In Defense of Modern Legal Positivism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

In Defense of Modern Legal Positivism Florida State University Law Review Volume 16 Issue 4 Article 15 Spring 1989 In Defense of Modern Legal Positivism Peter Mirfield Florida State University College of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.law.fsu.edu/lr Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Legal Education Commons Recommended Citation Peter Mirfield, In Defense of Modern Legal Positivism, 16 Fla. St. U. L. Rev. 985 (1989) . https://ir.law.fsu.edu/lr/vol16/iss4/15 This Essay is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Florida State University Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOK ESSAY IN DEFENSE OF MODERN LEGAL POSITIVISM PETER MIRFIELD* Professor Mirfield uses the example of a recent casebook to show that the process of excerpting passages from various writings about jurisprudence as a method of introducing the study of jurisprudence has very grave dangers attached to it. These dangers are demonstrated by "The World of Rules: The Jurisprudence of Positivism," a chapter of W. Michael Reisman and Aaron M. Schreiber's Jurisprudence: Understanding and Shaping Law. Professor Mirfield contends that Reisman and Schreiber's presentation of positivism is incomplete and is, in places, framed with inaccuratesummaries and characterizations. O NE MAY, perhaps, be unconvinced of the merits of studying dis- crete legal subjects via the medium of extracts from cases, arti- cles and the rest. Linking commentary from casebook editors seems more often to reveal their idiosyncracies than to lead the student reader to fruitful enquiry. But, this may be a cry from a legal tradi- tion rather different from that of the United States. These may be matters upon which reasonable people, lawyers even, may properly differ. I would be somewhat more resolute in denying the value of the "bleeding chunk" approach to "jurisprudence," whatever vastly varying material may lie between the covers of volumes bearing that title. Acquaintanceship with the recently published work, Jurispru- dence: Understanding and Shaping Law: Cases, Readings, Commen- tary,' written and edited by Professors W. Michael Reisman2 and * Tutor and Fellow in Law, Jesus College, Oxford; former Visiting Professor of Law, Florida State University, 1987-1988. B.A., 1971; B.C.L., 1972; M.A., 1976, Oxford University. 1. W. REISMAN & A. SCHREIBER, JURISPRUDENCE: UNDERSTANDING AND SHAPING LAW: CASES, READINGS, COMMENTARY (1987). 2. Wesley Newcomb Hofeld Professor of Jurisprudence, Yale Law School. L.L.B., 1963, Hebrew University; L.L.M., 1964; J.S.D., 1965, Yale University. 986 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 16:985 Aaron M. Schreiber,3 has done nothing to persuade me away from my prejudice. The reasons will appear in due course. I ought, in fairness, to reveal another feature of my philosophy of the study of law before going any further. I can think of almost noth- ing with which I more profoundly disagree than the following senti- ment expressed by the editors near the beginning of their book and repeated, in different terms, at times later therein: Legal theory or jurisprudence is of importance only if it contributes to problem-solving for our profession and society. If it does not, there is no reason why it should be incorporated in the law school curriculum and distract the attention of those preparing to serve their 4 communities and fellow citizens from matters of real importance. I confess distaste for the notion that lawyers "serve" their communi- ties and fellow citizens; the word smacks too much of ordination and calling for me. I think it safer to regard the generally rather mundane life led by the average legal practitioner as being closer to the job of a plumber than the office of a priest. However, the substance of what the editors are saying is far more significant than the way in which it is expressed. It seems to me that what separates law from other intellectual disci- plines is far less important than what it shares with them. A good lawyer is not to be confused with a good legal practitioner, though the former will, I hope and believe, tend to become the latter should he or she choose to enter practice. I am almost tempted to say that the value of legal theory lies precisely in the fact that it has no practical utility. Certainly its value does not lie in its capacity to prepare students for the practice of law, even practice at the problem-solving level. Rather, its value lies in that which it shares with, for example, theories of his- tory or literary criticism, namely its capacity to advance one's under- standing of the intellectual discipline which is its subject. Having regard to Reisman and Schreiber's attitudq to legal theory, it is not surprising that the branch of legal theory known as "positiv- ism" comes in for rough treatment. Of Hans Kelsen's 5 Pure Theory of Law,6 they say that it "almost seems to have been designed for the bureaucratic universe .. [I]t would appear to be amoral and an- 3. Professor of Law, Pace University Law School. B.B.A., 1950, City University of New York; J.D., 1955, Brooklyn Law School; L.L.M., 1967; J.S.D., 1978, Yale University. 