On the Computational Hardness of Manipulating Pairwise Voting Rules

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

On the Computational Hardness of Manipulating Pairwise Voting Rules On the Computational Hardness of Manipulating Pairwise Voting Rules Rohit Vaish Neeldhara Misra Indian Institute of Science IIT Gandhinagar India India [email protected] [email protected] Shivani Agarwal Avrim Blum Indian Institute of Science Carnegie Mellon University India USA [email protected] [email protected] ABSTRACT impossibility suggested by this theorem, there has been sub- Standard voting rules usually assume that the preferences stantial work concerning a finer analysis of the situation and of voters are provided in the form of complete rankings over finding possible workarounds. A prominent example of this a fixed set of alternatives. This assumption does not hold in is the seminal work of Bartholdi, Tovey and Trick [4] who applications like recommendation systems where the set of proposed the possibility of using computational hardness as alternatives is extremely large and only partial preferences a barrier against manipulation of voting rules. They argue can be elicited. In this paper, we study the problem of that although opportunities for manipulation always exist in strategic manipulation of voting rules that aggregate voter principle, there might not exist any efficient general purpose preferences provided in the form of pairwise comparisons be- algorithm for finding them in practice. tween alternatives. Our contributions are twofold: first, we Since then, a considerable body of work has developed show that any onto pairwise voting rule is manipulable in around the computational study of manipulation (see [5] for principle. Next, we analyze how the computational complex- a survey on this topic). Much of this work models voter ity of manipulation of such rules varies with the structure of preferences as complete rankings over a fixed set of alterna- the graph induced by the pairs of alternatives that the ma- tives (or candidates). While this is a reasonable choice for nipulator is allowed to vote over and the type of the prefer- certain situations, many large-scale settings prevalent today ence relation. Building on natural connections between the (like recommendation systems) involve extremely large can- pairwise manipulation and sports elimination problems (in- didate sets (such as movies, products, webpages etc.). It is cluding a mixed-elimination variant that we introduce in this therefore unreasonable, and often impractical, to elicit pref- paper), we show that manipulating pairwise voting rules can erences from users in the form of complete rankings of these be computationally hard even in the single-manipulator set- alternatives. For these settings, it is decidedly more natural ting, a setting where most standard voting rules are known to aggregate partial user preferences to arrive at an out- to be easy to manipulate. come (e.g. top-k preferences [6,7], partial orders [8] etc.). Similarly, some situations call for relaxing the requirement of transitivity among the preferences. Indeed, when alter- General Terms natives are compared using not one but multiple quality Algorithms, Economics, Theory parameters, it is natural to permit possibly cyclic prefer- ences [9]. In this work, we consider the model of pairwise prefer- Keywords ences, where every vote is simply a collection of pairwise Social Choice Theory; Voting; Manipulation; Pairwise Pref- comparisons between alternatives with no constraints other erences than anti-symmetry (i.e. AB ) B6A). The preferences provided by voters in this setting can be incomplete (i.e. not all pairs of candidates are compared by a voter) and 1. INTRODUCTION can contain cycles (AB; BC; CA). Thus, all the situa- A central result in social choice theory [1] is the Gibbard- tions described above are subsumed by this model. This is a Satterthwaite theorem [2,3] which states that any non- simple model that offers substantial generality, and as a re- dictatorial voting rule over at least three candidates under sult there has been growing interest in designing preference which each candidate has some chance of winning is sus- aggregation algorithms that elicit pairwise preferences from ceptible to strategic voting i.e. is manipulable. Given the the users [10, 11, 12, 13, 14]. Although these studies explore the statistical properties of aggregation algorithms for pair- Appears in: Proceedings of the 15th International Conference wise preferences, the question of whether these algorithms on Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems (AAMAS 2016), (or pairwise voting rules) are resistant to strategic user be- J. Thangarajah, K. Tuyls, C. Jonker, S. Marsella (eds.), havior remains to be answered. The focus of the present May 9{13, 2016, Singapore. work is to address these questions from both axiomatic and Copyright c 2016, International Foundation for Autonomous