Two Distinct Doxastic Attitudes 23 2.1 the Notion ‘Doxastic Attitude’

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Two Distinct Doxastic Attitudes 23 2.1 the Notion ‘Doxastic Attitude’ Submitted December 11th, 2013. Supervisors: Prof. dr. Joke Meheus, Universiteit Gent Dr. Bert Leuridan, Universiteit Gent Reading Committee: Prof. dr. Atocha Aliseda, Universidad Nacional Autonoma´ de M´exico Prof. dr. Igor Douven, Rijksuniversiteit Groningen Dr. Michela Massimi, The University of Edinburgh Prof. dr. Maarten Van Dyck, Universiteit Gent Prof. dr. Erik Weber, Universiteit Gent This thesis was typeset in LATEX. Cover Image: Daya Bay Neutrino Experiment (Courtesy of Brookhaven National Laboratory) Cover Design: Gitte Callaert Faculteit Letteren en Wijsbegeerte Tjerk Gauderis Patterns of Hypothesis Formation At the crossroads of Philosophy of Science, Logic, Epistemology, Artificial Intelligence and Physics Proefschrift voorgelegd tot het behalen van de graad van Doctor in de Wijsbegeerte Promotoren: Prof. Dr. Joke Meheus en Dr. Bert Leuridan to my daughter Ada, who explains it all acknowledgments This piece of work would never have emerged in its present form, were it not for the support of many. In particular, I want to thank my love Nel, for being there and complementing me; my daughter Ada for bringing her liveliness into our home: her look on the world was and is a con- stant inspiration; my supervisor Joke for allow- ing me to pursue my own path in these muddy waters; my co-supervisor Bert for his detailed and constructive remarks on every part of this thesis; the Centre for Logic and Philosophy of Science for giving me a four years grant; its cur- rent and former employees for their many useful comments and ideas over the years; my friends, they mean more to me than they realize; and finally, the world itself, for being such an intrigu- ing and fascinating place to dwell in. Contents 1 Introduction 1 1.1 General Topic of the Dissertation . 2 1.2 Overview of the Literature . 3 1.3 Four Parts, Four Approaches . 8 1.4 ‘Scientific Discovery’ and ‘Abductive Reasoning’ . 9 1.5 Some Common Themes . 13 1.6 A Note on the Structure . 15 I Epistemological Considerations 17 2 Two Distinct Doxastic Attitudes 23 2.1 The Notion ‘Doxastic Attitude’ . 23 2.2 Doxastic Attitudes and Doxastic Concepts . 26 2.3 The Theoretical and the Practical Doxastic Attitude . 27 2.4 Three Categories of Doxastic Concepts . 31 2.5 Belief and Acceptance . 33 2.6 Belief, Degrees of Belief and the Bayesian Challenge . 37 2.7 Conclusion . 40 3 The Attitude of Entertaining a Hypothesis 43 3.1 Uncertainties and Doxastic Attitudes . 43 3.2 Hypotheses and Beliefs . 48 3.3 The Doxastic Attitude of Entertaining a Hypothesis . 57 3.4 Hypotheses and Science, Rationality and Skepticism . 59 II Logical Patterns 65 4 Singular Fact Abduction in Science 83 4.1 Introduction . 83 ii CONTENTS 4.2 General Characterization of Adaptive Logics . 86 4.3 The Deductive Framework . 89 s 4.4 Informal Presentation of the Logic MLAs . 90 s 4.5 Formal Presentation of the Logic MLAs . 96 4.6 Modeling Human Reasoning and Consequence Sets . 97 4.7 Case Study: The Origin of the Moon . 99 4.8 Conclusion . 103 5 Singular Fact Abduction in AI 105 5.1 A Set-based Formulation of Adaptive Logics Syntax . 106 5.2 Other Conditional Approaches in AI . 109 5.3 The Problem of Multiple Explanatory Hypotheses . 109 s 5.4 A Set-based Formulation of the Logic MLAs . 112 5.5 An Elaborate Example: a Bird called Tweety . 116 5.6 Conclusion . 119 6 Abduction of Generalizations 121 6.1 Introduction . 121 6.2 Abduction of a Generalization . 123 6.3 Introducing the Formal Framework . 129 6.4 Presentation of The Logic LAr . 134 6.5 A New Problem for the Logic 8LAr . 140 6.6 Conclusion . .8 . 142 III A Historical Case 143 7 The Curious β spectrum 151 7.1 Introduction . 152 7.2 The β puzzle in 1927 . 155 7.3 Charles Ellis and William Wooster . 