4. W. R IdAN & A. ScImEIBER, supra note 1,at 11. 5. (1881-1973). An Austrian, Kelsen drafted the 1920 Austrian Constitution and served on the Austrian Supreme Constitutional Court before emigrating. 6. H. KELSEN, PuRE THEORY OF LAw (1967). 19891 MODERN LEGAL POSITIVISM ethical, primarily concerned with understanding and providing guide- lines for behavior in complex organizations." '7 Certainly, the theory is "amoral and an-ethical," for these are aspects of its purity. But, it is hard to see how Kelsen's theory can be said to have been concerned with understanding behavior, and for precisely the same reason. Were Kelsen concerned with this, he would be engaged in sociological juris- prudence, and would thus be compromising the purity of the exercise.' And, it is surely clear beyond a peradventure that Kelsen's theory was not concerned with providing guidelines for human behavior. His sci- ence of law was intended to be entirely descriptive, albeit that the ob- ject of its description was a system of legal norms which are themselves prescriptive in nature and form. As he said in Pure Theory of Law, "the science of law can only describe the law, it cannot prescribe a certain behavior like the law created by the legal authority (in the form of general or individual norms)." 9 It is true, as the editors, Reisman and Schreiber, point out, that some judges have purported to use the "Pure Theory" as providing them with justification for recognizing a revolution as having been le- gally successful.'0 However, this use has been subjected to cogent and convincing criticism precisely because it treats as prescriptive a theory which is itself entirely descriptive. 1 It is right to add that James Harris 2 has suggested that things may not be as straightforward as this, and that the theory properly has "indirect social suggestive force for judges."' 3 But, that is very far from a claim that this is the pri- mary concern of the theory, and Reisman and Schreiber do not, in any event, rely either explicitly or implicitly upon Harris's argument. In other words, it is one thing to argue that an unwelcome (for Kel- sen) but logically necessary feature of the theory is that it does speak to judges and other bureaucrats, quite another to argue that this was his theory's major point or purpose. This misleading assessment of Kelsen is no more than a sideswipe, for it is at the Anglo-Saxon version of positivism that the attack is 7. W. REISMAN & A. SCHREIBER, supra note 1, at 381. 8. See generally H. KELSEN, GE ERAL THEORY OF LAw AND STATE 162-64 (1961); H. KEL- SEN, PuRE THEORY OF LAW 1 (1967). 9. H. KELSEN, PuRE THEORY OF LAW 73 (1967) (emphasis in original). 10. The leading example is Madzimbamuto v. Lardner-Burke [19681 2 S. Afr. 284. See also State v. Dosso [1958] 2 Pak. Sup. Ct. Rep. 180; Uganda v. Comm'r of Prisons [1966] E. Afr. 514, 535-39. 11. See Hopton, Grundnorm and Constitution, 24 McGILL L.J. 72, 83-86 (1978). See also Brookfield, The Courts, Kelsen, and the Rhodesian Revolution, 19 U. TOR. L.J. 326, 342-44, 351-52 (1969). 12. Tutorial Fellow, Keble College, Oxford. B.C.L., 1966; M.A., 1966, Oxford University; Ph.D., 1973, London University. 13. Harris, When and Why Does the Grundnorm Change?, 29 CAMB. L.J. 103, 125 (1971). 988 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LA W REVIEW [Vol. 16:985 substantially directed. Chapter Seven, "The World of Rules: The Ju- risprudence of Positivism,"' 4 deals with what is now often called Hartian positivism. That said, I am not sure that Professor H.L.A. Hart'5 would recognize much of what is contained in the commentary in that chapter as based upon an accurate picture of his published views. If this caricature image of modern positivism represents the view of that doctrine held by the academic lawyer in the United States, it is small wonder that it seems to have little support here, at least in the law schools. Let me describe what I understand to be Hart's own doctrine of legal positivism before I go on to explain what is wrong with Reisman and Schreiber's treatment of that doctrine. 16 First, Hart stresses that law has social sources.
