Researches on the Clitophon

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Researches on the Clitophon Researches on the Clitophon Pietro Bertocchini, Università di Bologna, [email protected] 1 Status Quaestionis The Clitophon is a dialogue that belongs to the corpus of Platonic writings. However, it has been suspected of being spurious by many scholars. The modern debate began in 1809 when Schleiermacher took position against its authenticity. Since then, a lot of contributions on the topic have been released and a great number of hypothesis of attribution have been formulated. It is worth mentioning at least Grote’s thesis (1865), which speculates that the dialogue had been an introduction (later rejected) to the Republic, as well as Kunert’s essay (1881), which, for the first time, argued that the attack directed towards Socrates within the Clitophon was actually to be understood as directed towards the Socratic Antistenes. It was starting from this hypothesis that Slings (1999) formulated his proposition about the Clitophon in the end of his detailed commentary. According to him, the dialogue could be a literary pamphlet, i.e. a criticism of a specific genre of the Socratic literature that down- graded the philosophical research to a mere act of protrèpein (exhorting). On this basis, Slings claims to be persuaded of the authenticity of the text, though not without some reservations. Recently, there have been more scholars who have argued in favour of the Platonic authorship than not (cf. e.g. Bowe 2007). However, they have simply repeated – with some minor changes – the old interpretation of Socrates’ attack as a merely symbolic one. Neither before nor after Slings’ commentary (1999) has there been work that analyses in depth the language and style of the dialogue as an interesting field of inquiry for its uncertain attribution. Nonetheless, such an object seems to be the most reliable to base Clitophon’s accusation or defence on. I have therefore decided to focus my research on the linguistic and stylistic aspects of the text, aiming at proposing a new and updated analysis, alternative to Slings’ one. Both qualitative and quantitative analysis were conducted in my Master degree’s thesis. Herein I will especially concentrate on the quantitative aspect, though my research has been, so far, rather focused on the qualitative one. 2 Qualitative Analysis In the first place I approached the problem in a traditional way. In fact, I produced a com- mentary in which I stopped at every passage of the dialogue that was, each one for a different reason, suspected of not being Platonic. For every passage, I analysed the arguments - both in favour and against the authenticity - that were raised by the passage itself. This first stage of the research brought to attention that the reasons for concern are arguably more numer- ous and more serious than Slings had pointed out in his 1999’s commentary: some verb 177 178 P. Bertocchini phrases, single terms, or utterances of various lengths were found to be in contrast with the Platonic language as it is known from the other writings of the corpus. Moreover, a limited number of odd passages were identified as possibly caused by some clumsy imitation of other passages belonging to undoubtedly Platonic dialogues, and such a procedure could hardly be ascribed to Plato. Among the various aspects touched upon in the commentary, it is worth mentioning the problem of the potential date of the dialogue within Plato’s production. On this point, the conclusion that had already been reached by others – i.e. that the Clitophon needs to be grouped with the dialogues of the last period (Sophist, Statesman, Philebus, Timaeus, Critias, Laws) – appeared to be confirmed and, in some cases, even reinforced by new evidence. Yet, the consistency of language and style thus found with these other Platonic writings did not seem sufficient to erase the suspicion of inauthenticity. 3 Quantitative Analysis Even though the analysis on the single dubious passages is far from being concluded (as therefore is the authenticity’s issue), I decided to undertake, in parallel to it, some stylo- metric researches aimed at gathering new evidence to be compared with that previously found1. Though during the qualitative analysis I had taken into consideration some spe- cific passages, at this second stage I tried to assess the overall features of the language and style. In other words, I looked for unperceived stylistic tics, typical constructions, and distinguishing marks, which even the most skilful forger would have trouble to perfectly reproduce. Had the Clitophon proved to be significantly different from the norm outlined by the other dialogues, it would have emerged as important evidence against authenticity. In order to be fully reliable, such a test should compare the dialogue under debate with all the other writings of the Platonic corpus2, or even involve one or more contemporary authors as terms of comparison (e.g. Xenophon, the orators). At this point of the research, however, this was not possible. Nonetheless, as an initial sample for developing