Experience and Belief

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Experience and Belief EXPERIENCE AND BELIEF AN INQUIRY INTO THE DOXASTIC VARIABILITY OF EXPERIENCE by Tom Raja Rosenhagen M.A., Westfälische Wilhelms-Universität Münster 2005 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Kenneth P. Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2018 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH THE KENNETH P. DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Tom Raja Rosenhagen It was defended on June 21, 2018 and approved by Anil Gupta, Alan Ross Anderson Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy John McDowell, Distinguished University Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy Robert B. Brandom, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy Edouard Machery, Distinguished Professor of History and Philosophy of Science, Department of History and Philosophy of Science Dissertation Director: Anil Gupta, Alan Ross Anderson Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy ii Copyright © by Tom Raja Rosenhagen 2018 iii EXPERIENCE AND BELIEF AN INQUIRY INTO THE DOXASTIC VARIABILITY OF EXPERIENCE Tom Raja Rosenhagen, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2018 If what we believe can directly modify our (visual) experience, our experience is doxastically variable. If so, the following seems possible: our false and irrational background beliefs can modify our experience such that in it, things look distorted, or that it conforms with and appears to confirm the false and irrational beliefs that helped bring it about in the first place. If experience is doxastically variable, it seems, its epistemic function can be undermined. However, in this dissertation, I argue that we can devise accounts of (visual) experience that meet two requirements: they are fully compatible with all kinds of doxastic variation and on them, even doxastically variable experience serves to rationally constrain our beliefs. I begin with a novel interpretation of Hanson’s account of theory-laden observation—a valiant, yet ultimately unsuccessful attempt to meet both these requirements. Next, I analyze and reject various contemporary relationalist accounts of experience and the most sophisticated recent representationalist attempt to accommodate phenomena of doxastic variation: Siegel’s (Rich) Content View. Then, based on the lessons learned and drawing on Hanson’s and Gupta’s work, I show what shape a successful account may take. Ultimately, I argue for the following theses: 1) Neither of the two dominant accounts of experience—relationalism and standard representationalism—currently succeeds in satisfactorily meeting both requirements. 2) To arrive at accounts that do meet them, we should drop both the restrictive relationalist conception of experience as a relation to mind-independent items and the standard representationalist conception of experience as justifying beliefs. 3) We make progress by iv adopting both the general conception of experience as making rational transitions to beliefs, judgments, and actions and a (slightly) modified version of Gupta’s presentationalist account of experiential phenomenology. Finally, 4) the possibility of devising successful accounts is independent of a major issue dividing relationalists and representationalists: whether experience has content. In the final chapters, I address various follow-up questions concerning the nature of views, conceptual capacities, conceptual content, and linkages between a subject’s experience and her responses. In concluding, I show that the account of experience I recommend is widely applicable in philosophy and beyond. v TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE x 1.0 INTRODUCTION 1 2.0 HANSON’S ACCOUNT OF THEORY-LADEN OBSERVATION 9 2.1 EPISTEMICALLY SIGNIFICANT SEEING INVOLVES SEEING AS 11 2.2 SEEING AS IS INTELLIGIBLE ONLY IN TERMS OF SEEING THAT 13 2.3 THROUGH SEEING AS, BELIEFS CAN AFFECT ONE’S VISUAL FIELD 22 2.3.1 What’s Wrong with Sense-Datum Accounts 22 2.3.2 The Organization of the Visual Field 25 2.3.3 Effects on the Elements of the Visual Field 28 2.4 DOES OBSERVATION CONSTRAIN OUR BELIEFS? 