Recommended publications
  • Legal Positivism: an Analysis of Austin and Bentham
    INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW AND LEGAL JURISPRUDENCE STUDIES, VOLUME 1, ISSUE 6 LEGAL POSITIVISM: AN ANALYSIS OF AUSTIN AND BENTHAM Authors PRAGALBH BHARDWAJ National Law University, Odisha BH-1, National Law University, Odisha, Sector 13, CDA, Cuttack, Odisha. Country-India [email protected] RISHI RAJ National Law University, Odisha BH-1, National Law University, Odisha, Sector 13, CDA, Cuttack, Odisha. Country-India [email protected] 1 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW AND LEGAL JURISPRUDENCE STUDIES, VOLUME 1, ISSUE 6 Abstract Key words- Austin, Bentham, Criticism of Positivist School, Indian Perspective of Positivist School, Legal Positivist School. The school of Legal Positivism developed over the period of 18th and 19th century through the works of influential jurists such as John Austin and Jeremey Bentham. The works of these two great jurists was mainly responsible for the Legal Positivist School to acquire such importance in the field of legal jurisprudence. Their work was taken forward by jurists such as H.L.A.Hart. Although not free from shortcomings, the Legal Positivist School is regarded as the most influential school of thought in jurisprudence. Judges have based their decisions on this school of thought across various countries, including India. Indian Judges have been greatly influenced by the thinking of legal positivists and have applied their jurisprudence while giving landmark judgements such as A.K.Gopalan v. State of Madras to name one of them. The basic idea behind legal positivists was that they considered law as it is and not what it ought to be. They separated moral principles from legal principles.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Theory Workshop UCLA School of Law Samuele Chilovi
    Legal Theory Workshop UCLA School of Law Samuele Chilovi Postdoctoral Fellow Pompeu Fabra University “GROUNDING, EXPLANATION, AND LEGAL POSITIVISM” Thursday, October 15, 2020, 12:15-1:15 pm Via Zoom Draft, October 6, 2020. For UCLA Workshop. Please Don’t Cite Or Quote Without Permission. Grounding, Explanation, and Legal Positivism Samuele Chilovi & George Pavlakos 1. Introduction On recent prominent accounts, legal positivism and physicalism about the mind are viewed as making parallel claims about the metaphysical determinants or grounds of legal and mental facts respectively.1 On a first approximation, while physicalists claim that facts about consciousness, and mental phenomena more generally, are fully grounded in physical facts, positivists similarly maintain that facts about the content of the law (in a legal system, at a time) are fully grounded in descriptive social facts.2 Explanatory gap arguments have long played a central role in evaluating physicalist theories in the philosophy of mind, and as such have been widely discussed in the literature.3 Arguments of this kind typically move from a claim that an epistemic gap between physical and phenomenal facts implies a corresponding metaphysical gap, together with the claim that there is an epistemic gap between facts of these kinds, to the negation of physicalism. Such is the structure of, for instance, Chalmers’ (1996) conceivability argument, Levine’s (1983) intelligibility argument, and Jackson’s (1986) knowledge argument. Though less prominently than in the philosophy of mind, explanatory gap arguments have also played some role in legal philosophy. In this area, the most incisive and compelling use of an argument of this kind is constituted by Greenberg’s (2004, 2006a, 2006b) powerful attack on positivism.