162 7.4 Ernest Rutherford and James Chadwick . 165 7.5 George Paget Thomson . 169 7.6 Niels Bohr . 174 7.7 Werner Heisenberg . 182 7.8 Wolfgang Pauli . 184 7.9 Summary and Conclusions . 192 CONTENTS iii IV Thinking about Models 197 8 The Adaptation of Old Ideas 203 8.1 The Heuristic Role of Models in Science . 204 8.2 Models and Scientific Discovery in Physics . 205 8.3 Case Study A: Rutherford’s idea of the Neutron . 209 8.4 Case Study B: Pauli’s idea of the Neutrino . 212 8.5 Conclusion . 216 9 Models and Hypotheses 217 9.1 Introduction . 217 9.2 Some Conceptual Issues . 219 9.3 Four Stances on their Relation . 223 9.4 Three Case Studies from Astrophysics . 230 9.5 Heuristic and Fully Interpretable Hypotheses . 237 9.6 Hypotheses in Model-Based Scientific Practice . 240 9.7 Conclusion . 242 Conclusion 245 Bibliography 251 1Introduction The Muses love alternatives. — Virgil, Eclogues, Book III How do scientists form new hypotheses? Are there general patterns of hypothesis formation? If so, is the list of patterns humans are capable of limited? Are there better or worse patterns to form new hypotheses? Can we simulate processes of hypothesis formation? How do scientists choose if different patterns are available? How do hypotheses relate to scientific models? How do scientists deal with mutually exclusive hypotheses? Can we rationally endorse mutually exclusive alternatives? Are hypotheses part of our daily life? Can we live with uncertainties? These are the general questions that motivated and led to this disserta- tion, a tour which took me through various philosophical subdisciplines to obtain as rich as possible a view of the topic of hypothesis formation in science. In this general introduction, I will situate my main topic, give an over- view of the existing literature and address some common themes. More specific introductions to the philosophical methods I will use can be found in the separate introductions to the various parts. 2 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION 1.1 General Topic of the Dissertation The topic of this PhD thesis is the formation and use of hypotheses in sci- ence, with a focus on the physical sciences. According to the view I develop, scientific hypotheses can be defined as follows: Scientific hypotheses are statements about the empirical world with an unknown or underdetermined truth status that are ad- vanced as a tentative answer to a particular research question. The different aspects of this definition of scientific hypotheses are argued for and assumed at various places throughout the dissertation, and a full elaboration of this definition can be found in Section 9.2. In the remainder of this section, I want to point out some delineating choices and general features to set the scene. More detailed argumentation will be given in due course. Doxastic Attitude In forming a hypothesis an agent adopts at the same time a specific attitude or cognitive relation towards that hypothesis. As scientific reasoning should not be considered to be isolated from general reasoning in every day life, this attitude, which will be determined as a dox- astic attitude sui generis, can be studied from a more general perspective in the field of epistemology. Truth-purposiveness In this thesis, I deal only with truth-purposive hy- potheses, hypotheses which the agent considers as neither true nor false, but as unknown or even underdetermined. The agent’s main purpose in forming such hypotheses is either to determine their truth value or to use their possible truth for other epistemic purposes. This class of hypotheses has to be sharply distinguished from truth-denying hypotheses, hypotheses the agent considers to be false, but which can be useful for her, for instance, in setting up a thought experiment. Reference to the Empirical World My topic is further limited by the fact that I consider only hypotheses that make reference to the empirical world. In other words, I do not focus on mathematical conjectures or hypothesized conceptual relations. While the analysis of the epistemological and logical parts of this dissertation may probably be extended to include this kind of hypotheses, my analysis of the use of hypotheses in scientific practice is tailored specifically for hypotheses that refer to the empirical world. 