future Generations
    Moral Obligations toward the Future I. Introduction Until now our ethical considerations have typically involved our interactions with people such as family members, fellow students, and fellow citizens—those who together might be called our moral community. Even when our considerations have encompassed the wider “community” of human beings, we have still limited our thinking to those presently living—to our contemporaries. The same can be said of most moral theories—which likewise tend to focus on the moral obligations of the living toward their contemporaries. This suggests an interesting question: Can we also have moral concerns and obligations involving those who do not belong to our contemporary moral community? For instance, what about those who lived in the past? Although we cannot now affect any persons who are no longer alive, we can still affect some of their interests. Like ourselves, past people certainly had interests in their own human dignity, in what others thought of them, and in the welfare of their progeny. We thus appear to have moral obligations not to desecrate their graves, slander them, or take for ourselves what they willed to their offspring. Further, it seems that we can sometimes hold past persons morally blameworthy for the ways their actions have affected us. Consider a present-day man whose grandparents were gassed by the Nazis. Besides blaming the Nazis for what they did to his grandparents, doesn’t this man also have a right to hold the Nazis responsible for personally wronging him by causing the untimely deaths of his grandparents? Doesn’t the Native American who is destitute today because of policies carried out against her ancestors likewise have a personal moral claim against those past people whose actions led to her present condition? In fact, we take such moral judgments so seriously that reparations are sometimes made to people today for wrongs committed by past generations.
    [Show full text]
  • John Stuart Mill's Sanction Utilitarianism
    JOHN STUART MILL’S SANCTION UTILITARIANISM: A PHILOSOPHICAL AND HISTORICAL INTERPRETATION A Dissertation by DAVID EUGENE WRIGHT Submitted to the Office of Graduate and Professional Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Chair of Committee, Linda Radzik Committee Members, Clare Palmer Scott Austin R.J.Q. Adams Head of Department, Gary Varner May 2014 Major Subject: Philosophy Copyright 2014 David Eugene Wright ABSTRACT This dissertation argues for a particular interpretation of John Stuart Mill’s utilitarianism, namely that Mill is best read as a sanction utilitarian. In general, scholars commonly interpret Mill as some type of act or rule utilitarian. In making their case for these interpretations, it is also common for scholars to use large portions of Mill’s Utilitarianism as the chief source of insight into his moral theory. By contrast, I argue that Utilitarianism is best read as an ecumenical text where Mill explains and defends the general tenets of utilitarianism rather than setting out his own preferred theory. The exception to this ecumenical approach to the text comes in the fifth chapter on justice which, I argue on textual and historical grounds, outlines the central features of Mill’s utilitarianism. With this understanding of Utilitarianism in place, many of the passages commonly cited in favor of the previous interpretations are rendered less plausible, and interpretations emphasizing Mill’s other writings are strengthened. Using this methodology, I critique four of the most prominent act or rule utilitarian interpretations of Mill’s moral theory. I then provide an interpretation of Mill’s theory of moral obligation and utilitarianism.
    [Show full text]
  • Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility
    Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility Draft of September 2015 Elinor Mason For Christian Seidel (ed.) Consequentialism: new directions, new problems? OUP, forthcoming. There are two different ways of thinking about the relationship between consequentialism and moral responsibility. First, we might think that consequentialism can give us an account of responsibility. I discuss this possibility briefly, and then set it aside. The other way of thinking about the relationship is the focus of this paper. The question that concerns me, is, to what extent is a normative theory, consequentialism in particular, constrained by requirements that stem from concerns about responsibility? 1. Consequentialist Accounts of Moral Responsibility J.J.C. Smart suggests that we can extend consequentialist reasoning about morality to reasoning about responsibility. One of the attractions of consequentialism is that it provides such a straightforward and attractive account of justification for our moral practices. Why do we pay our taxes, treat each other with respect, look after each other and so on? Because doing so has good consequences. However, this sort of justification, though very appealing when considering moral practice, becomes extremely counterintuitive in other sorts of case. For example, it seems obvious that justification for beliefs cannot be consequentialist. Beliefs must be justified in some way that relates to their truth, though of course there is disagreement about exactly what makes a belief justified. Similarly, so a familiar line of thought goes, whether or not someone is responsible for an act, or for anything else, cannot be determined by looking at the consequences of holding them responsible. The claim that 1 responsibility can be understood in a consequentialist way seems like a category mistake.1 Smart’s view might be correct that, insofar as praising and blaming are actions, consequentialists should take the value of the consequences of performing those acts as the relevant factor in deciding whether or not to perform them.
