Knowledge, Warrant & Foundationalism (W15)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Knowledge, Warrant & Foundationalism (W15) KNOWLEDGE, EPISTEMIC WARRANT & FOUNDATIONALISM I am going to deal with the foundations of First Philosophy in its entirety. — Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy To say that a belief is [epistemically] warranted or justified for a person is to evaluate it or him (or both) positively; his holding that belief in his circumstances is right, or proper, or acceptable, or approvable, or up to the standard. We evaluate a person’s beliefs (more exactly, her believings) as warranted, or justified, or rational, or reasonable, contrasting them with beliefs that are unwarranted, unjustified, irrational, unreasonable. — Alvin Plantinga, Warrant: The Current Debate [Epistemic warrant] is a normative concept. It is an evaluation of how well one has pursued one’s epistemic goals. — Stewart Cohen & Keith Lehrer, “Justification, Truth and Coherence” On (two of the) epistemologist’s concerns: the nature & THE BIG IDEAS TO MASTER possibility of propositional knowledge • Doxastic attitudes • Propositional knowledge Before we delve into Descartes’ philosophical project, it will • Traditional analysis of knowledge be helpful for us to understand some basic epistemology, • Epistemic warrant namely, its primary questions and the kinds of answers that • Evidentialism have been offered. • Basic vs. non-basic belief • Foundationalist theory of epistemic As we said, epistemology is the study of the structure and warrant nature of knowledge and well-grounded belief. But what • The Regress Argument exactly does that mean? Let us consider the following. Epistemologists are primarily interested in answering three questions: (1) what is knowledge?; (2) what, if anything, can we know?; (3) how do we acquire knowledge?1 On the ambiguity of the term ‘knowledge’ So, what is knowledge? To answer this, we must recall that the term ‘knowledge’ is ambiguous. The Greeks, you will recall, distinguish it into three types: epistemê, technê and phronesis. Rather than use this set of distinctions, let use the contemporary notions and distinguish it a little differently. The three are: propositional, procedural and acquaintance. Knowledge Propositional Non-propositional knowledge knowledge Procedural Acquaintance knowledge knowledge 1 Descartes hopes to answer these same questions in his Meditations on First Philosophy. What he calls “first philosophy” is, to a large degree, nothing less than a philosophical theory on (a) the nature (i.e., the essence) of knowledge, (b) the possibility of having it, and (c) the proper method for gaining that knowledge. What’s the difference between each type? Let us understand them accordingly: • Propositional knowledge: knowing that such-and-such proposition is true, e.g., Jones knows that Socrates is mortal. • Procedural knowledge: knowing how to do such-and-such, e.g., Smith knows how to ride a bike. • Acquaintance knowledge: knowing such-and-such object, e.g., Brown knows the car. Here you can see that what distinguishes each type of knowledge is the object that is said to be known. In the case of propositional knowledge, the object is the proposition’s truth-value (whether it’s true or false); in procedural knowledge, it is a procedure for performing a task; and in acquaintance knowledge it is familiarity we might say with a thing’s properties.2 Our concern is with propositional knowledge, knowledge that a proposition is true or false. So what is propositional knowledge? On the concept of propositional knowledge While epistemologists throughout history have had many different answers to that question, they have traditionally answered it with what is known as the traditional analysis of propositional knowledge (also referred to as justified-true-belief analysis). According to the traditional analysis, propositional knowledge is to be understood as follows: TAK: If a person S knows that a proposition p (is true), then it must also be that: (i) S believes p (i.e., that p is true), (ii) p is true, and (iii) S’s belief that p is epistemically warranted. So, for instance, if Jones knows that Socrates is mortal, then it must also be that Jones believes Socrates is mortal, Socrates is mortal, and Jones’ believing that Socrates is mortal is an epistemically warranted belief. Only so long as those things are true can Jones know that Socrates is mortal. In this way, we see that advocates of (TAK) claim that there are three necessary conditions in order to have propositional knowledge: • The believes condition (the person must believe that p is true), • The truth condition (p must be true), and • The warrant condition (the person must be epistemically warranted in believing that p is true).3 It is the last condition that will be our focus. Why? For two reasons. First, given the nature of Descartes’ skeptical worries, his concern is with (iii), the warrant condition. Second, since knowledge is a special kind of true belief, we have to ask what is the distinguishing feature between having a true 2 Notice that propositional knowledge and procedural knowledge are rather similar to the Greek conceptions of epistêmê and technê, respectively. 