some ex- ploratory researches, I was able to gain access to a corpus composed of 16 dialogues3, that is about one-third of the Platonic writings (having taken into account the different lengths of the texts). Among these, 13 are normally considered authentic, while 3 (Alcibiades II, Hip- parcus, Rival Lovers) are believed to be spurious by most scholars. Such a corpus was edited, on behalf of the “Laboratoire d’Analyse Statistique des Langues Anciennes” (LASLA) based in Liège, by Mauro Siviero, who manually4 assigned information to each word of every di- 1Platonic scholars long ago discovered the potentiality of statistical procedures. Yet, they have been mainly employed in the investigation of the long debated problem of the dialogues’ internal chronological order (cf. e.g. Campbell 1867, Ledger 1989, Brandwood 1990). As far as Plato is concerned, it is rare to see such procedures applied to questions of authorship attribution. However, an example of this can be found in Ledger (1989), who, among other important contributions, signalled that the Hippias Major and the Rival Lovers were stylistically closer to Xenophon’s writings than to Plato’s ones. 2On the contrary, a comparison with a corpus that comprehended only the dialogues purportedly belong- ing to the same period (Sophist, Statesman, Philebus, Timaeus, Critias, Laws) would have proved to be useless for the question of authenticity. In fact, such a comparison would probably confirm some sort of resemblance between these texts and the Clitophon. Yet, as stated earlier, such a result would not be decisive. 3Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Cratylus, Theaetetus, Sophist, Statesman, Parmenides, Philebus, Sympo- sium, Phaedrus, Alcibiades I, Alcibiades II, Hipparchus, Rival Lovers. 4The manually performed lemmatisation is one of the main qualities of LASLA’s corpus, together with Researches on the Clitophon 179 alogue, such as a) its lemma (attributed on account of LSJ9), and b) a symbol representing the grammatical category (or POS: Part Of Speech) to which the word belonged5. Once the same lemmatisation process was implemented for Clitophon’s text, it was possible to recompose a database with homogeneous features, comprehensive of 17 dialogues. Some new and automatically deducible information was then added to the already given one: c) word’s length; d) POS’ variability or invariability; e) lemma’s frequency within LASLA’s corpus. As this preparatory phase was concluded, I identified ten indicators6 in order to measure if and how Clitophon’s behaviour was inconsistent with the remaining 16 dialogues. Since the analysed features were unmarked linguistic traits, which are involuntary for the most part, it seems that the neutrality of the choice of the phenomena to be analysed has been partly granted. Even so, some part of subjectivity is clearly inescapable. The ten indicators can be summarised as follows: 1. Lemmata variety index. 2. Percentage of the six most frequent lemmata within LASLA’s corpus. 3. Average percentage of lemmata belonging to some specific POS (substantives, adjec- tives, verbs, adverbs) within LASLA’s corpus. 4. Coexistence ratio of variable and invariable words. 5. Average length (n° of letters) of the words. 6. Coexistence ratio of ὅς and ὅστιc. 7. Index of dissimilarity between POS frequency distribution of each dialogue and of LASLA’s corpus. 8. Index of dissimilarity between lemmata frequency distribution of each dialogue and of LASLA’s corpus. 9. Percentage of lemmata non occurring in other dialogues. 10. Percentage of three lemmata sequences non occurring in other dialogues. the annotation for each word of its respective part of speech (POS). For future research it would certainly be useful to gain access to the databases provided with all the dialogues. A database of this type is, for example, the one edited by Bombacigno as a part of Radice’s lexicon (2004). Even though in this case the lemmatisation was performed through semi-automatic procedures, the curators’ équipe assures to have manually intervened on each case the software was not able to solve. 5This information comes from LASLA’s official website. A detailed illustration of the criteria adopted by LASLA’s group is found in Denooz (1988, II-IV). 6Some others indicators were rejected as redundant since they measured the same phenomenon in two different ways. 180 P. Bertocchini 4 Length factor The results’ analysis and interpretation required taking into account the distortions that could derive from the extreme shortness of the Clitophon (1.564 words). In fact, among the writings included in LASLA’s corpus – together with those normally held to be spurious (Alcibiades II, Hipparcus and Rival Lovers which amount, respectively, to 4.211, 2.270 and 2.418 words) – the only one whose length is comparable to Clitophon’s length is the Al- cibiades II (1.650). The Crito (4.164 words), the Euthyphro (5.187) and the Apology (8.786) too can be grouped as relatively short dialogues if compared to the other nine, whose di- mensions are radically superior (they range from Sophist’s 16.199 words to Phaedo’s 22.440).