    [Show full text]
  • Positivism and the Inseparability of Law and Morals
    \\server05\productn\N\NYU\83-4\NYU403.txt unknown Seq: 1 25-SEP-08 12:20 POSITIVISM AND THE INSEPARABILITY OF LAW AND MORALS LESLIE GREEN* H.L.A. Hart made a famous claim that legal positivism somehow involves a “sepa- ration of law and morals.” This Article seeks to clarify and assess this claim, con- tending that Hart’s separability thesis should not be confused with the social thesis, the sources thesis, or a methodological thesis about jurisprudence. In contrast, Hart’s separability thesis denies the existence of any necessary conceptual connec- tions between law and morality. That thesis, however, is false: There are many necessary connections between law and morality, some of them conceptually signif- icant. Among them is an important negative connection: Law is, of its nature, morally fallible and morally risky. Lon Fuller emphasized what he called the “internal morality of law,” the “morality that makes law possible.” This Article argues that Hart’s most important message is that there is also an immorality that law makes possible. Law’s nature is seen not only in its internal virtues, in legality, but also in its internal vices, in legalism. INTRODUCTION H.L.A. Hart’s Holmes Lecture gave new expression to the old idea that legal systems comprise positive law only, a thesis usually labeled “legal positivism.” Hart did this in two ways. First, he disen- tangled the idea from the independent and distracting projects of the imperative theory of law, the analytic study of legal language, and non-cognitivist moral philosophies. Hart’s second move was to offer a fresh characterization of the thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Towards Classical Legal Positivism Dan Priel Osgoode Hall Law School of York University, [email protected]
    Osgoode Hall Law School of York University Osgoode Digital Commons Research Papers, Working Papers, Conference Comparative Research in Law & Political Economy Papers Research Report No. 20/2011 Towards Classical Legal Positivism Dan Priel Osgoode Hall Law School of York University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/clpe Recommended Citation Priel, Dan, "Towards Classical Legal Positivism" (2011). Comparative Research in Law & Political Economy. Research Paper No. 20/2011. http://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/clpe/58 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Research Papers, Working Papers, Conference Papers at Osgoode Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Comparative Research in Law & Political Economy by an authorized administrator of Osgoode Digital Commons. ! ! ! !"#!!$%!&'(()('*)"+&!!(! !"#$%&%'()*+,*-*%&./+(0+1%2+3+4"5('(.%5+6."0"#7+ ) ,%"%',+&)-'-%,)"%,.%") "#$#%&'(!)%*#&!+,-!.00.122! Towards Classical Legal Positivism! Dan Priel ) ) IC65,&$:) -556)789:30450);!4<==15)&3>>)(3?)"@A==>B)C=6=0D=B)$/65@D=6)+=9E363D/F5)) ,54536@A)/0)(3?)301)-=>/D/@3>)%@=0=92G) H=A0)*I)+/=JJ/);K0/F564/D2)=J)+3>/J=60/3)3D),/F564/15G) (553005)L==D930);!4<==15)&3>>)(3?)"@A==>B)C=6=0D=B)-6=18@D/=0)%1/D=6G) ! ! ! ! ! ! Towards Classical Legal Positivism Dan Priel* Abstract. Open almost any textbook or jurisprudence and you will nd it beginning with a discussion of natural law and legal positivism. What sets them apart, we are told, is a di"erence on the conceptual question of the relationship between law and morality. Natural lawyers believe that law or legality are necessarily connected to morality, whereas legal positivists deny that.
    [Show full text]
  • Demanding Philosophy from Legal Positivism: an Investigation Into the Argumentative Support for the Separation Thesis
    Demanding Philosophy from Legal Positivism: An Investigation into the Argumentative Support for the Separation Thesis by Samuel Steadman A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral affairs in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of M.A. Legal Studies Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario ©2011 Samuel Steadman Library and Archives Bibliotheque et 1*1 Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du Branch Patrimoine de I'edition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington OttawaONK1A0N4 OttawaONK1A0N4 Canada Canada Your We Votre inference ISBN: 978-0-494-81624-0 Our file Notre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-81624-0 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non­ L'auteur a accorde une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library and permettant a la Bibliotheque et Archives Archives Canada to reproduce, Canada de reproduire, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve, sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par telecommunication ou par I'lnternet, preter, telecommunication or on the Internet, distribuer et vendre des theses partout dans le loan, distribute and sell theses monde, a des fins commerciales ou autres, sur worldwide, for commercial or non­ support microforme, papier, electronique et/ou commercial purposes, in microform, autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriete du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in this et des droits moraux qui protege cette these. Ni thesis. Neither the thesis nor la these ni des extraits substantiels de celle-ci substantial extracts from it may be ne doivent etre im primes ou autrement printed or otherwise reproduced reproduits sans son autorisation.
    [Show full text]
  • Law As a Means
    LEGAL RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Paper No 8/2009 March 2009 Law as a Means LESLIE GREEN A revised version of this paper will appear in Peter Cane, ed. Hart-Fuller at 50 (Oxford: Hart Publishing) An abstract of this paper can be downloaded without charge from the Social Science Research Network electronic library at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1351304 An index to the working papers in the University of Oxford Legal Research Paper Series is located at: <http://www.ssrn.com/link/oxford-legal-studies.html> LAW AS A MEANS Leslie Green∗ I. The instrumentalist thesis No one doubts that individual laws often serve as means to promote or secure certain ends. The rule against perpetuities is a means of setting temporal limitations on the grant of an estate. Bundles of laws working through statutes or fields of doctrine are also means to ends, including ends that are, under other descriptions, means to further ends. Enacting the Fewer School Boards Act1, for example, was intended as a means to the end of reducing the number of school boards, which was in turn intended as a means of uncoupling education from property tax, which was intended as a means of asserting financial discipline (and other sorts of discipline) over local schools, which the government of the day considered a desirable end. Examples like that make the instrumentality of laws sound like a top‐down affair. Just as often it is bottom‐up. It is not only legislatures and courts but also individuals who use laws as means to their ends. Leona Helmsley wanted her dog to be adequately provided for after her own death.