3 Two things. First, these three conditions are necessary in that if a person does not satisfy each of them, knowledge is not possible. They are, however, not by themselves sufficient. Whether they are jointly sufficient is the matter of a great deal of debate. Second, notice how this analysis differs from that of Plato’s analysis in that it drops the fourth condition: the understanding condition. belief that a proposition is true and knowing the proposition is true. It is generally regarding that epistemic warrant is (at least a substantive part of) what does that distinguishing. So, we will have to ask what is epistemic warrant? Before I give that, however, let us state what it is to believe something.4 On being a believer We all believe things. We don’t necessarily believe all of the same things. No, some of us, for instance, believe that the earth is an orb-shaped object; others believe that the earth is a flat disk. To be sure, these are contrary attitudes, but they are what people believe.5 But what is it to believe something? Philosophically speaking, to believe something is simply to assent to the truth of a proposition. It is think that the proposition correctly corresponds to the facts, that it correctly describes “the world.” So, for instance, to say that (A) Hawking believes that gravity is the curvature of spacetime, just means that (A*) Hawking thinks that gravity is the curvature of spacetime is a true proposition. Believing a proposition, however, is just one of three possible doxastic attitudes. The three (and only three) doxastic attitudes are: • S believes p if S thinks or accepts that p is true, • S disbelieves p if S denies or rejects that p is true, and • S suspends judgement about p if S neither believes p nor disbelieves p. Now, it should be clear that each of these attitudes seems to be tied up with making a judgement. If so, then to believe a proposition p is to make the judgement that p is true; to disbelieve p is to make the judgement that p is false; to suspend judgement is to withhold making a judgement about whether p is true or false. Two more things. First, having a given doxastic attitude does not mean you are correct. No, people believe and disbelieve mistakenly all time. These are called misjudgements. Second, that a person has a given doxastic attitude does not mean that attitude is epistemically warranted. Certainly they think it is warranted; arguably, no one adopts a given doxastic attitude without what they believe are good reasons for doing so. But whether their reasons are in fact good is another question altogether. So, let’s see if we can make sense of what’s required to have actually good reasons for adopting a particular doxastic attitude. On the concept of epistemic warrant As Cohen and Lehrer note in the above quote, epistemic warrant—what some philosophers call ‘epistemic justification’—is a normative or evaluative property. It is a property that makes one’s doxastic attitude rationally good, or right, or appropriate to have in their given circumstances. It specifies the ideal attitude state to have. But what is it? What is that property exactly? To answer this, let us begin by 4 We already defined what ‘…is true’ means on the course handout entitled “Plato, Philosophical Inquiry, and the Elenctic Method.” 5 You might be tempted to say that some people don’t believe the earth is an orb-shaped object, but that they know it is. But as we’ll discuss, it’s more accurate to say they don’t merely believe it, they also know it. distinguishing two types of doxastic attitudes: those that are properly held by a person versus those that are improperly held by a person. (Note: by ‘held’ I mean accepted or adopted.) Here’s the difference: PROPER-BELIEF: A person’s S’s doxastic attitude A is properly held by S when and only when there is no contrary attitude A* that S should adopt instead in exactly the same circumstances, and IMPROPER-BELIEF: A person’s S’s doxastic attitude A is improperly held by S when there is a contrary attitude A* that S should hold instead in exactly the same circumstances. So, here we can see that the difference has to do when something is what one should believe, when that’s the right thing to believe. But not right in the sense that it’s true; rather, right in the sense that that is what the ideally rational person believes in those circumstances. What then are the conditions for a doxastic attitude being properly held versus improperly held? Like many topics, different epistemologists have different answers.
Recommended publications
  • Should You Believe What You Hear?