29 2.5 PHENOMENOLOGY, EMPIRICAL CONSTRAINT, AND AMALGAMATION 34 3.0 FROM HANSON TO RELATIONALISM 38 3.1 NO CONTENT, ACQUAINTANCE, AND CONSTITUTION 45 3.2 RELATIONALISM, DVEC, BMCEC, AND BMCC 52 3.3 HANSON AND RELATIONALISM 55 4.0 RELATIONALISM I: FISH’S OBJECT-PROPERTY VIEW 60 4.1 CONSTITUTION, THE PHENOMENAL, THE PRESENTATIONAL, AND CONSTRAINING FACTORS 60 4.2 NO ACQUAINTANCE WITHOUT CONCEPTUAL CAPACITIES: FISH ON EXPERT VISION 68 4.3 IDENTITY*, SUPERVENIENCE, AND INTERSUBJECTIVE COMMONALITIES 72 4.4 FACTS, PROPERTIES, AND CONCEPTUAL CAPACITIES 78 4.5 BASIC ACQUAINTANCE AND PROJECTION EFFECTS 88 4.5.1 Basic Acquaintance 88 4.5.2 Projection Effects 91 vi 4.5.2.1 The Banana Case 93 4.5.2.2 Physical Illusions 95 4.5.2.3 Cognitive Illusions 99 4.5.2.4 Optical Illusions 105 4.6 CONCLUSION 107 5.0 RELATIONALISM II: BREWER’S OBJECT VIEW 109 5.1 THINLY AND THICKLY LOOKING OBJECTS 111 5.2 WAYS OF THINLY LOOKING AND VISUALLY RELEVANT SIMILARITY RELATIONS 112 5.3 THINLY LOOKING THE SAME, NO DVEP FOR THIN LOOKS, BREWERIAN CONSTITUTION, AND THE GENERAL CONSTRAINT ON THIN LOOKS 117 5.4 THICKLY LOOKING SOME WAY 123 5.5 FISH AND BREWER 125 5.6 MULTIPLE PHENOMENOLOGIES AND (AGAIN) THE BANANA CASE 131 5.7 CONCLUSION 140 6.0 RELATIONALISM III: GENONE’S PROPERTY VIEW 142 6.1 APPEARANCES AS MIND-INDEPENDENT PROPERTIES 146 6.2 GENONE’S (MISSING) ACCOUNT OF CONSTITUTION 154 6.3 MISLEADING APPEARANCES AND DVEP 159 6.3.1 Misleading Appearances 159 6.3.2 Genonean Expert Vision 164 6.3.3 The Banana Case—Strategy 1: Phenomenal Pluralism 169 6.3.4 The Banana Case—Strategy 2: Appearance-Judgment Relations Shifted 174 6.4 OPEN QUESTIONS 180 6.4.1 Phenomenal Pluralism After All? 180 6.4.2 Flexibility—an Epistemic Downside? 182 6.4.3 Appearance-Judgment Relations 186 6.5 LEAVING RELATIONALISM BEHIND 189 7.0 SIEGEL’S RICH CONTENT VIEW 194 7.1 THE CONTENT VIEW 197 7.1.1 Siegel’s Notion of Visual Experience 198 vii 7.1.2 Content-Bearing Phenomenal States 201 7.1.3 The Argument from Appearing 206 7.1.4 Which Properties do Phenomenal States Represent? 212 7.1.4.1 Non-Arbitrariness and Expert Vision 214 7.1.4.2 Phenomenal States and Their Contents 217 7.1.5 Implications 229 7.2 THE RATIONAL ROLE OF SIEGELIAN EXPERIENCE 233 7.2.1 Irrational Experiences and Reduced Epistemic Powers 234 7.2.2 Objections 241 7.3 THE GENERAL ROLE OF EXPERIENCE 250 7.3.1 Dropping the Standard Representationalist Conception of the Role of Experience 250 7.3.2 No Defensive Measures Necessary 255 7.3.3 The Alternative 256 7.3.4 Taking Stock 262 8.0 HANSON REVAMPED 263 8.1 A HANSONIAN VARIABLE CONTENT VIEW 265 8.1.1 Experiential Content 266 8.1.2 Empirical Constraint Recouched 269 8.1.3 Amalgamation 274 8.1.4 Modifiable Amalgamation, Genonean Misleading Appearances, and Seeings As as Dispositional States 277 8.1.5 Stable Amalgamations 279 8.2 ACTUAL VS. RATIONAL TRANSITIONS & CONCLUDING REMARKS 281 9.0 GUPTA’S PRESENTATIONALISM 287 9.1 APPEARANCES 291 9.1.1 Subjective Identity, Color Appearances, Projection Effects, and Expert Vision Proper 292 9.1.2 Appearances and Manifestation, Total Hallucinations, the Items Requirement on Appearance, and Projection Effects Again 298 9.2 LINKAGES 306 9.2.1 Linkages in Views 308 viii 9.2.2 Linkage Institution 314 9.2.3 Ineffability 317 9.3 TAKING STOCK 324 10.0 CONCLUSION 327 10.1 SUMMARY 327 10.2 LESSONS LEARNED 343 10.3 THE NO PHENOMENOLOGY CHALLENGE AND THE RECEPTIVE KNOWLEDGE COMPLAINT 346 10.3.1 The No Phenomenology Challenge 347 10.3.2 The Receptive Knowledge Complaint 355 10.3.2.1 McDowell on Receptive Knowledge 356 10.3.2.2 Hansonian Receptive Knowledge 362 10.4 STILL NO END IN SIGHT: OPEN QUESTIONS AND FURTHER AVENUES TO PURSUE 367 BIBLIOGRAPHY 376 ix PREFACE “बिन गु셁 ज्ञान कह ॉंसे पाऊँ ।” Mohammad Rafi (1952). Man Tarpat Hari Darshan Ko Aaj. Baiju Bawra This is a long dissertation. Also, it has been long in the making. I cannot pinpoint exactly when I began to think about the so-called theory-ladenness of observation, but I suspect that it must have been roughly 15 years ago, when at the University of Münster, I participated in a reading group on philosophy of science and somehow happened upon Norwood Russell Hanson’s first chapter of his 1958 book Patterns of Discovery—the chapter on observation—in which the term ‘theory-ladenness of observation’ is coined. It is impossible to say how often I have read this chapter since, or the much more extended version of the arguments it contains that spans several chapters in Hanson’s posthumously published Perception and Discovery. Not only did I reread this material frequently, I also drew on the concept of theory-ladenness in my Master’s thesis on Bas van Fraassen’s constructive empiricism. In it, I complained, inter alia, that van Fraassen does not provide us with a notion of experience that fits his empiricist leanings. Accordingly, I submitted, we cannot assess whether his account improves over that once proposed by the Logical Empiricists, whose notion of experience, arguably, was ill-suited to accommodate theory-ladenness. I repeatedly presented on Hanson’s work and on theory-ladenness in general at various conferences and Hanson’s chapter on observation became a standard syllabus component whenever I taught introductory classes on philosophy of science. Typically, my audiences—and many students, too—enjoyed Hanson’s work and what I extracted from it, but only a handful of people had even so much as heard about Hanson before. And among these select few, even fewer had read anything of him, and nobody had ever read it the way I think we should.