    [Show full text]
  • Law and Morality: a Kantian Perspective
    Columbia Law School Scholarship Archive Faculty Scholarship Faculty Publications 1987 Law and Morality: A Kantian Perspective George P. Fletcher Columbia Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Law and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation George P. Fletcher, Law and Morality: A Kantian Perspective, 87 COLUM. L. REV. 533 (1987). Available at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship/1071 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Scholarship Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LAW AND MORALITY: A KANTIAN PERSPECTIVE George P. Fletcher* The relationship between law and morality has emerged as the cen- tral question in the jurisprudential reflection of our time. Those who call themselves positivists hold with H.L.A. Hart' that calling a statute or a judicial decision "law" need not carry any implications about the morality of that statute or decision.2 Valid laws might be immoral or unjust. Those who resist this reduction of law to valid enactments sometimes argue, with Lon Fuller, that moral acceptability is a neces- sary condition for holding that a statute is law; 3 or, with Ronald Dworkin, that moral principles supplement valid enactments as compo- 4 nents of the law. Whether the positivists or their "moralist" opponents are right about the nature of law, all seem to agree about the nature of morality. We have to distinguish, it is commonly said, between conventional and critical morality.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Foundations of East Asian Jurisprudence ― Confucianism, Legalism and Taoism ― 1)
    141 〈논 문〉 Ancient Foundations of East Asian Jurisprudence ― Confucianism, Legalism and Taoism ― 1) Chongko Choi* Foreword In the age of “Globalization,” the most important factor in the world politics seems to be the civilizations, not the ideologies, as Samuel Huntington eloquently asserts. With the magnificent emergence of the Chinese civilization on the world stage, many people, including intellectuals, pay attention with great interest to East Asian civilization.1) If you read books on Chinese philosophy, you may find that almost all the books overwhelmingly discuss ancient philosophies like Confucianism, Taoism, Legalism and “Hundred Schools”. This fact shows the richness of ancient philosophy and how it played continuously an important role in Chinese history. It applies not only to China, but also to Korea and Japan, perhaps to the whole of East Asia. I am currently trying to build up the concept of East Asian jurisprudence.2) * Professor of Law, Seoul National University 1) As the recent publications, Gina Barnes, China, Japan, Korea: The Rise of Civilization in East Asia, London, 1993: Warren Cohen, East Asia at the Center: Four Thousand Years of Engagement with the World, Columbia Univ. Press, 2000: Charles Holcombe, The Genesis of East Asia: 221BC-AD 907, Uni. of Hawaii Press, 2001. 2) Chongko Choi, Foundations of East Asian Jurisprudence, Seoul Law Journal, Vol. 41. No. 1, 2000, pp.60-76; Chongko Choi, The Development of East Asian Law till the End of 18th Century, Law in History, Vol. 1, 2000, pp.21-55; Chongko Choi, Foundations of Law and Justice in East Asia, Comparative Law, Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Law, Positivism, and the Limits of Jurisprudence: a Modern Round
    Book Review Natural Law, Positivism, and the Limits of Jurisprudence: A Modern Round The Authority of Law: Essays in Law and Morality. By Joseph Raz. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979. Pp. ix, 292. Natural Law and Natural Rights. By John Finnis. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980. Pp. vii, 425. Ruth Gavisont In his recent collection of essays,' Joseph Raz presents and defends a version of positivism; in his first book-length contribution to legal philoso- phy,' John Finnis explores a natural law perspective. These two books, both published by Oxford, may thus serve as a reminder of the persistence of the debate between legal positivists and those adhering to the natural law tradition. As this review will show, the books demonstrate that these apparently contradictory schools of thought both can and must be inte- grated to enhance our understanding of the complex phenomenon of law. Rather than rival theories of law, positivism and natural law are, and should be taken to be, complementary and equally necessary approaches to a social institution of the utmost importance. The call to integrate these theories of law is anything but revolutionary. Sensitive legal scholars, even those who clearly identify themselves as ad- hering to one school or the other, have always granted that the two per- spectives are complementary rather than contradictory, and that the ap- peal of neither is transitory? Raz and Finnis, while presenting approaches t Senior Lecturer, Faculty of Law, Hebrew University, Jerusalem. An earlier version of this review was presented and discussed in December 1980 at a seminar of that Faculty of Law.