1.2. OVERVIEW OF THE LITERATURE 3 The Importance of a Research Question Not just any conjectural state- ment can be considered as a hypothesis. Scientific hypotheses are formed in response to and in relation with a certain research question, which acts as a trigger for them. Although hypotheses are sometimes presented more or less independently at later stages of research, they cannot be fully un- derstood if they are disconnected from their triggers. Hypothesis Formation and Rationality In this thesis I assume through- out the possibility of rational hypothesis formation, both in an absolute and a relative sense. More precisely, I assume that it can be rationally justified to suggest a hypothesis in answer to a particular trigger, and I assume that it can be rationally justified to prefer one method of hypothesis formation above another one in a particular case. Yet I do not assume that there is always a difference: two methods can be (equally) rationally justified in a particular case. Also, rational hypothesis formation does not guar- antee higher truth probabilities for individual hypotheses. It is assumed, however, that rational hypothesis formation serves the agent’s epistemic interests better (largely because of a better understanding and coverage of the space of possibilities). Scientific Discovery and Abductive Reasoning In the literature, hypoth- esis formation in science is generally brought into connection with the con- cepts of ‘scientific discovery’ and ‘abductive reasoning’. However, as the precise meaning of these notions can be ambiguous, I will first give an overview of the literature on hypothesis formation, abduction and scien- tific discovery and clarify how the main questions of this dissertation con- nect to the different research challenges presented in this literature.
Recommended publications
  • Responding to Skepticism About Doxastic Agency
    Erkenn (2018) 83:627–645 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-017-9906-2 ORIGINAL RESEARCH Responding to Skepticism About Doxastic Agency Miriam Schleifer McCormick1 Received: 16 April 2016 / Accepted: 9 May 2017 / Published online: 8 June 2017 Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017 Abstract My main aim is to argue that most conceptions of doxastic agency do not respond to the skeptic’s challenge. I begin by considering some reasons for thinking that we are not doxastic agents. I then turn to a discussion of those who try to make sense of doxastic agency by appeal to belief’s reasons-responsive nature. What they end up calling agency is not robust enough to satisfy the challenge posed by the skeptics. To satisfy the skeptic, one needs to make sense of the possibility of believing for nonevidential reasons. While this has been seen as an untenable view for both skeptics and anti-skeptics, I conclude by suggesting it is a position that has been too hastily dismissed. 1 Introduction In what sense or to what extent is agency exercised in the doxastic realm? Some argue that the kind of control we have over beliefs is sufficient for doxastic agency, while others argue that the nature of beliefs precludes agency being exercised in what we believe. But getting clear on the nature of these disagreements is difficult because the disputants do not always share a common notion of what is required for agency in general, and doxastic agency in particular. A skeptic about doxastic agency may agree with everything an anti-skeptic says but insist that none of what is proposed counts as real agency.