    [Show full text]
  • 5. What Matters Is the Motive / Immanuel Kant
    This excerpt is from Michael J. Sandel, Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do?, pp. 103-116, by permission of the publisher. 5. WHAT MATTERS IS THE MOTIVE / IMMANUEL KANT If you believe in universal human rights, you are probably not a utili- tarian. If all human beings are worthy of respect, regardless of who they are or where they live, then it’s wrong to treat them as mere in- struments of the collective happiness. (Recall the story of the mal- nourished child languishing in the cellar for the sake of the “city of happiness.”) You might defend human rights on the grounds that respecting them will maximize utility in the long run. In that case, however, your reason for respecting rights is not to respect the person who holds them but to make things better for everyone. It is one thing to con- demn the scenario of the su! ering child because it reduces overall util- ity, and something else to condemn it as an intrinsic moral wrong, an injustice to the child. If rights don’t rest on utility, what is their moral basis? Libertarians o! er a possible answer: Persons should not be used merely as means to the welfare of others, because doing so violates the fundamental right of self-ownership. My life, labor, and person belong to me and me alone. They are not at the disposal of the society as a whole. As we have seen, however, the idea of self-ownership, consistently applied, has implications that only an ardent libertarian can love—an unfettered market without a safety net for those who fall behind; a 104 JUSTICE minimal state that rules out most mea sures to ease inequality and pro- mote the common good; and a celebration of consent so complete that it permits self-in" icted a! ronts to human dignity such as consensual cannibalism or selling oneself into slav ery.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 1994 Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics Nelson T. Potter Jr. University of Nebraska - Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Legal Ethics and Professional Responsibility Commons, and the Legal History Commons Potter, Nelson T. Jr., "Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics" (1994). Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy. 15. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub/15 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Potter in Jarbuch für Recht und Ethik (1994) 2. Copyright 1994, Friedrich-Alexander-Universität Erlangen-Nürnberg. Used by permission. Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics Nelson Potter I. There is a passage in Immanuel Kant's general introduction to both parts of Die Metaphysik der Sitten that deserves more attention than it has received. I plan to build the present paper around the implil:ations of this passage: In all lawgiving (Gesetzgebung) (whether it prescribes for internal or external actions, and whether it prescribes them a priori by reason alone or by the choice of another) there are two elements: first, a law, which represents an action that is to be done as objectively necessary, that is, which makes the action a duty; and second, an incentive, which connects a ground for determining choice to this action subjectively with the representation of the law.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine's Ethics
    15 BONNIE KENT Augustine’s ethics Augustine regards ethics as an enquiry into the Summum Bonum: the supreme good, which provides the happiness all human beings seek. In this respect his moral thought comes closer to the eudaimonistic virtue ethics of the classical Western tradition than to the ethics of duty and law associated with Christianity in the modern period. But even though Augustine addresses many of the same problems that pagan philosophers do, he often defends very different answers. For him, happiness consists in the enjoyment of God, a reward granted in the afterlife for virtue in this life. Virtue itself is a gift of God, and founded on love, not on the wisdom prized by philosophers. The art of living In Book 8 of De civitate Dei Augustine describes “moral philosophy” (a Latin expression), or “ethics” (the Greek equivalent), as an enquiry into the supreme good and how we can attain it. The supreme good is that which we seek for its own sake, not as a means to some other end, and which makes us happy. Augustine adds, as if this were an uncontroversial point, that happiness is the aim of philosophy in general.1 Book 19 opens with a similar discussion. In his summary of Varro’s treatise De philosophia, Augustine reports that no school of philosophy deserves to be considered a distinct school unless it differs from others on the supreme good. For the supreme good is that which makes us happy, and the only purpose of philosophizing is the attainment of happiness.2 Both of these discussions cast philosophy as a fundamentally practical discipline, so that ethics appears to overshadow logic, metaphysics, and other comparatively abstract areas as a philosopher’s chief concern.