Agents and computational perspectives. Multiagent Systems (www.ifaamas.org). All rights reserved. pref-type pref-type strict + acyclic strict unrestricted strict + acyclic strict unrestricted acyclic acyclic tree/ tree/ max deg=2 P max deg=2 A complete P A complete bipartite P NP-complete bipartite general general Table 2: The complexity of Copeland0-Manipulation and Table 1: The complexity of pBorda-Manipulation under Copeland1-Manipulation. the conditions specified by the corresponding action space A and type of preference relation pref-type (refer Defini- pref-type tion 2.1 in Section2). strict + acyclic strict unrstd. acyclic tree/ Contributions max deg=2 P Our contributions can be summarized as follows: A complete bipartite P NP- P 1. We show that any pairwise voting rule that is onto general complete (i.e. under which each candidate has some chance of winning) must be manipulable (Theorem 3.1). Table 3: The complexity of Copeland0:5-Manipulation. 2. Given the above impossibility, we study settings un- pref-type der which computational difficulty acts as a worst-case strict + acyclic strict unrestricted barrier against manipulation (Sections 3.2 and 3.3) acyclic Specifically, we study the problem of manipulation of tree/ pairwise voting rules along the following two dimen- max deg=2 P sions: (i) the structure of the graph induced by the set A complete of candidate pairs that the manipulator is allowed to bipartite P NP-complete vote over (e.g. tree, bipartite, complete) and (ii) the general type of preference relation (e.g. strict, acyclic). Our analysis is focused on the pairwise Borda (pBorda) rule Table 4: The complexity of Copelandα-Manipulation α and the Copeland family of voting rules. Tables1 to4 for α 2 Q \ (0; 1) n f0:5g. summarize our results for these rules. The essence of our results is that the structure of the induced graph and the type of revealed preferences (and the parame- 2. PRELIMINARIES ter α in case of Copelandα) can shape the complexity Let [n] = f1; 2; : : : ; ng denote the set of candidates and landscape in important ways. We remark that while U = fu ; u ; : : : ; u g denote the set of voters in an election. the manipulation problem in the context of rankings 1 2 m is polynomially solvable for most voting rules [4], we already encounter hardness results in the setting of Pairwise preferences and pairwise voting rules. pairwise comparisons with one manipulator for the rel- Let u ⊆ [n] × [n] denote the binary relation indicat- α atively simple pBorda and Copeland rules, which we ing the preferences of voter u, so that i u j indicates that consider an important contrast1. voter u prefers candidate i over candidate j. For each pair of candidates i; j and each voter u, we can have exactly one of i u j, j u i or neither (i.e. voter u skips the compari- Organization of this paper. son between i and j). We let R denote the set of all such anti-symmetric and irreflexive binary relations on [n]; and After setting the requisite notation and definitions in let Π = ( ; ; ··· ; ) 2 Rm denote the pairwise Section2, we describe the main ideas and proof tech- u1 u2 um preference profile of the voters. niques involved in the axiomatic (Section 3.1) and classical A pairwise voting rule r maps a pairwise preference complexity-theoretic results for pairwise Borda (Section 3.2) profile Π 2 [1 Rk to a unique candidate r(Π) 2 [n]. and Copelandα (Section 3.3) rules. A survey of the related k=1 Given a preference profile Π 2 Rm and a pair of can- literature is provided in Section4. We conclude by identi- didates i; j, let m (Π) denote the number of vot- fying further implications of our results and directions for ij ers who strictly prefer candidate i over candidate j, future research in Section5. Due to space constraints, we i.e. m (Π) = Pm 1(i j) where 1(:) is the indicator defer the detailed proofs of all the results presented here to ij k=1 uk function. A score-based pairwise voting rule is any pair- the full version of the paper. wise voting rule r for which there exists a (natural) scoring function s : [1 Rk ! n such that r(Π) is the highest- 1Even in the context of rankings, however, voting rules like k=1 R the second-order Copeland rule [4] and many elimination- scoring candidate according to s(Π) under some fixed tie- style rules [15, 16, 17, 18] are known to be computationally breaking rule. That is, r(Π) = T (arg maxi si(Π)) for some resistant to manipulation by a single voter. tie-breaking rule T : 2[n] n f;g ! [n] satisfying T (S) 2 S for (a) Before manipulation (b) After manipulation (c) After restricted manipulation Figure 1: An illustration of the election instance in Example 2.1. (a) Each vertex of the multigraph represents a candidate and each dashed edge represents the number of voters with that preference (e.g. two voters prefer AC). (b) The pairwise comparisons made by the manipulator are represented by solid edges and the pBorda score of the winning candidate is indicated in boldface.