    [Show full text]
  • A Social Solution to the Puzzle of Doxastic Responsibility: a Two-Dimensional Account of Responsibility for Belief
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers Forthcoming in Synthese 1 A Social Solution to the Puzzle of Doxastic Responsibility: A Two-Dimensional Account of Responsibility for Belief Robert Carry Osborne (This is a final, pre-copyedit version of an article published in Synthese. The final authenticated version is available online at: http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s11229-020-02637-9) 1. Introduction There are various, well-known difficulties surrounding the notion of doxastic responsibility and the so-called ‘ethics of belief’. The “puzzle of doxastic responsibility,” as Miriam McCormick (2015) has recently called it, arises from the tension between some version of the following three claims, each intuitively plausible on its own, but together jointly inconsistent: (RESPONSIBLE) We sometimes rightly hold agents responsible for their doxastic attitudes. (CONTROL) Voluntary control over X is a prerequisite for responsibility for X. (NON-VOLUNTARY) Beliefs are not subject to the will, that is, we lack voluntary control over them.1 The puzzle, then, is why beliefs seem to be the kinds of things for which we can rightly be held responsible, and yet do not appear to be something over which we exercise direct (voluntary or intentional) control.2 A solution to the puzzle seems to require that we reject at least one of the three claims above. As a result, the puzzle has three general answers: (a) Reject (RESPONSIBLE) and thus deny that beliefs are the proper objects of normative assessment, and so deny that anyone 1 McHugh (2017) also discusses a version of the same puzzle, which he calls “the problem of epistemic responsibility,” though his version involves four claims, and depends explicitly on a comparison with the kind of control we have over our (bodily) actions.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Epistemology and the Project of Mapping Science
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 9-2015 Social Epistemology and the Project of Mapping Science Kamili Posey Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/1097 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! SOCIAL EPISTEMOLOGY AND THE PROJECT OF MAPPING SCIENCE BY KAMILI POSEY A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York. 2015 © 2015 KAMILI POSEY All Rights Reserved ii This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Nikolas Pappas ______________________________ ______________________________ ______________________________ Date Chair of Examining Committee Iakovos Vasiliou ______________________________ ______________________________ ______________________________ Date Executive Officer Samir Chopra ______________________________________________ Linda Alcoff ______________________________________________ Robert Sinclair ______________________________________________ Supervisory Committee THE
    [Show full text]
  • I Am Going to Deal with the Foundations of First Philosophy in Its Entirety
    FOUNDATIONALISM & THE STRUCTURE OF EPISTEMIC WARRANT I am going to deal with the foundations of First Philosophy in its entirety. —Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy The basics of foundationalism Foundationalism is the classic view regarding the nature of warranted belief acceptance, non-acceptance and the suspending of judgement. It has been advocated by such historically significant philosophers as Aristotle, Aquinas, Descartes, Locke, Hume, Reid, and Kant as well as such significant contemporaries as A.J. Ayer, C.I. Lewis and Roderick Chisholm. It has been the subject of serious philosophical attacks by such prominent philosophers as Donald Davidson, Keith Lehrer, Laurence Bonjour and Richard Rorty.1 What is foundationalism, however? Given that foundationalism is a theory about the nature of epistemic warrant, it should be clear that it is a normative theory—i.e., it tells us when we are warranted, reasonable, or permitted to assent, not assent or suspend judgment regarding a proposition. How does it differ from the internalist and externalist views of epistemic warrant we have been discussing? Most importantly, it tells us about the structure of epistemically warranted doxastic attitudes. That is, it tells us how our epistemically warranted doxastic attitudes are related to each other. Put differently, it tells us that every member of a cognitive being’s set of doxastic attitudes is organized and formally related in very important ways. What is that organization and formal relation? According to the foundationalist, genuine (propositional) knowledge and epistemically warranted belief has a two-tier structure: some instances of our knowledge and epistemically warranted belief are foundational and every other instance is non-foundational.
    [Show full text]
  • Questions for Uniqueness (3408 Words)
    1 Questions for Uniqueness (3408 words) Abstract: In this paper, I argue that the so-called Uniqueness Thesis, or Uniqueness, is untenable because we cannot conceive of epistemic rationality as free of any practical components. Uniqueness states that given the same body of evidence, there is at most one rational doxastic attitude taken towards any proposition. Some authors, on the other hand, argue that it is rationally permissible to hold differing doxastic attitudes; call that view Permissivism. First, I provide a precise formulation for Uniqueness and evaluate some of the arguments for and against it. I show that many extant arguments against Uniqueness are question-begging and why these arguments fail. Finally, I offer a better argument against Uniqueness. My argument brings out that rational belief is not determined solely by evidence but also by the questions that guide one’s inquiry. 1. Introduction Given the same body of evidence, is it rational to possess differing doxastic attitudes towards a certain proposition? Some authors argue that it is permissible; call that Permissivism. Others oppose this view and argue for the so-called Uniqueness Thesis, or Uniqueness, which states that for agents with the same body of total evidence, there is at most one rational doxastic attitude taken towards any proposition. What I argue is that Uniqueness is untenable because we cannot conceive of epistemic rationality as free of any practical components. Although arguments have been provided for and against Uniqueness based on practical grounds, these arguments treat doxastic attitudes similarly with bodily actions. The practical component that I discuss here, on the other hand, is restricted to knowledge, i.e., how one inquires.