    Should You Believe What You Hear? Dr. Allan Hazlett Much of what we think about the world we believe on the basis of what other people say. But is this trust in other people's testimony justified? This week, we’ll investigate how this question was addressed by two great philosophers of the Scottish Enlightenment, David Hume (1711 - 1776) and Thomas Reid (1710 - 1796). Hume and Reid's dispute about testimony represents a clash between two worldviews that would continue to clash for centuries: a skeptical and often secular worldview, eager to question everything (represented by Hume), and conservative and often religious worldview, keen to defend common sense (represented by Reid). Part One - Introduction: Hume on Testimony and Miracles Testimony and believing what others tell you. Enlightenment 1700-1800 Intellectual autonomy Hume – Essays on Miracles “there is no species of reasoning more common, more useful, and even necessary to human life, than that which is derived from the testimony of men” What is distinctive of "naturalistic" approaches to philosophy? (Select all that apply.) No appeal to, or reliance on, the notion of Nature. No appeal to, or reliance on, the notion of supernatural phenomena No appeal to, or reliance on, the notion of God No appeal to, or reliance on, the notion of human societies. Never believe a miracle based upon testimony Assumption of testimony: You have to have evidence that the person is speaking is likely to be right. Evidentialism – “A wise man…proportions his belief to the evidence.” Which of the following captures Hume's assumption about basing beliefs on testimony? To properly base a belief on testimony, you must have independent evidence that testimony is true.
    [Show full text]
  • A Dispositional, Internalist, Evidentialist Virtue Epistemology
    This is a repository copy of A Dispositional, Internalist, Evidentialist Virtue Epistemology. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/94260/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Byerly, T.R. (2014) A Dispositional, Internalist, Evidentialist Virtue Epistemology. Logos and Episteme : an International Journal of Epistemology, V (4). pp. 399-424. ISSN 2069-3052 Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher’s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ A Dispositional Internalist Evidentialist Virtue Epistemology This paper articulates and defends a novel version of internalist evidentialism which employs dispositions to account for the relation of evidential support. In section one, I explain internalist evidentialist views generally, highlighting the way in which the relation of evidential support stands at the heart of these views. I then discuss two leading ways in which evidential support has been understood by evidentialists, and argue that an account of support which employs what I call epistemic dispositions remedies difficulties arguably faced by these two leading accounts.
    [Show full text]
  • Responding to Skepticism About Doxastic Agency
    Erkenn (2018) 83:627–645 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-017-9906-2 ORIGINAL RESEARCH Responding to Skepticism About Doxastic Agency Miriam Schleifer McCormick1 Received: 16 April 2016 / Accepted: 9 May 2017 / Published online: 8 June 2017 Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017 Abstract My main aim is to argue that most conceptions of doxastic agency do not respond to the skeptic’s challenge. I begin by considering some reasons for thinking that we are not doxastic agents. I then turn to a discussion of those who try to make sense of doxastic agency by appeal to belief’s reasons-responsive nature. What they end up calling agency is not robust enough to satisfy the challenge posed by the skeptics. To satisfy the skeptic, one needs to make sense of the possibility of believing for nonevidential reasons. While this has been seen as an untenable view for both skeptics and anti-skeptics, I conclude by suggesting it is a position that has been too hastily dismissed. 1 Introduction In what sense or to what extent is agency exercised in the doxastic realm? Some argue that the kind of control we have over beliefs is sufficient for doxastic agency, while others argue that the nature of beliefs precludes agency being exercised in what we believe. But getting clear on the nature of these disagreements is difficult because the disputants do not always share a common notion of what is required for agency in general, and doxastic agency in particular. A skeptic about doxastic agency may agree with everything an anti-skeptic says but insist that none of what is proposed counts as real agency.
    [Show full text]
  • Bi-Level Evidentialism and Reformed Apologetics
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 11 Issue 3 Article 2 7-1-1994 Bi-Level Evidentialism and Reformed Apologetics Michael L. Czapkay Sudduth Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Sudduth, Michael L. Czapkay (1994) "Bi-Level Evidentialism and Reformed Apologetics," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 11 : Iss. 3 , Article 2. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol11/iss3/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. BI-LEVEL EVIDENTIALISM AND REFORMED APOLOGETICS Michael L. Czapkay Sudduth In this paper I apply William Alston's "epistemic level distinctions" to the debate between evidentialist and anti-evidentialist approaches to Christian apologetics in the Reformed tradition. I first clarify the nature of this debate by showing that it rests fundamentally on a tension between the desire to have a comprehensive Christian apologetic and the belief that the Holy Spirit plays a special epistemic role in belief-formation, such that certain beliefs are formed and justified by conditions unique to Christian religious experi­ ence. Secondly, I argue that even if S's belief that p is immediately justified (through such privileged modes of belief-formation), (I) an evidentialist requirement can be placed on the higher-level belief that P* (p is immediately justified) and (2) apologetics can draw on the reasons which confer justifi­ cation on P*, thereby providing indirect support for p.