Recommended publications
  • Clitophon's Challenge and the Aporia of Socratic Protreptic* Teruo Mishima
    Clitophon’s Challenge and the Aporia of Socratic Protreptic* Teruo Mishima Before I discuss the text in detail, I would like to briefly sketch the main line of arguments in the Clitophon which I am going to take up, just for the sake of anamnēsis of the readers : In the opening scene Socrates speaks to Clitophon in the third person and tells him that he heard from somebody else that Clitophon, in his conversation with Lysias, has criticised Socratic diatribai (pursuits), whereas he has lavishly praised his synousia (association) with Thrasymachus. Taking Socrates’ words as a sort of disguised criticism or complaint, Clitophon answers that the story was only half true, because although he did on the one hand criticise Socrates, he also on the other hand highly praised him. Then, he explains to Socrates why he must take such an ambiguous attitude towards him. In the first half of his speech he focuses on the aspect of Socratic teaching which he admires unreservedly, namely Socrates’ protreptic speech towards virtues. Here he refers to a lot of Socratic dicta which remind us of well known passages in the early dialogues of Plato. By contrast, in the latter half Clitophon explains where his deep frustration with Socrates lies. He says that, being already converted by Socratic protreptic and resolved to pursue virtues, what he expects now from Socrates is “what comes next”, that is a detailed account of the essence of virtues to be acquired and a piece of concrete advice on how to acquire them. But to these - Clitophon complains - neither Socrates’ company nor Socrates himself gives any convincing answer.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpretation: a Journal of Political Philosophy
    Interpretation A JOURNAL A OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY Winter 1993-1994 Volume 21 Number 2 Thomas Lewis Identifying Rhetoric in the Apology: Does Socrates Use the Appeal for Pity? Joel Warren Lidz Reflections on and in Plato's Cave Bernard Jacob Aristotle's Dialectical Purposes Mary L. Bellhouse Rousseau Under Surveillance: Thoughts on a New Edition and Translation of Rousseau, Judge of Jean-Jacques: Dialogues Peter Augustine Lawler Tocqueville on Socialism and History Maurice Auerbach Carl Schmitt's Quest for the Political: Theology, Decisionism, and the Concept of the Enemy Discussion Victor Gourevich The End of History? Book Reviews Will Morrisey Self-Knowledge in Plato's Phaedrus, by Charles L. Griswold, Jr. Leslie G. Rubin Citizens and Statesmen: A Study of Aristotle's Politics, by Mary P. Nichols John S. Waggoner The Liberal Political Science of Raymond Aron: A Critical Introduction, by Daniel J. Mahoney Interpretation Editor-in-Chief Hilail Gildin, Dept. of Philosophy, Queens College Executive Editor Leonard Grey General Editors Seth G. Benardete Charles E. Butterworth Hilail Gildin Robert Horwitz (d. 1987) Howard B. White (d. 1974) Consulting Editors Christopher Bruell Joseph Cropsey Ernest L. Fortin John Hallowell (d. 1992) Harry V. Jaffa David Lowenthal Muhsin Mahdi Harvey C. Mansfield, Jr. Arnaldo Momigliano (d. 1987) Michael Oakeshott (d. 1990) Ellis Sandoz Leo Strauss (d. 1973) Kenneth W. Thompson European Editors Terence E. Marshall Heinrich Meier Editors Wayne Ambler Maurice Auerbach Fred Baumann Michael Blaustein - Patrick Coby Edward J. Erler Maureen Feder-Marcus Joseph E. Goldberg Stephen Harvey Pamela K. Jensen Ken Masugi Grant B. Mindle James W. Morris Will Morrisey Aryeh L.