    [Show full text]
  • Attitudes Beyond Belief: a Theory of Non-Doxastic Attitude Formation and Evaluation
    Attitudes Beyond Belief: A Theory of Non-Doxastic Attitude Formation and Evaluation by Daniel Drucker A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Philosophy) in the University of Michigan 2017 Doctoral Committee: Associate Professor Eric Swanson, Chair Associate Professor Ezra Russell Keshet Associate Professor Sarah Swanson Moss Professor Brian James Weatherson Daniel Drucker [email protected] ORCID iD 0000-0001-6075-1170 ©Daniel Drucker 2017 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I’ll be brief; there’s no way to fully express my gratitude here. So, thank you to Eric Swanson for being the best possible committee chair, conscientious, empathetic, and wise; to Sarah Moss, for the intense and challenging conversations that always left me wanting to be and do better; to Brian Weatherson, for showing the importance of a view of the whole of philosophy; and to Ezra Keshet, for his generosity and example(s). Thanks to Michigan’s (sometimes honorary) philosophers, who’ve been my friends and family for six years, including: Chloe, Sara, Boris, Dave, Gordon, Kevin, Mara, Paul, Bryan, Francesca, Sarah B., Victor, Lingxi, Mercy, Guus, Alex, Matt, Josh, Sydney, Zoe,¨ Jim, Maria, Ishani, Eduardo, Neil, Filipa, Adam, Cat, Alvaro, Chip, Steve, Umer, Patrick, Nils, Rohan, Jamie, Rich, Damian, Nina, and Elise. It’s incredible that this kind of community exists; I’m unspeakably lucky to have been a part of it. The proof of this is how impossible it feels to leave it. Thanks to Plato and Agnes Callard, who shaped my worldview in ways I still don’t fully understand. Thanks to Hakeem Jerome Jefferson, one of the only non-philosophers on the list, for teaching me as much as any philosopher could.
    [Show full text]
  • Belief Without Credence
    Synthese DOI 10.1007/s11229-015-0846-6 Belief without credence J. Adam Carter1 · Benjamin W. Jarvis2 · Katherine Rubin3 Received: 14 May 2014 / Accepted: 31 July 2015 © The Author(s) 2016. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract One of the deepest ideological divides in contemporary epistemology con- cerns the relative importance of belief versus credence. A prominent consideration in favor of credence-based epistemology is the ease with which it appears to account for rational action. In contrast, cases with risky payoff structures threaten to break the link between rational belief and rational action. This threat poses a challenge to traditional epistemology, which maintains the theoretical prominence of belief. The core prob- lem, we suggest, is that belief may not be enough to register all aspects of a subject’s epistemic position with respect to any given proposition. We claim this problem can be solved by introducing other doxastic attitudes—genuine representations—that dif- fer in strength from belief. The resulting alternative picture, a kind of doxastic states pluralism, retains the central features of traditional epistemology—most saliently, an emphasis on truth as a kind of objective accuracy—while adequately accounting for rational action. Keywords Belief · Rational action · Cognitive achievement · Contextualism · Truth · Virtue epistemology B J. Adam Carter [email protected] Benjamin W. Jarvis [email protected] Katherine Rubin [email protected] 1 University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh, UK 2 New York University, Stern School of Business, New York, NY, USA 3 Weill Cornell Medical College, New York, NY, USA 123 Synthese Introduction Consider the following case: car insurance: Your car insurance company offers you a deal.