Recommended publications
  • Complexity Theory Lecture 9 Co-NP Co-NP-Complete
    Complexity Theory 1 Complexity Theory 2 co-NP Complexity Theory Lecture 9 As co-NP is the collection of complements of languages in NP, and P is closed under complementation, co-NP can also be characterised as the collection of languages of the form: ′ L = x y y <p( x ) R (x, y) { |∀ | | | | → } Anuj Dawar University of Cambridge Computer Laboratory NP – the collection of languages with succinct certificates of Easter Term 2010 membership. co-NP – the collection of languages with succinct certificates of http://www.cl.cam.ac.uk/teaching/0910/Complexity/ disqualification. Anuj Dawar May 14, 2010 Anuj Dawar May 14, 2010 Complexity Theory 3 Complexity Theory 4 NP co-NP co-NP-complete P VAL – the collection of Boolean expressions that are valid is co-NP-complete. Any language L that is the complement of an NP-complete language is co-NP-complete. Any of the situations is consistent with our present state of ¯ knowledge: Any reduction of a language L1 to L2 is also a reduction of L1–the complement of L1–to L¯2–the complement of L2. P = NP = co-NP • There is an easy reduction from the complement of SAT to VAL, P = NP co-NP = NP = co-NP • ∩ namely the map that takes an expression to its negation. P = NP co-NP = NP = co-NP • ∩ VAL P P = NP = co-NP ∈ ⇒ P = NP co-NP = NP = co-NP • ∩ VAL NP NP = co-NP ∈ ⇒ Anuj Dawar May 14, 2010 Anuj Dawar May 14, 2010 Complexity Theory 5 Complexity Theory 6 Prime Numbers Primality Consider the decision problem PRIME: Another way of putting this is that Composite is in NP.
    [Show full text]
  • NP-Completeness: Reductions Tue, Nov 21, 2017
    CMSC 451 Dave Mount CMSC 451: Lecture 19 NP-Completeness: Reductions Tue, Nov 21, 2017 Reading: Chapt. 8 in KT and Chapt. 8 in DPV. Some of the reductions discussed here are not in either text. Recap: We have introduced a number of concepts on the way to defining NP-completeness: Decision Problems/Language recognition: are problems for which the answer is either yes or no. These can also be thought of as language recognition problems, assuming that the input has been encoded as a string. For example: HC = fG j G has a Hamiltonian cycleg MST = f(G; c) j G has a MST of cost at most cg: P: is the class of all decision problems which can be solved in polynomial time. While MST 2 P, we do not know whether HC 2 P (but we suspect not). Certificate: is a piece of evidence that allows us to verify in polynomial time that a string is in a given language. For example, the language HC above, a certificate could be a sequence of vertices along the cycle. (If the string is not in the language, the certificate can be anything.) NP: is defined to be the class of all languages that can be verified in polynomial time. (Formally, it stands for Nondeterministic Polynomial time.) Clearly, P ⊆ NP. It is widely believed that P 6= NP. To define NP-completeness, we need to introduce the concept of a reduction. Reductions: The class of NP-complete problems consists of a set of decision problems (languages) (a subset of the class NP) that no one knows how to solve efficiently, but if there were a polynomial time solution for even a single NP-complete problem, then every problem in NP would be solvable in polynomial time.