    [Show full text]
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche's Views on Plato Pre-Basel
    Sophia and Philosophia Volume 1 Issue 1 Spring-Summer Article 6 4-1-2016 Nietzsche's Views on Plato Pre-Basel Daniel Blue [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.belmont.edu/sph Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, German Language and Literature Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons, and the Metaphysics Commons Recommended Citation Blue, Daniel (2016) "Nietzsche's Views on Plato Pre-Basel," Sophia and Philosophia: Vol. 1 : Iss. 1 , Article 6. Available at: https://repository.belmont.edu/sph/vol1/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Belmont Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Sophia and Philosophia by an authorized editor of Belmont Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. S.Ph. Essays and Explorations 1.1 Copyright 2016, S.Ph. Press Nietzsche’s Views on Plato Pre-Basel Daniel Blue In an essay published in 20041 Thomas Brobjer surveyed Nietzsche’s attitudes toward Plato and argued that, far from entering into a dedicated agon with that philosopher, he had little personal engagement with Plato’s views at all. Certainly, he did not grapple so immediately and fruitfully with him as he did with Emerson, Schopenhauer, Lange, and even Socrates. Instead, he merely “set up a caricature of Plato as a representative of the metaphysical tradition … to which he opposed his own.”2 This hardly reflects the view of Nietzsche scholarship in general, but Brobjer argued his case vigorously by ranging broadly over Nietzsche’s life, collating his assessments of Plato, and then noting certain standard views which he believes to be overstated.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Athenian Democracy.Pdf
    Rethinking Athenian Democracy A dissertation presented by Daniela Louise Cammack to The Department of Government in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the subject of Political Science Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts January 2013 © 2013 Daniela Cammack All rights reserved. Professor Richard Tuck Daniela Cammack Abstract Conventional accounts of classical Athenian democracy represent the assembly as the primary democratic institution in the Athenian political system. This looks reasonable in the light of modern democracy, which has typically developed through the democratization of legislative assemblies. Yet it conflicts with the evidence at our disposal. Our ancient sources suggest that the most significant and distinctively democratic institution in Athens was the courts, where decisions were made by large panels of randomly selected ordinary citizens with no possibility of appeal. This dissertation reinterprets Athenian democracy as “dikastic democracy” (from the Greek dikastēs, “judge”), defined as a mode of government in which ordinary citizens rule principally through their control of the administration of justice. It begins by casting doubt on two major planks in the modern interpretation of Athenian democracy: first, that it rested on a conception of the “wisdom of the multitude” akin to that advanced by epistemic democrats today, and second that it was “deliberative,” meaning that mass discussion of political matters played a defining role. The first plank rests largely on an argument made by Aristotle in support of mass political participation, which I show has been comprehensively misunderstood. The second rests on the interpretation of the verb “bouleuomai” as indicating speech, but I suggest that it meant internal reflection in both the courts and the assembly.
    [Show full text]
  • Silencing the Female Voice in Longus and Achilles Tatius