Recommended publications
  • Logic in Action: Wittgenstein's Logical Pragmatism and the Impotence of Scepticism
    This is the final, pre-publication draft. Please cite only from published paper in Philosophical Investigations 26:2 (April 2003), 125-48. LOGIC IN ACTION: WITTGENSTEIN'S LOGICAL PRAGMATISM AND THE IMPOTENCE OF SCEPTICISM DANIÈLE MOYAL-SHARROCK UNIVERSITY OF GENEVA 1. The Many Faces of Certainty: Wittgenstein's Logical Pragmatism So I am trying to say something that sounds like pragmatism. (OC 422) In his struggle to uncover the nature of our basic beliefs, Wittgenstein depicts them variously in On Certainty: he thinks of them in propositional terms, in pictorial terms and in terms of acting. As propositions, they would be of a peculiar sort – a hybrid between a logical and an empirical proposition (OC 136, 309). These are the so-called 'hinge propositions' of On Certainty (OC 341). Wittgenstein also thinks of these beliefs as forming a picture, a World-picture – or Weltbild (OC 167). This is a step in the right (nonpropositional) direction, but not the ultimate step. Wittgenstein's ultimate and crucial depiction of our basic beliefs is in terms of a know-how, an attitude, a way of acting (OC 204). Here, he treads on pragmatist ground. But can Wittgenstein be labelled a pragmatist, having himself rejected the affiliation because of its utility implication? But you aren't a pragmatist? No. For I am not saying that a proposition is true if it is useful. (RPP I, 266) Wittgenstein resists affiliation with pragmatism because he does not want his use of use to be confused with the utility use of use. For him, it is not that a proposition is true if it is useful, but that use gives the proposition its sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Generalized Molecular Formulas in Logical Atomism
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy An Argument for Completely General Facts: Volume 9, Number 7 Generalized Molecular Formulas in Logical Editor in Chief Atomism Audrey Yap, University of Victoria Landon D. C. Elkind Editorial Board Annalisa Coliva, UC Irvine In his 1918 logical atomism lectures, Russell argued that there are Vera Flocke, Indiana University, Bloomington no molecular facts. But he posed a problem for anyone wanting Henry Jackman, York University to avoid molecular facts: we need truth-makers for generaliza- Frederique Janssen-Lauret, University of Manchester tions of molecular formulas, but such truth-makers seem to be Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts both unavoidable and to have an abominably molecular charac- Consuelo Preti, The College of New Jersey ter. Call this the problem of generalized molecular formulas. I clarify Marcus Rossberg, University of Connecticut the problem here by distinguishing two kinds of generalized Anthony Skelton, Western University molecular formula: incompletely generalized molecular formulas Mark Textor, King’s College London and completely generalized molecular formulas. I next argue that, if empty worlds are logically possible, then the model-theoretic Editors for Special Issues and truth-functional considerations that are usually given ad- Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University dress the problem posed by the first kind of formula, but not the Alexander Klein, McMaster University problem posed by the second kind. I then show that Russell’s Review Editors commitments in 1918 provide an answer to the problem of com- Sean Morris, Metropolitan State University of Denver pletely generalized molecular formulas: some truth-makers will Sanford Shieh, Wesleyan University be non-atomic facts that have no constituents.
    [Show full text]
  • Redalyc.Logical Consequence for Nominalists
    THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia ISSN: 0495-4548 [email protected] Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea España ROSSBERG, Marcus; COHNITZ, Daniel Logical Consequence for Nominalists THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, vol. 24, núm. 2, 2009, pp. 147- 168 Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea Donostia-San Sebastián, España Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=339730809003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative Logical Consequence for Nominalists Marcus ROSSBERG and Daniel COHNITZ BIBLID [0495-4548 (2009) 24: 65; pp. 147-168] ABSTRACT: It has repeatedly been argued that nominalistic programmes in the philosophy of mathematics fail, since they will at some point or other involve the notion of logical consequence which is unavailable to the nominalist. In this paper we will argue that this is not the case. Using an idea of Nelson Goodman and W.V.Quine's which they developed in Goodman and Quine (1947) and supplementing it with means that should be nominalistically acceptable, we present a way to explicate logical consequence in a nominalistically acceptable way. Keywords: Philosophy of mathematics, nominalism, logical consequence, inferentialism, Nelson Goodman, W.V. Quine. 1. The Argument from Logical Consequence We do not have any strong convictions concerning the question of the existence or non- existence of abstract objects. We do, however, believe that ontological fastidiousness is prima facie a good attitude to adopt.
    [Show full text]
  • "Metaphysical" Possibility Revisited
    Justin Clarke-Doane Columbia University “Metaphysical” Possibility Revisited Metaphysical Possibility: That alethic, non-deontic, modality whose necessities are supposed to include the likes of conceptual truths, (pure) mathematical truths, truths of fundamental ontology (such as that there are, or are not, propositions, properties, or possible worlds), mereological truths, identity truths, explanatorily basic normative truths, and grounding truths. o Sider: “We are told that logic…is metaphysically necessary. We are told that laws of nature are not….[I]t is metaphysically necessary that “nothing can be in two places at once”, and so on. This conception falls…short of a full criterion. But a thin conception is not in itself problematic. For when a notion is taken to be fundamental, one often assumes that the facts involving the notion will outrun one's conception [2011, 266].” It is widely agreed that the intelligibility of metaphysical modality has been vindicated. o Quine: “I do not myself make sense…of metaphysical necessity [1990, 224].” o Williamson: “[M]etaphysical modality is only one member of the extended family of objective modalities. Arguments for scepticism about metaphysical modality tend [implausibly] to generalize to other objective modalities [2016, 462].” But even if metaphysical modality is intelligible, it could lack much metaphysical significance. I will argue that this is the case, and will conclude with an alternative conception of possibility. Extant “Deflationist” Critiques Sidelle [1989] & Unger [2014]: “Twin Earth” thought experiments just concern the meaning of a word. We all agree what worlds there are. We just disagree about how to describe them. Problem: This critique is quite limited.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Make Possibility Safe for Empiricists Abstract 1. Introduction
    Draft commenced August 31, 2020. Version of October 16, 26, November 4, 2020; January 12, February 21, March 1, 2021. Typo corrections, August 26, 2021 How to Make Possibility Safe for Empiricists John D. Norton1 Department of History and Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh http://www.pitt.edu/~jdnorton Abstract What is possible, according to the empiricist conception, is what our evidence positively allows; and what is necessary is what it compels. These notions, along with logical possibility, are the only defensible notions of possibility and necessity. In so far as nomic and metaphysical possibilities are defensible, they fall within empirical possibility. These empirical conceptions are incompatible with traditional possible world semantics. Empirically necessary propositions cannot be defined as those true in all possible worlds. There can be empirical possibilities without empirical necessities. The duality of possibility and necessity can be degenerate and can even be falsified. 1. Introduction What are “small-e” empiricist2 philosophers of science, like me, to make of possibilities? They are central to science. Our best theories of gravity and stellar structure tell us that it is 1 My thanks to Yemima Ben-Menahem, Jeremy Butterfield, Patrick Dürr, Carl Hoefer, Edouard Machery, Brian McLoone, James Norton, Matt Parker, Bryan Roberts, Margot Strohminger and Jim Woodward for helpful discussion. They bear no responsibility for the content of this paper other than for failing to talk me out of it. 2 A “small-e” empiricist holds that we can only learn contingent truths of the world from experiences of the world. A “big-E” Empiricist holds the stronger view that these experiences are all we can learn.