    [Show full text]
  • Why There Are No Epistemic Duties
    Why There are no Epistemic Duties (Forthcoming in Dialogue: The Canadian Philosophical Review) Chase B. Wrenn Department of Philosophy University of Alabama Abstract Epistemic duties would be duties to believe, disbelieve, or withhold judgment propositions, and they would be grounded in purely evidential considerations. I offer a new argument for the claim that there are no epistemic duties. Though people may have duties to believe, disbelieve, or withhold judgment from propositions, those duties are never grounded in purely epistemic considerations. Rather, allegedly epistemic duties are a species of moral duty. 1 Introduction A person can be morally, legally, or prudentially obligated to do something. There are even cases in which a person might be morally, legally, or prudentially obligated to believe something. Maybe I cannot act rightly without believing in the fundamentally equal moral value of all persons, or maybe the law says I must know the expiration dates on the milk I sell, or maybe it is in my best interest to believe my doctors are competent. Such cases respectively impose moral, legal, and prudential obligations to have certain beliefs. Can a person be epistemically obligated to believe, disbelieve, or withhold judgment about something? An affirmative answer means that there are purely epistemic sources of duty, over and above such other sources as morality, prudence, and law. Usually, those who believe in epistemic duties see them as grounded in the evidence available to a person. I see, hear, and feel the falling rain. Because I have such excellent evidence it is raining, and I lack weightier evidence to the contrary, I epistemically ought to believe it is raining.
    [Show full text]
  • Rational Agnosticism and Degrees of Belief †‡
    Rational Agnosticism and Degrees of Belief †‡ Jane Friedman | [email protected] 08/2013 1 Preliminaries “Traditional” epistemology presents us with a quite spare doxastic taxonomy. This taxonomy is typically thought to include just belief, disbelief and sus- pension of judgment. And given that in this context disbelieving p is thought identical to believing ¬p, traditionalists present us with just two attitudes: belief and suspension of judgment. “Formal” epistemology presents us with an expansive doxastic taxonomy: a subject faces a continuum-many different doxastic options with respect to p. These doxastic states are thought to be something like states of confidence in the truth of the relevant propositions. These states of confidence come in degrees and those degrees of belief (credences) are taken to bear some intimate relation to the probability calculus. A number of interesting questions arise about the relationship between these two doxastic taxonomies. An obviously pressing one is which (if any) are ac- curate: do both of these doxastic taxonomies accurately describe our doxastic lives, or does just one (or does neither)? If only one gives a correct descrip- tion, which one, and what should we say about the other? Many have thought †In Oxford Studies in Epistemology (2013), Volume 4: 57-81. Please cite published version, online here. ‡Thanks to audiences at a conference on the ontology of the doxastic attitudes in Odense, Denmark and at the Pacific APA in San Diego for discussion of some of the arguments here. Thanks to Alan Hájek and an anonymous reviewer for Oxford Studies in Epistemology for ex- tremely helpful written comments.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic’ Mean?