    Silencing the female voice in Longus and Achilles Tatius Word Count: 12,904 Exam Number: B052116 Classical Studies MA (Hons) School of History, Classics and Archaeology University of Edinburgh B052116 Acknowledgments I am indebted to the brilliant Dr Calum Maciver, whose passion for these novels is continually inspiring. Thank you for your incredible supervision and patience. I’d also like to thank Dr Donncha O’Rourke for his advice and boundless encouragement. My warmest thanks to Sekheena and Emily for their assistance in proofreading this paper. To my fantastic circle of Classics girls, thank you for your companionship and humour. Thanks to my parents for their love and support. To Ben, for giving me strength and light. And finally, to the Edinburgh University Classics Department, for a truly rewarding four years. 1 B052116 Table of Contents Acknowledgments………………………………………………………………………….1 List of Abbreviations………………………………………………………………………3 Introduction ……………………………………………………………………………….4 Chapter 1: Through the Male Lens………………………………………………………6 The Aftertaste of Sophrosune……………………………………………………………….6 Male Viewers and Voyeuristic Fantasy.…………………………………………………....8 Narratorial Manipulation of Perspective………………………………………………….11 Chapter 2: The Mythic Hush…………………………………………………………….15 Echoing Violence in Longus……………………………………………………………….16 Making a myth out of Chloe………………………………………………………………..19 Leucippe and Europa: introducing the mythic parallel……………………………………21 Andromeda, Philomela and Procne: shifting perspectives………………………………...22 Chapter 3: Rupturing the
    [Show full text]
  • The Spell of Achilles Tatius: Magic and Metafiction in Leucippe and Clitophon
    The Spell of Achilles Tatius: Magic and Metafiction in Leucippe and Clitophon ASHLI J.E. BAKER Bucknell University Eros is “…δεινὸς γόης καὶ φαρμακεὺς καὶ σοφιστής…” (Plato, Symposium 203d) Introduction In the beginning of Book Two of Achilles Tatius’ Leucippe and Clitophon, the clever but thus far failed lover Clitophon witnesses a remarkable – and useful – scene. He passes by just as Clio, Leucippe’s slave, is stung on the hand by a bee. He sees Leucippe soothe Clio’s pain by singing incantations (ἐπᾴδω) she says she learned from an Egyptian woman.1 When Clitophon, determined to woo Leu- cippe, finds himself alone with her on the following day, he pretends that he too has been stung by a bee. Leucippe approaches, asking where he has been stung. In reply, Clitophon says, ————— 1 παύσειν γὰρ αὐτὴν τῆς ἀλγηδόνος δύο ἐπᾴσασαν ῥήματα· διδαχθῆναι γὰρ αὐτὴν ὑπό τινος Αἰγυπτίας εἰς πληγὰς σφηκῶν καὶ μελιττῶν. Καὶ ἅμα ἐπῇδε· καὶ ἔλεγεν ἡ Κλειὼ μετὰ μικρὸν ῥᾴων γεγονέναι. (2.7 - “…she would, she said, stop her pain by chanting two spells; she had been taught by an Egyptian woman how to deal with wasp- and bee-stings. As she had chanted, Clio had said that the pain was gradually relieved.”). All Greek text of Leu- cippe and Clitophon is that of Garnaud 1991. All translations are cited, with occasional alterations, from Whitmarsh 2001. I want to give special thanks to Catherine Connors for her insightful comments throughout the drafting of this paper. Thanks too to Alex Hollmann and Stephen Trzaskoma for feedback on earlier versions of this project.
    [Show full text]
  • Euanthes and the World of Rhetoric in Achilles Tatius' Leucippe And
    Euanthes and the World of Rhetoric in Achilles Tatius’ Leucippe and Cleitophon KATHERINE A. MCHUGH The University of Edinburgh In Book Three of Achilles Tatius’ Leucippe and Cleitophon there is an ekphrasis of a painting, one of three within the entirety of the novel. The description takes place after the protagonists’ arrival at Pelusium, as they happen upon the Temple of Zeus and come across “double images” (εἰκόνα διπλῆν, 3,6,3) which have been signed by the artist Euanthes (3,6,3).1 The main aim of this article is to consider the name of this artist, as opposed to the painting itself; it seeks to prove that Euanthes was not a real figure, but a name created by Achilles which is imbued with rhetorical references in keeping with the intellectual climate of 2nd Century AD Greek literature. The name Euanthes and its possible rhetorical connotations will be explored in conjunction with a detailed consideration of Achilles’ use of ekphrasis throughout Leucippe and Cleitophon and his interest in rhetorical edu- cation in order to assert that some of the author’s playful in-jokes have been un- derstudied, and that they can provide us with a clearer picture of how the author strives to appeal to his reader; that is, a reader who is steeped in a rhetorical edu- cation himself. The article also considers the other two ekphraseis of paintings in Leucippe and Cleitophon (which occur in Books One and Five) in order to aid with an understanding of Achilles’ use of the rhetorical technique and how sig- nificant rhetoric is to his novel as a whole.