    [Show full text]
  • Computational Complexity: a Modern Approach
    i Computational Complexity: A Modern Approach Draft of a book: Dated January 2007 Comments welcome! Sanjeev Arora and Boaz Barak Princeton University [email protected] Not to be reproduced or distributed without the authors’ permission This is an Internet draft. Some chapters are more finished than others. References and attributions are very preliminary and we apologize in advance for any omissions (but hope you will nevertheless point them out to us). Please send us bugs, typos, missing references or general comments to [email protected] — Thank You!! DRAFT ii DRAFT Chapter 9 Complexity of counting “It is an empirical fact that for many combinatorial problems the detection of the existence of a solution is easy, yet no computationally efficient method is known for counting their number.... for a variety of problems this phenomenon can be explained.” L. Valiant 1979 The class NP captures the difficulty of finding certificates. However, in many contexts, one is interested not just in a single certificate, but actually counting the number of certificates. This chapter studies #P, (pronounced “sharp p”), a complexity class that captures this notion. Counting problems arise in diverse fields, often in situations having to do with estimations of probability. Examples include statistical estimation, statistical physics, network design, and more. Counting problems are also studied in a field of mathematics called enumerative combinatorics, which tries to obtain closed-form mathematical expressions for counting problems. To give an example, in the 19th century Kirchoff showed how to count the number of spanning trees in a graph using a simple determinant computation. Results in this chapter will show that for many natural counting problems, such efficiently computable expressions are unlikely to exist.
    [Show full text]
  • NP-Completeness Part I
    NP-Completeness Part I Outline for Today ● Recap from Last Time ● Welcome back from break! Let's make sure we're all on the same page here. ● Polynomial-Time Reducibility ● Connecting problems together. ● NP-Completeness ● What are the hardest problems in NP? ● The Cook-Levin Theorem ● A concrete NP-complete problem. Recap from Last Time The Limits of Computability EQTM EQTM co-RE R RE LD LD ADD HALT ATM HALT ATM 0*1* The Limits of Efficient Computation P NP R P and NP Refresher ● The class P consists of all problems solvable in deterministic polynomial time. ● The class NP consists of all problems solvable in nondeterministic polynomial time. ● Equivalently, NP consists of all problems for which there is a deterministic, polynomial-time verifier for the problem. Reducibility Maximum Matching ● Given an undirected graph G, a matching in G is a set of edges such that no two edges share an endpoint. ● A maximum matching is a matching with the largest number of edges. AA maximummaximum matching.matching. Maximum Matching ● Jack Edmonds' paper “Paths, Trees, and Flowers” gives a polynomial-time algorithm for finding maximum matchings. ● (This is the same Edmonds as in “Cobham- Edmonds Thesis.) ● Using this fact, what other problems can we solve? Domino Tiling Domino Tiling Solving Domino Tiling Solving Domino Tiling Solving Domino Tiling Solving Domino Tiling Solving Domino Tiling Solving Domino Tiling Solving Domino Tiling Solving Domino Tiling The Setup ● To determine whether you can place at least k dominoes on a crossword grid, do the following: ● Convert the grid into a graph: each empty cell is a node, and any two adjacent empty cells have an edge between them.