    [Show full text]
  • Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility Elinor Mason, University of Edinburgh
    Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility Elinor Mason, University of Edinburgh Abstract I aim to vindicate the thought that there is something very unsatisfactory about objective consequentialism – moral theories just can’t be like that. The root of this thought is to be found in our intuitions about the nature of moral responsibility, so in order to vindicate it we have to investigate moral responsibility. I argue that moral responsibility and normative theory are inextricably linked. R.J. Wallace has defended a related view, but Wallace claims that investigation of moral responsibility must proceed by investigating our normative notion of fairness. I argue that we should not assume that fairness – only one particular aspect of our normative moral theory - is what should inform our account of moral responsibility. I show that our questions about responsibility are really questions about morality, and correspondingly, our questions about morality are also questions about responsibility. Thus plausible answers to each of these questions must be plausible answers to both, and this provides interesting constraints on our theories. I thus show that objective consequentialism does not have its own corresponding theory of responsibility, and that is why it seems unsatisfactory. Subjective consequentialism is in fact a variant of a basic moral outlook that is Kantian. In Kantian terms, what matters is that the will is good – according to a subjective consequentialist, the good will is one that forms consequentialist intentions. Draft of September 2008 This paper is part of a larger project in which I try to show that theories of moral responsibility are grounded in normative moral theories.
    [Show full text]
  • Instrumentalism About Moral Responsibility Revisited
    The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 69,No.276 2019 ISSN 0031-8094 doi: 10.1093/pq/pqy062 Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/pq/article/69/276/555/5266881 by guest on 30 September 2021 INSTRUMENTALISM ABOUT MORAL RESPONSIBILITY REVISITED By Anneli Jefferson I defend an instrumentalist account of moral responsibility and adopt Manuel Vargas’ idea that our responsibility practices are justified by their effects. However, whereas Vargas gives an independent account of morally responsible agency, on my account, responsible agency is defined as the suscepti- bility to developing and maintaining moral agency through being held responsible. I show that the instrumentalism I propose can avoid some problems more crude forms of instrumentalism encounter by adopting aspects of Strawsonian accounts. I then show the implications for our understanding of responsibility: my account requires us to adopt a graded notion of responsibility and accept the claim that certain individuals may not be responsible because they are not susceptible to being influenced by our moral responsibility practices. Finally, I discuss whether the account is committed to allowing the instrumentalization of non-responsible individuals in cases where blaming them may benefit others’ moral agency. Keywords: moral responsibility, consequentialism, reactive attitudes, moral influ- ence, instrumentalization. When we think about responsibility, we always have one eye to the future and one eye to the past. We look at agents’ past behaviour and intentions to establish desert, and we look to the consequences it is appropriate to visit on them in the future. In his seminal 1961 paper ‘Free will, praise and blame’, Smart put forward an instrumentalist account of what it means to be morally responsible.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberty of the Higher-Order Will: Frankfurt and Augustine
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 19 Issue 4 Article 3 10-1-2002 Liberty of the Higher-Order Will: Frankfurt and Augustine John J. Davenport Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Davenport, John J. (2002) "Liberty of the Higher-Order Will: Frankfurt and Augustine," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 19 : Iss. 4 , Article 3. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol19/iss4/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. LIBERTY OF THE HIGHER-ORDER WILL: FRANKFURT AND AUGUSTINE 1 John J. Davenport In Augustine's early account of good and evil (in On Free Choice of the Will), and in his story of his own moral struggles (in the Confessions) we find a view similar to Harry Frankfurt's account of the first and second orders of the will. However, while Frankfurt thinks that his hierarchical account of the will provides evidence against the libertarian principle (PAP) that alternative possibilities are required for a person to be morally responsible for her actions, Augustine's account shows that this is not so. Rather, Augustine holds that moral responsibility for our char­ acter as constituted by our volitional identifications requires alternative possibili­ ties of the higher-order will.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Responsibility and Consciousness
    JOURNAL OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY Journal of Moral Philosophy 9 (2012) 200–228 brill.nl/jmp Moral Responsibility and Consciousness Matt King St. Bonaventure University [email protected] Peter Carruthers * University of Maryland [email protected] Abstract Our goal in this paper is to raise a general question about the relationship between theories of responsibility, on the one hand, and a commitment to conscious attitudes, on the other. The evidence from cognitive science suggests that there are no conscious mental states playing the right causal roles to count as decisions, judgments, or evaluations. We propose that all theorists should determine whether their theories (or the examples that motivate them) could survive the discovery that there are no conscious states of these kinds. Since we take it that theories of moral responsibility should, in general, operate with the weakest possible empirical assumptions about the natural world, such theories should be framed in such a way as to be free of any commitment to the existence of conscious attitudes, given the very real possibility that there might turn out not to be any. Keywords consciousness ; moral responsibility ; psychology ; Real Self views Our aim in this paper is to raise a question about the relationship between theories of responsibility, on the one hand, and a commitment to conscious attitudes, on the other. Our question has rarely been raised previously. Among those who believe in the reality of human freedom, compatibilists have traditionally devoted their energies to providing an account that can avoid any commitment to the falsity of determinism while successfully accommodating a range of intuitive examples.