    [Show full text]
  • An Argument for Completely General Facts: Generalized Molecular Formulas in Logical Atomism
    An Argument for Completely General Facts: Generalized Molecular Formulas in Logical Atomism Abstract In his 1918 logical atomism lectures, Russell argued that there are no molecular facts. But he posed a problem for anyone wanting to avoid molecular facts: we need truth-makers for generalizations of molecular formulas, but such truth-makers seem to be both unavoidable and to have an abominably molecular character. We might call this the problem of generalized molecular formulas. I clarify the problem here by first distinguishing two cases: incompletely generalized molecular formulas and completely generalized molecular formulas. I next argue that, if empty worlds are logically possible, then the model- theoretic truth-functional considerations that are usually given address the first kind of formula, but not the second kind. I then show that the commitments Russell has already made provide an answer to the problem of completely generalized molecular formulas. An upshot of this discussion is that, assuming empty worlds are logically possible, some truth-makers will be general facts that have no constituents. Keywords logical atomism, truth maker, metaphysical nihilism, fact, empty worlds Russell argued in his 1918 logical atomism lectures that there are no molecular facts, though he held that there are positive and negative atomic facts, and that there are universal and existential facts. However, he posed a problem for anyone wanting to avoid molecular facts: we need truth-makers for generalizations of molecular formulas|formulas such that a molecular connective occurs in the scope of a quantifier. But such truth-makers seem to be have an abominably molecular character because some of the formulas that they make true seem ineliminably molecular.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Combinatorialism
    Logical Combinatorialism Andrew Bacon* July 13, 2020 Abstract In explaining the notion of a fundamental property or relation, metaphysicians will often draw an analogy with languages. The fundamental properties and relations stand to reality as the primitive predicates and relations stand to a language: the smallest set of vocabulary God would need in order to write the `book of the world'. In this paper I attempt to make good on this metaphor. In order to do this I introduce a modality that, put informally, stands to propositions as logical truth stands to sentences. The resulting theory, formulated in higher-order logic, also vindicates the Humean idea that fundamental properties and relations are freely recombinable and a variant of the structural idea that propositions can be decomposed into their fundamental constituents via logical operations. Indeed, it is seen that, although these ideas are seemingly distinct, they are not independent, and fall out of a natural and general theory about the granularity of reality. Metaphysicians often theorize in terms of the notion of a property or relation being fundamental. When it comes to spelling out what this means, metaphors abound. According to one gloss, the fundamental properties and relations are the primitive constants in the language of reality, from which all other properties and relations can be defined; they are the vocabulary God would need in order to write the `book of the world' (Sider (2011)). The metaphor of reality as a language is one that is hard to make precise, and, taken too literally, has been shown to be subject to paradoxes.1 I take this as a warning to proceed cautiously, by codifying our metaphysics in a precise formal language where possible | in this case, higher-order logic | and employing model theoretic techniques to check for consistency.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defense of Radical Empiricism