    [Show full text]
  • CS286.2 Lectures 5-6: Introduction to Hamiltonian Complexity, QMA-Completeness of the Local Hamiltonian Problem
    CS286.2 Lectures 5-6: Introduction to Hamiltonian Complexity, QMA-completeness of the Local Hamiltonian problem Scribe: Jenish C. Mehta The Complexity Class BQP The complexity class BQP is the quantum analog of the class BPP. It consists of all languages that can be decided in quantum polynomial time. More formally, Definition 1. A language L 2 BQP if there exists a classical polynomial time algorithm A that ∗ maps inputs x 2 f0, 1g to quantum circuits Cx on n = poly(jxj) qubits, where the circuit is considered a sequence of unitary operators each on 2 qubits, i.e Cx = UTUT−1...U1 where each 2 2 Ui 2 L C ⊗ C , such that: 2 i. Completeness: x 2 L ) Pr(Cx accepts j0ni) ≥ 3 1 ii. Soundness: x 62 L ) Pr(Cx accepts j0ni) ≤ 3 We say that the circuit “Cx accepts jyi” if the first output qubit measured in Cxjyi is 0. More j0i specifically, letting P1 = j0ih0j1 be the projection of the first qubit on state j0i, j0i 2 Pr(Cx accepts jyi) =k (P1 ⊗ In−1)Cxjyi k2 The Complexity Class QMA The complexity class QMA (or BQNP, as Kitaev originally named it) is the quantum analog of the class NP. More formally, Definition 2. A language L 2 QMA if there exists a classical polynomial time algorithm A that ∗ maps inputs x 2 f0, 1g to quantum circuits Cx on n + q = poly(jxj) qubits, such that: 2q i. Completeness: x 2 L ) 9jyi 2 C , kjyik2 = 1, such that Pr(Cx accepts j0ni ⊗ 2 jyi) ≥ 3 2q 1 ii.
    [Show full text]
  • NP-Completeness Part II
    NP-Completeness Part II Outline for Today ● Recap from Last Time ● What is NP-completeness again, anyway? ● 3SAT ● A simple, canonical NP-complete problem. ● Independent Sets ● Discovering a new NP-complete problem. ● Gadget-Based Reductions ● A common technique in NP reductions. ● 3-Colorability ● A more elaborate NP-completeness reduction. ● Recent News ● Things happened! What were they? Polynomial-Time Reductions ● If A ≤P B and B ∈ P, then A ∈ P. ● If A ≤P B and B ∈ NP, then A ∈ NP. P NP NP-Hardness ● A language L is called NP-hard if for every A ∈ NP, we have A ≤P L. ● A language in L is called NP-complete if L is NP-hard and L ∈ NP. ● The class NPC is the set of NP-complete problems. NP NP-Hard NPC P The Tantalizing Truth Theorem: If any NP-complete language is in P, then P = NP. Proof: Suppose that L is NP-complete and L ∈ P. Now consider any arbitrary NP problem A. Since L is NP-complete, we know that A ≤p L. Since L ∈ P and A ≤p L, we see that A ∈ P. Since our choice of A was arbitrary, this means that NP ⊆ P, so P = NP. ■ P = NP The Tantalizing Truth Theorem: If any NP-complete language is not in P, then P ≠ NP. Proof: Suppose that L is an NP-complete language not in P. Since L is NP-complete, we know that L ∈ NP. Therefore, we know that L ∈ NP and L ∉ P, so P ≠ NP. ■ NP NPC P How do we even know NP-complete problems exist in the first place? Satisfiability ● A propositional logic formula φ is called satisfiable if there is some assignment to its variables that makes it evaluate to true.