    [Show full text]
  • Clitophon and Socrates in the Platonic Clitophon
    Ancient Philosophy 32 (2012) ©Mathesis Publications 1 Clitophon and Socrates in the Platonic Clitophon Christopher Moore The Clitophon shows us a man similar to Socrates in analytic skill, social ease, frankness, and avowed interest in justice. He praises Socrates for bringing people to desire to be just, but criticizes Socrates for not helping them be just, the object of their desire. H gives his experience as an example: having listened to Socrates he desires justice, but does not know how to be just. Readers have often accepted both the cogency of and warrant for Clitophon’s criticism. But details of the dia - logue undermine both. Its characterization of Socrates shows that desiring to be just, considered robustly—recognizing one’s ignorance, listening to other views, and trying to learn about the good—is much the same as being just, and so Socrates cannot be faulted for merely inculcating the desire. And though Cli - tophon has heard Scorates speak and is interested in justice—especially in find - ing some apt formula—he has not listened closely to Socrates, and therefore has not allowed himself to be brought fully into desiring to be just. Therefore, he fails, both theoretically and personally, to understand Socrates’ efforts, and so his criticism fails too. The dialogue begins with Socrates reporting a rumor. He heard that Clitophon disparaged their time together but raved about his time with Thrasymachus. Cli - tophon calls this rumor mistaken. Far from disparaging their time together, Cli - tophon says, he lauded much about Socrates. He asks leave to speak frankly. He wants to give a fuller report about what he actually said to Lysias, the source of the rumor.
    [Show full text]
  • Speusippus and Xenocrates on the Pursuit and Ends of Philosophy
    chapter 1 Speusippus and Xenocrates on the Pursuit and Ends of Philosophy Phillip Sidney Horky I Introduction The educational and institutional structure of the Academy after Plato’s death is one of the great unknowns in the history of ancient philosophy.1 Harold Cherniss, who thought the answer might lie in the educational curriculum out- lined in Republic VII, dubbed it the great “riddle of the early Academy”;2 con- trariwise, in considering the external evidence provided by Plato’s students and contemporaries, John Dillon speaks of a “fairly distinctive, though still quite open-ended, intellectual tradition.”3 One would think, especially given the extent of Plato’s discussion of the problem of educational and institution- al structures (not to mention the pedagogic journey of the individual teacher and student) that those figures who took over supervision of the Academy after Plato’s death – notably his polymath nephew Speusippus of Athens and his pop- ular and brilliant student Xenocrates of Chalcedon4 – would have devoted some attention to this issue of educational theory and practice in their writings. Af- ter all, several pseudepigraphical texts that are usually considered to have been written in the Academy and were ascribed to Plato – Theages, Alcibiades I (if inau- thentic), Alcibiades II, Epinomis, Rival Lovers, On Virtue, the Seventh Letter – do, indeed, devote significant space to elaborating pedagogical methods, practices, 1 Special thanks are owed to Mauro Bonazzi, Giulia De Cesaris, and David Sedley, each of whom read this piece with care and attention. I cannot promise to have responded suffi- ciently to their challenges in all circumstances, but I can say with confidence that this paper is much improved owing to their critical acumen.
    [Show full text]
  • The Wisdom of Noble Simplicity
    The Εὐηθέστεροι Myth: the Wisdom of Noble Simplicity L. M. J. Coulson A Thesis Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Classics and Ancient History School of Philosophical and Historical Inquiry Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences The University of Sydney November 2016 Statement of Originality This is to certify that to the best of my knowledge, the content of this thesis is my own work. This thesis has not been submitted for any degree or other purposes. I certify that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work and that all the assistance received in preparing this thesis and sources have been acknowledged. L. M. J. Coulson November 2016 i Acknowledgements Throughout this undertaking it has been my great good fortune and privilege to have the gracious and generous support of my family, supervisors and colleagues. On November 5, 2012 Professor Eric Csapo and I met for the first time. At that meeting Eric suggested the apparently paradoxical use of εὐήθεια in Ancient Greece as a postgraduate research topic. This thesis is a direct consequence of his suggestion, encouragement and forbearance. Eric’s erudition in the Classics’ disciplines is extraordinary and gives constant cause for admiration. Professor Rick Benitez is officially designated as my auxiliary supervisor. However, he has been far more that that, especially in the last year of this project when the depth of his Platonic scholarship and generous support made an invaluable contribution to the completion of this thesis. I am grateful for the opportunity to have worked closely with these exceptional scholars.
    [Show full text]