    [Show full text]
  • Making It Evident: Evidence and Evidentness, Justification and Belief
    1 Making it Evident: Evidence and Evidentness, Justification and Belief “We give the name of evidence to whatever is the ground of belief.” (Reid IP II 20, W 328a1) “A proposition is epistemically justified to someone when it is evident to that person that the proposition is true.” (Conee 1992, 252) “…a central function of evidence is to make evident that which would not be so in its absence” (Kelly 2006, §3). 1. Introduction As usually stated, evidentialism constitutes the outline of a theory: supposing that justification of the sort required for knowing is solely a function of one’s evidence,2 a well-developed evidentialist theory will tell us what sorts of things constitute one’s evidence, what it is to have evidence, what it is for evidence to support a given belief or proposition, and so on. But whether or not evidentialism is true such questions merit attention. For whether or not evidentialism is true evidence remains a central epistemological concept. Answering questions concerning evidence, however, is made more difficult by the fact that it is often asked to play roles in addition to that (/those) featured by evidentialism. And while one would like (other things equal) to provide a unified account of a given concept or phenomenon, as Thomas Kelly (2006) has documented some of the roles that evidence has been thought to play stand in apparent tension to each other; the result is that it’s not clear whether a single theory can fit everything we want to say about evidence. The present paper offers partial and tentative answers to questions like those posed above, while attempting too to move towards a resolution of the apparent tensions Kelly describes.
    [Show full text]
  • A Social Solution to the Puzzle of Doxastic Responsibility: a Two-Dimensional Account of Responsibility for Belief
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers Forthcoming in Synthese 1 A Social Solution to the Puzzle of Doxastic Responsibility: A Two-Dimensional Account of Responsibility for Belief Robert Carry Osborne (This is a final, pre-copyedit version of an article published in Synthese. The final authenticated version is available online at: http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s11229-020-02637-9) 1. Introduction There are various, well-known difficulties surrounding the notion of doxastic responsibility and the so-called ‘ethics of belief’. The “puzzle of doxastic responsibility,” as Miriam McCormick (2015) has recently called it, arises from the tension between some version of the following three claims, each intuitively plausible on its own, but together jointly inconsistent: (RESPONSIBLE) We sometimes rightly hold agents responsible for their doxastic attitudes. (CONTROL) Voluntary control over X is a prerequisite for responsibility for X. (NON-VOLUNTARY) Beliefs are not subject to the will, that is, we lack voluntary control over them.1 The puzzle, then, is why beliefs seem to be the kinds of things for which we can rightly be held responsible, and yet do not appear to be something over which we exercise direct (voluntary or intentional) control.2 A solution to the puzzle seems to require that we reject at least one of the three claims above. As a result, the puzzle has three general answers: (a) Reject (RESPONSIBLE) and thus deny that beliefs are the proper objects of normative assessment, and so deny that anyone 1 McHugh (2017) also discusses a version of the same puzzle, which he calls “the problem of epistemic responsibility,” though his version involves four claims, and depends explicitly on a comparison with the kind of control we have over our (bodily) actions.