    [Show full text]
  • The Polynomial Hierarchy and Alternations
    Chapter 5 The Polynomial Hierarchy and Alternations “..synthesizing circuits is exceedingly difficulty. It is even more difficult to show that a circuit found in this way is the most economical one to realize a function. The difficulty springs from the large number of essentially different networks available.” Claude Shannon 1949 This chapter discusses the polynomial hierarchy, a generalization of P, NP and coNP that tends to crop up in many complexity theoretic inves- tigations (including several chapters of this book). We will provide three equivalent definitions for the polynomial hierarchy, using quantified pred- icates, alternating Turing machines, and oracle TMs (a fourth definition, using uniform families of circuits, will be given in Chapter 6). We also use the hierarchy to show that solving the SAT problem requires either linear space or super-linear time. p p 5.1 The classes Σ2 and Π2 To understand the need for going beyond nondeterminism, let’s recall an NP problem, INDSET, for which we do have a short certificate of membership: INDSET = {hG, ki : graph G has an independent set of size ≥ k} . Consider a slight modification to the above problem, namely, determin- ing the largest independent set in a graph (phrased as a decision problem): EXACT INDSET = {hG, ki : the largest independent set in G has size exactly k} . Web draft 2006-09-28 18:09 95 Complexity Theory: A Modern Approach. c 2006 Sanjeev Arora and Boaz Barak. DRAFTReferences and attributions are still incomplete. P P 96 5.1. THE CLASSES Σ2 AND Π2 Now there seems to be no short certificate for membership: hG, ki ∈ EXACT INDSET iff there exists an independent set of size k in G and every other independent set has size at most k.
    [Show full text]
  • Glossary of Complexity Classes
    App endix A Glossary of Complexity Classes Summary This glossary includes selfcontained denitions of most complexity classes mentioned in the b o ok Needless to say the glossary oers a very minimal discussion of these classes and the reader is re ferred to the main text for further discussion The items are organized by topics rather than by alphab etic order Sp ecically the glossary is partitioned into two parts dealing separately with complexity classes that are dened in terms of algorithms and their resources ie time and space complexity of Turing machines and complexity classes de ned in terms of nonuniform circuits and referring to their size and depth The algorithmic classes include timecomplexity based classes such as P NP coNP BPP RP coRP PH E EXP and NEXP and the space complexity classes L NL RL and P S P AC E The non k uniform classes include the circuit classes P p oly as well as NC and k AC Denitions and basic results regarding many other complexity classes are available at the constantly evolving Complexity Zoo A Preliminaries Complexity classes are sets of computational problems where each class contains problems that can b e solved with sp ecic computational resources To dene a complexity class one sp ecies a mo del of computation a complexity measure like time or space which is always measured as a function of the input length and a b ound on the complexity of problems in the class We follow the tradition of fo cusing on decision problems but refer to these problems using the terminology of promise problems
    [Show full text]
  • A Short History of Computational Complexity
    The Computational Complexity Column by Lance FORTNOW NEC Laboratories America 4 Independence Way, Princeton, NJ 08540, USA [email protected] http://www.neci.nj.nec.com/homepages/fortnow/beatcs Every third year the Conference on Computational Complexity is held in Europe and this summer the University of Aarhus (Denmark) will host the meeting July 7-10. More details at the conference web page http://www.computationalcomplexity.org This month we present a historical view of computational complexity written by Steve Homer and myself. This is a preliminary version of a chapter to be included in an upcoming North-Holland Handbook of the History of Mathematical Logic edited by Dirk van Dalen, John Dawson and Aki Kanamori. A Short History of Computational Complexity Lance Fortnow1 Steve Homer2 NEC Research Institute Computer Science Department 4 Independence Way Boston University Princeton, NJ 08540 111 Cummington Street Boston, MA 02215 1 Introduction It all started with a machine. In 1936, Turing developed his theoretical com- putational model. He based his model on how he perceived mathematicians think. As digital computers were developed in the 40's and 50's, the Turing machine proved itself as the right theoretical model for computation. Quickly though we discovered that the basic Turing machine model fails to account for the amount of time or memory needed by a computer, a critical issue today but even more so in those early days of computing. The key idea to measure time and space as a function of the length of the input came in the early 1960's by Hartmanis and Stearns.