    In Defense of Radical Empiricism A thesis presented to the faculty of the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts Ryan D. Ross May 2015 © 2015 Ryan D. Ross. All Rights Reserved. 2 This thesis titled In Defense of Radical Empiricism by RYAN D. ROSS has been approved for the Department of Philosophy and the College of Arts and Sciences by John W. Bender Professor of Philosophy Robert Frank Dean, College of Arts and Sciences 3 Abstract ROSS, RYAN D., M. A., May 2015, Philosophy In Defense of Radical Empiricism Director of Thesis: John W. Bender Laurence BonJour defends a moderate version of rationalism against rivaling empiricist epistemologies. His moderate rationalism maintains that some beliefs are justified a priori in a way that does not reduce to mere analyticity, but he tempers this strong claim by saying that such justification is both fallible and empirically defeasible. With the aim of ruling out radical empiricism (the form of empiricism that repudiates the a priori), BonJour puts forth what he calls the “master argument.” According to this argument, the resources available to radical empiricists are too slender to allow for justified empirical beliefs that go beyond what is immediately available to sense- perception, e.g., what we see, hear, and taste. If so, then radical empiricists are committed to a severe form of skepticism, one in which it is impossible to have justified beliefs about the distant past, the future, unobserved aspects of the present, etc. Worse, radical empiricists, who pride themselves on their scientific worldview, would be unable to account for justified beliefs about the abstract, theoretical claims of science itself! Clearly, the master argument is intended to hit the radical empiricist where it hurts.
    [Show full text]
  • Russellms Logical Atomism 1914P1918: Epistemological
    Russell’sLogical Atomism 1914–1918: Epistemological Ontology and Logical Form Nino B. Cocchiarella May 23, 2017 Abstract Logical analysis, according to Bertrand Russell, leads to and ends with logical atomism, an ontology of atomic facts that is epistemologi- cally founded on sense-data, which Russell claimed are mind-independent physical objects. We …rst explain how Russell’s 1914–1918 epistemolog- ical version of logical atomism is to be understood, and then, because constructing logical forms is a fundamental part of the process of logical analysis, we brie‡y look at what has happened to Russell’s type theory in this ontology. We then turn to the problem of explaining whether or not the logical forms of Russell’s new logic can explain both the forms of atomic facts and yet also the sentences of natural language, especially those about beliefs. The main problem is to explain the logical forms for belief and desire sentences and how those forms do not correspond to the logical forms of the facts of logical atomism. According to Bertrand Russell all “philosophy is logic,”by which he meant that “every philosophical problem, when it is subjected to the necessary analysis and puri…cation, is found either to be not really philosophical, or else to be, in the sense in which we are using the word, logical” (OKEW, 42). By necessary analysis Russell meant logical analysis, i.e., formally breaking up a complex whole into its separate parts or constituents, and then explaining the way the parts are held together in terms of a logical form (OKEW, 52).
    [Show full text]
  • Modal Propositional Logic
    6 Modal Propositional Logic 1. INTRODUCTION In this book we undertook — among other things — to show how metaphysical talk of possible worlds and propositions can be used to make sense of the science of deductive logic. In chapter 1, we used that talk to explicate such fundamental logical concepts as those of contingency, noncontingency, implication, consistency, inconsistency, and the like. Next, in chapter 2, while resisting the attempt to identify propositions with sets of possible worlds, we suggested that identity-conditions for the constituents of propositions (i.e., for concepts), can be explicated by making reference to possible worlds and showed, further, how appeal to possible worlds can help us both to disambiguate proposition-expressing sentences and to refute certain false theories. In chapter 3 we argued the importance of distinguishing between, on the one hand, the modal concepts of the contingent and the noncontingent (explicable in terms of possible worlds) and, on the other hand, the epistemic concepts of the empirical and the a priori (not explicable in terms of possible worlds). In chapter 4 we showed how the fundamental methods of logic — analysis and valid inference — are explicable in terms of possible worlds and argued for the centrality within logic as a whole of modal logic in general and S5 in particular. Then, in chapter 5, we tried to make good our claim that modal concepts are needed in order to make sound philosophical sense even of that kind of propositional logic — truth-functional logic — from which they seem conspicuously absent. Now in this, our last chapter, we concentrate our attention on the kind of propositional logic — modal propositional logic — within which modal concepts feature overtly.