    [Show full text]
  • Shuman: Legal Positivism: Its Scope and Limitations
    Michigan Law Review Volume 62 Issue 1 1963 Shuman: Legal Positivism: Its Scope and Limitations Edgar Bodenheimer University of Utah Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, Law and Philosophy Commons, Law and Society Commons, and the Natural Law Commons Recommended Citation Edgar Bodenheimer, Shuman: Legal Positivism: Its Scope and Limitations, 62 MICH. L. REV. 154 (1963). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol62/iss1/12 This Book Reviews is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RECENT BOOKS LEGAL POSITIVISM: ITS SCOPE AND LIMITATIONS. By Samuel I. Shuman. Detroit: Wayne State University Press. 1963. Pp. vi, 265. $8.50. One of the criteria that might be applied in the evaluation of a book dealing with theoretical or philosophical matters in the social science field is whether the book raises and discusses questions that are meaningful and important in their relation to, and impact upon, human social life. Judged by this criterion, Professor Shuman's book will easily pass muster before a board of critics. Anyone interested in the law as a means of social control will concede that the problems taken up by Professor Shuman, notwithstanding their theoretical and philosophical character, have a decisive bearing upon the solution of issues that every organized society has to cope with.
    [Show full text]
  • Professor Dworkin's Views on Legal Positivism
    Indiana Law Journal Volume 55 Issue 2 Article 1 Winter 1979 Professor Dworkin's Views on Legal Positivism Genaro R. Carrio Follow this and additional works at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Legal History Commons Recommended Citation Carrio, Genaro R. (1979) "Professor Dworkin's Views on Legal Positivism," Indiana Law Journal: Vol. 55 : Iss. 2 , Article 1. Available at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj/vol55/iss2/1 This Lecture is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School Journals at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Indiana Law Journal by an authorized editor of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Vol. 55, No. 2 INDIANA1979-1980 LAW JOURNAL Professor Dworkin's Views on Legal Positivismt GENARO R. CARRI6 * The expression "legal positivism" is intolerably ambiguous. It has been used in the past and is still used to designate a heterogeneous variety of attitudes, theses, conceptions and doctrines, all of which concern in different ways the social phenomenon known as "law." Some of them are incompatible with each other. Others are inter- connected by family ties. That is why in most cases it will not do to try to identify the general trend of ideas of a given jurist by saying that he is a positivist. Furthermore, when someone directs his at- tacks, indiscriminately, against "legal positivism," it may be quite confusing if he fails to state in what sense he is using that expres- sion.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg Considered
    Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law Volume 9 Issue 1 Article 9 1977 Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg Considered Neal Koch Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/jil Part of the International Law Commons Recommended Citation Neal Koch, Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg Considered, 9 Case W. Res. J. Int'l L. 161 (1977) Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/jil/vol9/iss1/9 This Comment is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Journals at Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law by an authorized administrator of Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. 1977] COMMENT Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg Considered* N THE ARTICLE, Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg,' Stanley L. Paulson effectively demonstrates that the rejection of the criminal defenses offered at the Nuremberg Trials follows from the rejection of underlying classical legal positivist doctrines. Specifically, his aim is to show that noncontingent links exist be- tween the doctrines of classical legal positivism and the defenses of the act of state doctrine and superior orders. Paulson argues that the defenses of act of state and superior orders both presuppose the doctrine of absolute sovereignty. The presupposition underlying the act of state defense is explained in terms of Austin's analysis of positive legal rights as triadic rela- tions. The presupposition underlying the defense of superior or- ders is explained by analyzing the requirement of unconditional obedience. The Austinian theory of classical legal positivism depends upon the command doctrine and the doctrine of absolute sovereignty.
    [Show full text]