    [Show full text]
  • NP-Complete Problems and Physical Reality
    NP-complete Problems and Physical Reality Scott Aaronson∗ Abstract Can NP-complete problems be solved efficiently in the physical universe? I survey proposals including soap bubbles, protein folding, quantum computing, quantum advice, quantum adia- batic algorithms, quantum-mechanical nonlinearities, hidden variables, relativistic time dilation, analog computing, Malament-Hogarth spacetimes, quantum gravity, closed timelike curves, and “anthropic computing.” The section on soap bubbles even includes some “experimental” re- sults. While I do not believe that any of the proposals will let us solve NP-complete problems efficiently, I argue that by studying them, we can learn something not only about computation but also about physics. 1 Introduction “Let a computer smear—with the right kind of quantum randomness—and you create, in effect, a ‘parallel’ machine with an astronomical number of processors . All you have to do is be sure that when you collapse the system, you choose the version that happened to find the needle in the mathematical haystack.” —From Quarantine [31], a 1992 science-fiction novel by Greg Egan If I had to debate the science writer John Horgan’s claim that basic science is coming to an end [48], my argument would lean heavily on one fact: it has been only a decade since we learned that quantum computers could factor integers in polynomial time. In my (unbiased) opinion, the showdown that quantum computing has forced—between our deepest intuitions about computers on the one hand, and our best-confirmed theory of the physical world on the other—constitutes one of the most exciting scientific dramas of our time.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Complexity Theory
    LECTURES 4,5 & 6 1 Complexity Theory This part of the course will teach us why some problems are more difficult than others, but on the way we will learn a lot of different classes of problems like scheduling prob- lems, routing problems and facility location problems. The problems that we have seen in this course were all solvable with algorithms that were efficient, allowing to solve large instances exactly. E.g. every instance of MST with n vertices can be solved in O(nlogn) time. We will be very strict in this part of the course in distinguishing between a problem and its instances. The situation is much worse for the Travelling Salesman problem: TRAVELLING SALESMAN. (TSP) Instance: Given n points and a distance between each pair of points. Question: Find a tour that passes each point exactly once, ending in the point where it started, and with minimum total length. Despite 50 years of intensive research on the TSP no efficient algorithm has been found. Complexity theory aims to answer the question if the research community has been too stupid or unlucky, or that TSP is in fact intrinsically more difficult than other problems. Complexity theory works with a mathematically rigorous definition of efficient algo- rithm: Definition. An efficient algorithm for problem P is an algorithm that solves every in- stance of P in a number of elementary computer operations that is bounded by a poly- nomial function of the size of the instance. Some phrases in this definition are emphasized. The algorithm is to solve every instance, even the hardest instance.
    [Show full text]
  • Limits to Parallel Computation: P-Completeness Theory
    Limits to Parallel Computation: P-Completeness Theory RAYMOND GREENLAW University of New Hampshire H. JAMES HOOVER University of Alberta WALTER L. RUZZO University of Washington New York Oxford OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS 1995 This book is dedicated to our families, who already know that life is inherently sequential. Preface This book is an introduction to the rapidly growing theory of P- completeness — the branch of complexity theory that focuses on identifying the “hardest” problems in the class P of problems solv- able in polynomial time. P-complete problems are of interest because they all appear to lack highly parallel solutions. That is, algorithm designers have failed to find NC algorithms, feasible highly parallel solutions that take time polynomial in the logarithm of the problem size while using only a polynomial number of processors, for them. Consequently, the promise of parallel computation, namely that ap- plying more processors to a problem can greatly speed its solution, appears to be broken by the entire class of P-complete problems. This state of affairs is succinctly expressed as the following question: Does P equal NC ? Organization of the Material The book is organized into two parts: an introduction to P- completeness theory, and a catalog of P-complete and open prob- lems. The first part of the book is a thorough introduction to the theory of P-completeness. We begin with an informal introduction. Then we discuss the major parallel models of computation, describe the classes NC and P, and present the notions of reducibility and com- pleteness. We subsequently introduce some fundamental P-complete problems, followed by evidence suggesting why NC does not equal P.
    [Show full text]