    [Show full text]
  • Thinking the Impossible
    Thinking the Impossible Graham Priest City University of New York University of Melbourne Abstract The article looks at the structure of impossible worlds, and their deployment in the analysis of some intentional notions. In particular, it is argued that one can, in fact, conceive anything, whether or not it is impossible. Thus a semantics of con- ceivability requires impossible worlds. Keywords: Possible World, Impossible World, Conceivability, David Hume, FDE. «Possible? Is anything impossible? Read the newspapers». Arthur Wellesley (Duke of Wellington).1 1. Introduction: The History of Modality Possibility has been a familiar character in Western philosophy since the incep- tion of the discipline. Systematic ways of thinking about it are to be found in both of the first two great periods of logic: Ancient and Medieval. Witness Aris- totle’s modal syllogistic2 and and its medieval developments, such as the doc- trine of ampliation, and the notions of sensu composito and sensu diviso.3 The articulation of the notion has taken a very distinctive turn in the third great (and contemporary) period. Possible-world semantics has come to take centre stage. And the applicability of these has spread the tentacles of modality into areas where connections had not before been made, such as meaning, be- lief, conditionals, and intentionality.4 Of late, we have seen an extension of this logical technology into the area of impossible worlds, stretching the tentacles further, and—arguably—untangling some knots in the earlier tentacles.5 The present paper takes a close look at the structure of impossible worlds, and of one in particular of the tentacles: the mental state of concep- tion/imagination.
    [Show full text]
  • • .. Anintroduction to Logic and , Its Philosophy
    • .. an Introduction ~- to Logic and , Its Philosophy Raymond Bradley / Norman Swartz AN INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC AND ITS PHILOSOPHY ! I RAYMOND BRADLEY NORMAN SWARTZ Department of Philosophy Simon Fraser University HACKETT PUBLISHING COMPANY PublishedPublished inin thethe UnitedUnited StatesStates ofof AmericaAmerica byby HACKETTHACKETT PUBLISHINGPUBLISHING COMPANY,COMPANY, INCINC.. Copyright © 19791979 byby RaymondRaymond BradleyBradley andand NormanNorman SwartzSwartz AlAlll rightsrights reservedreserved PublishedPublished inin GreatGreat BritainBritain byby BasilBasil BlackwellBlackwell PublisherPublisher PrintedPrinted inin thethe UnitedUnited StatesStates ofof AmericaAmerica FourthFourth printinprintingg 19881988 LibraryLibrary ofof CongressCongress CatalogCatalog CardCard NumberNumber 79-5103779-51037 ISBNISBN 0-915144-60-30-915144-60-3 0-915144-59-x0-915144-59-x (pbk(pbk)) CoverCover designdesign byby RichardRichard L.L. ListenbergerListenberger ArArtt forfor covercover byby JamesJames Felter,Felter, CentreCentre forfor thethe Arts,Arts, SimonSimon FraserFraser UniversityUniversity InteriorInterior designdesign byby JamesJames N.N. RogersRogers ForFor furtherfurther information,information, pleaseplease addressaddress HackettHackett PublishingPublishing Company,Company, IncInc.. P.O.P.O. BoxBox 4493744937 Indianapolis,Indianapolis, IndianaIndiana 4620446204 TToo ththee membermemberss ooff ouourr familiesfamilies,, ooff whoswhosee compancompanyy wwee werewere totooo ofteoftenn deprivedeprivedd durinduringg ththee yearyearss spenspentt
    [Show full text]