    [Show full text]
  • Evidentialism and the Great Pumpkin Objection
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 8/8/2011, SPi 7 Evidentialism and the Great Pumpkin Objection Michael Bergmann Evidentialism, as understood by its chief contemporary proponents (i.e. Richard Feldman and Earl Conee), is the view that epistemic justification supervenes on the evidence one has1—whether that evidence is other beliefs or experiences or feelings. Earl Conee argues that, unlike other views, evidentialism has a response to skepticism about the external world that escapes what can be called ‘the Great Pumpkin Objection’.2 That objection says, of a response to skepticism, that those endorsing a silly view—such as the view that the gift-delivering Great Pumpkin rises each Halloween over the most sincere pumpkin patch—can offer exactly parallel responses to those who are skeptical of their Great Pumpkin beliefs.3 The obvious suggestion is that if one’s response to skepticism about the external world can be mimicked by those defending such a silly view, then that response to skepticism is inadequate. There are two main ways to respond to the Great Pumpkin Objection when it is applied to your favored response to some sort of skepticism. You could say that the allegedly parallel response offered by those defending belief in a silly view does not successfully mimic your favored response to skepticism. Or you could admit that it does successfully mimic your favored response to skepticism and yet deny that this implies 1 Conee and Feldman (2004: 1). Note that this use of the term ‘evidentialism’ is different from the way it is sometimes used in philosophy of religion to refer to the view that belief in God can be made rational or justified only on the basis of propositional evidence.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Epistemology and the Project of Mapping Science
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 9-2015 Social Epistemology and the Project of Mapping Science Kamili Posey Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/1097 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! SOCIAL EPISTEMOLOGY AND THE PROJECT OF MAPPING SCIENCE BY KAMILI POSEY A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York. 2015 © 2015 KAMILI POSEY All Rights Reserved ii This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Nikolas Pappas ______________________________ ______________________________ ______________________________ Date Chair of Examining Committee Iakovos Vasiliou ______________________________ ______________________________ ______________________________ Date Executive Officer Samir Chopra ______________________________________________ Linda Alcoff ______________________________________________ Robert Sinclair ______________________________________________ Supervisory Committee THE
    [Show full text]
  • The Prospects of Evidentialism Trent Dougherty (Ed.): Evidentialism and Its Discontents
    Metascience DOI 10.1007/s11016-013-9764-8 BOOK REVIEW The prospects of evidentialism Trent Dougherty (ed.): Evidentialism and its discontents. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2011 xii+336pp, £45.00 HB Mark P. Newman Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013 This is a collection of sixteen essays, mostly written by well-established epistemologists, providing insightful criticism and constructive recommendations on Earl Conee and Richard Feldman’s epistemology. The essays are organized under the following topics: disagreement; virtue critique; skepticism; knowledge; internalism; evidence; and synthesis with other accounts. Each paper comes with a response from Conee and Feldman. Overall the collection provides a useful, although somewhat jumbled picture of issues facing evidentialism. Whether one is favorable to the position or not, these essays are important reading for any philosopher struggling with epistemic justification. The collection starts with a very useful historical-conceptual introduction to evidentialism from the editor Trent Dougherty. He draws on the most recent formulations from Conee and Feldman who articulate their position in several ways. The most commonly cited is from their book Evidentialism: EJ: Doxastic attitude D towards proposition p is epistemically justified for S at t if and only if having D toward p fits the evidence S has at the time. They also have a more recent supervenience formulation of evidentialism from their article ‘Evidence’ (2008): SE: Necessarily, if S1 is justified in believing p, and E is the evidence that S1 has, then necessarily (1) on balance E supports p, and (2) if E is the evidence that S2 has, then S2 is justified in believing p.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemology Reading List
    Epistemology Reading List I. Books Majors and Minors Read: 1. Lehrer, Theory of Knouledge z. Pollock, Contemporary Theories of Knouledge Majors Only Read: 3. Harman,Thought 4. Foley, Theory of Epistemic Rationality II. Articles Starced readings arefor majors and minors, unst{trred readings in this section 'arefor majors only. Overview *Pryor, J. zoor. "Highlights of Recent Epistemology," British Journalfor the Philosophy of Science, 52:95-124 Justification *Alston, William P. 1985. "Concepts of Epistemic Justification," Monist 68 "Goldman, Alvin. tg79."What is Justified Belief?" In Justification and Knowledge, ed. G.S. Pappas, 1-23. Dordrecht: D. Reidel. Steup, M. r988."The Deontic Conception of Epistemic Justification," Philosophical Studies S3: 65-84. Feldman & Conee. 198b. "Evidentialism," Philosophical Studies 48: t5-34. Foundationalisrn & Coherentism BonJour, L. t978. "Can Empirical Knowledge Have a Foundation?" American Philosophical Quarterly , 1b . 1: 1- 13 . " BonJour , L. tggg . "The Dialectic of Foundationalism and Coherentism, " in Blacktuell Guide to Epistemology, ed. Greco & Sosa, 117-742. * Klein, P. zoo4. "Infinitism is the Solution to the Regress Problem," in ContempororA Debates in Epistemology, ed. Sosa, E. and Steup, M. Blackwell. (Ian Euans hcs written a long expositional paper on Klein's uiews, so contact him if you'd like a copy.) Epistemic Circularity "Van Cleve, James. rg7g. "Foundationalism, Epistemic Principles, and the Cartesian Circle," Philosophical Reuietu 8B : 55-9r. Knowledge & Warrant "Gettier, E. 1963. "Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?" Analysis 2J: r2r-123. Goldman, A. t967. "Causal Theory of Knowledge," Journal of Philosophy 64: 357-372. "Lehrer & Paxson. 1969. "Knowledge: Undefeated, Justified, True Belief," Journal of Philosophy, 66: 225-257.