    [Show full text]
  • Conscious Will, Reason-Responsiveness, and Moral Responsibility
    Conscious will, reason-responsiveness, and moral responsibility Markus E. Schlosser Forthcoming in the Journal of Ethics This is the manuscript (which may differ from the final print version in minor details) Abstract: Empirical evidence challenges many of the assumptions that underlie traditional philosophical and commonsense conceptions of human agency. It has been suggested that this evidence threatens also to undermine free will and moral responsibility. In this paper, I will focus on the purported threat to moral responsibility. The evidence challenges assumptions concerning the ability to exercise conscious control and to act for reasons. This raises an apparent challenge to moral responsibility as these abilities appear to be necessary for morally responsible agency. I will argue that this challenge collapses once the underlying conditions on moral responsibility are specified in sufficient detail. I will argue, in other words, that the empirical evidence does not support a challenge to the assumption that we are, in general, morally responsible agents. In the final section, I will suggest that empirical research on human agency is nevertheless relevant to various questions about moral responsibility. Keywords: Moral responsibility, conscious control, automaticity, reason-responsiveness, situationism, philosophy of cognitive science 1. Introduction Over the past few decades, it has often been argued that common conceptions of human agency are untenable in the light of empirical evidence from psychology and cognitive neuroscience. It has also often been suggested that this evidence challenges the assumption that we are free and morally responsible agents. Intuitively, it is not difficult to see why the evidence seems to threaten free will and moral responsibility.
    [Show full text]
  • Free Will, Determinism, and Moral Responsibility: an Analysis of Event-Causal Incompatibilism Gunnar Footh Macalester College, [email protected]
    Macalester College DigitalCommons@Macalester College Philosophy Honors Projects Philosophy Department July 2017 Free Will, Determinism, and Moral Responsibility: An Analysis of Event-Causal Incompatibilism Gunnar Footh Macalester College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/phil_honors Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Footh, Gunnar, "Free Will, Determinism, and Moral Responsibility: An Analysis of Event-Causal Incompatibilism" (2017). Philosophy Honors Projects. 10. http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/phil_honors/10 This Honors Project is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at DigitalCommons@Macalester College. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Honors Projects by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Macalester College. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Free Will, Determinism, and Moral Responsibility: An Analysis of Event-Causal Incompatibilism By Gunnar John Footh Professor Geoffrey Gorham Department of Philosophy 4/26/17 Chapter 1: Introduction The question of moral responsibility has been around for millenia. What is moral responsibility? How do we define it? What does it mean to be a moral person? This philosophical topic alone has been analyzed and debated among philosophers for centuries. The very existence of the debates over moral responsibility and value theory as a whole evidences the importance humanity puts on answering these moral questions. It is no surprise that these topics are still being discussed and debated today. The moral responsibility-determinism debate is ongoing in contemporary philosophy, and it asks the following question: is moral responsibility reconcilable or compatible with a deterministic universe? Here I will define determinism as causal ​ determinism, the idea that every event is necessitated by antecedent events in conjunction ​ with the laws of nature.
    [Show full text]