    Phil. 252: Norms of Belief Sept. 6, 2017 Meeting 1: What Does ‘Epistemic’ Mean? I. Uses of ‘Epistemic’ One of the central sets of questions we will be asking in this seminar is: Suppose I am considering whether to believe some proposition, P. What kinds of reasons do I have for and against this belief? Are they exclusively epistemic reasons (such as, for instance, those provided by my evidence for or against P)? Or can they include practical reasons (such as, for instance, those provided by the happiness that believing P would bring about in myself or others)? Notice that, in setting up this issue, I have appealed to the notion of an ‘epistemic reason’. One encounters ‘epistemic’ (and its cognates) a lot in contemporary philosophy. Some other instances: • ‘epistemically justified’ / ‘epistemically warranted’ / ‘epistemically merited’ / ‘epistemically proper’, • ‘epistemically ought’ / ‘epistemic duty’ / ‘epistemic requirement’ / ‘epistemic norm’, • ‘epistemic value’ / ‘epistemic good’ / ‘epistemic goal’, • ‘epistemic responsibility’ / ‘epistemic blame’ / ‘epistemic blameworthiness’, • ‘epistemic injustice’. However, it is not always clear what philosophers mean by ‘epistemic’ in these expressions. II. Cohen’s Challenge In “Theorizing about the Epistemic,” Stewart Cohen goes one step further: he thinks that ‘epistemic’ functions as an undefined technical term in much contemporary epistemology, and as a result it is not even clear what many of these debates are supposed to be about. Let us focus on the case that Cohen makes with regard to debates about epistemic justification: “. ‘epistemic’ is a technical term. If you ask competent, even sophisticated English speakers who are not philosophers whether a belief is epistemically justified, they will have no idea what they are being asked” (p.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Duties and Failure to Understand One's Evidence
    doi: 10.5007/1808-1711.2012v16n1p147 EPISTEMIC DUTIESAND FAILURE TO UNDERSTAND ONE’S EVIDENCE SCOTT STAPLEFORD St. Thomas University Abstract. The paper defends the thesis that our epistemic duty is the duty to proportion our beliefs to the evidence we possess. An inclusive view of evidence possessed is put forward on the grounds that it makes sense of our intuitions about when it is right to say that a person ought to believe some proposition P. A second thesis is that we have no epistemic duty to adopt any particular doxastic attitudes. The apparent tension between the two theses is resolved by applying the concept of duty to belief indirectly. Keywords: Epistemic duties; ethics of belief; doxastic voluntarism; evidence; evidentialism; R. Feldman. Richard Feldman argues that we never have an epistemic duty to believe any propo- sition P that our evidence supports if we fail to apprehend the connection between our evidence and P.1 I argue that an implication of this view is that we never have an epistemic duty to believe any proposition that we do not in fact believe. My argument depends upon the falsity of one fairly implausible version of doxastic vol- untarism. Given that this conclusion conflicts with our understanding of what it is to have a duty, I infer that the only epistemic duty we have is the duty to propor- tion our beliefs to the evidence, a view which is consistent with our never having an epistemic duty to believe some proposition P. The idea that I want to defend is suggested by a passage in John Locke’s Es- say Concerning Human Understanding.
    [Show full text]
  • Doxastic Attitudes As Belief-Revision Policies
    Doxastic Attitudes as Belief-Revision Policies Alexandru Baltag Ben Rodenh¨auser Sonja Smets ILLC, University of Amsterdam Abstract. While propositional doxastic atti- encodes what the recipient will do if an input tudes, like knowledge and belief, capture an from that source is received. agent's opinion about certain propositions, her Traces of this idea are found scattered attitudes towards sources of information express across the literature, sometimes formulated her opinion about the reliability (or trustwor- in terms of notions like \evidential reliabil- thiness) of those sources. If an agent trusts ity" or \epistemic trust".1 In Bayesian Epis- a witness, then she will, within certain limits, temology, the reliability of a source is cap- tend to accept his testimony as veridical. But tured by weights or probabilities attached to if she considers the witness to be a notorious the new information, which determine differ- liar, she may come to believe the opposite of ent ways of processing it (e.g., Bayesian con- what he tells her. In this paper, we put such at- ditioning versus Jeffrey conditioning).2 In titudes towards sources (or dynamic (doxastic) Belief Revision theory, various methods for attitudes) center stage, and formalize them as (iterated) belief revision have been proposed belief-revision strategies: policies governing how that can be understood as corresponding to an agent changess her beliefs whenever new in- different attitudes to the incoming informa- formation from a certain (type of) source is re- tion.3 ceived. We present a semantic, qualitative mod- While most previous authors have focused elling of this notion and investigate its proper- on quantitative approaches formalizing de- ties.
    [Show full text]