    [Show full text]
  • I Am Going to Deal with the Foundations of First Philosophy in Its Entirety
    FOUNDATIONALISM & THE STRUCTURE OF EPISTEMIC WARRANT I am going to deal with the foundations of First Philosophy in its entirety. —Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy The basics of foundationalism Foundationalism is the classic view regarding the nature of warranted belief acceptance, non-acceptance and the suspending of judgement. It has been advocated by such historically significant philosophers as Aristotle, Aquinas, Descartes, Locke, Hume, Reid, and Kant as well as such significant contemporaries as A.J. Ayer, C.I. Lewis and Roderick Chisholm. It has been the subject of serious philosophical attacks by such prominent philosophers as Donald Davidson, Keith Lehrer, Laurence Bonjour and Richard Rorty.1 What is foundationalism, however? Given that foundationalism is a theory about the nature of epistemic warrant, it should be clear that it is a normative theory—i.e., it tells us when we are warranted, reasonable, or permitted to assent, not assent or suspend judgment regarding a proposition. How does it differ from the internalist and externalist views of epistemic warrant we have been discussing? Most importantly, it tells us about the structure of epistemically warranted doxastic attitudes. That is, it tells us how our epistemically warranted doxastic attitudes are related to each other. Put differently, it tells us that every member of a cognitive being’s set of doxastic attitudes is organized and formally related in very important ways. What is that organization and formal relation? According to the foundationalist, genuine (propositional) knowledge and epistemically warranted belief has a two-tier structure: some instances of our knowledge and epistemically warranted belief are foundational and every other instance is non-foundational.
    [Show full text]
  • Transglobal Evidentialism-Reliabilism
    Acta anal. (2007) 22:281–300 DOI 10.1007/s12136-007-0015-8 Transglobal Evidentialism-Reliabilism David Henderson & Terry Horgan & Matjaž Potrč Received: 9 October 2007 /Accepted: 16 November 2007 /Published online: 8 January 2008 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V. 2007 Abstract We propose an approach to epistemic justification that incorporates elements of both reliabilism and evidentialism, while also transforming these elements in significant ways. After briefly describing and motivating the non- standard version of reliabilism that Henderson and Horgan call “transglobal” reliabilism, we harness some of Henderson and Horgan’s conceptual machinery to provide a non-reliabilist account of propositional justification (i.e., evidential support). We then invoke this account, together with the notion of a transglobally reliable belief-forming process, to give an account of doxastic justification. Keywords Evidentialism . Reliabilism . Justification . Transglobal reliability 1 Introduction Evidentialism and reliabilism, two prominent philosophical approaches to epistemic justification, typically are taken to be incompatible in a number of important ways. Evidentialism gives pride of place to the idea of contentful evidential-support relations among propositions (relations of “propositional justification”). In order for an agent’s belief that p to be justified (to possess “doxastic justification”), according to evidentialism, two constitutive requirements are (i) that the agent possesses evidence whose content provides propositional justification for p, and (ii) that the agent believes that p because of this evidence. Although doxastically justified beliefs typically are produced by reliable belief-forming processes, this etiological fact is not constitutive of doxastic justification. A belief qualifies as justified not because of D. Henderson University of Nebraska-Lincoln, Lincoln, NE, USA T.
    [Show full text]