This Thesis Has Been Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for a Postgraduate Degree (E.G

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

This Thesis Has Been Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for a Postgraduate Degree (E.G This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: • This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. • A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. • This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. • The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author. • When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given. Peter Fazekas Tagging the World: Descrying Consciousness in Cognitive Processes PhD Thesis School of Philosophy, Psychology and Language Sciences The University of Edinburgh 2012 Word Count Full: 116 524 Preliminaries: 3 435 Main text: 91 564 Footnotes: 16 260 Bibliography: 5 265 Table of Contents Table of Contents i Declaration vi Note on Publication vii Abstract viii Introduction ix PART 1: SETTING THE STAGE Chapter 1: Physicalism 1.1 The Doctrine of Physicalism 1 1.2 The Causal Argument for Physicalism 3 1.2.1 Prima facie non-physical causes having physical effects 4 1.2.2 The causal completeness of the physical 5 1.2.3 No overdetermination 7 1.3 Understanding ‘Nothing Over and Above‘ 8 1.3.1 Eliminative physicalism 8 1.3.2 Reductive physicalism 10 1.3.3 Non-reductive physicalism 14 1.4 Interpreting ‘Nothing Over and Above’ as Metaphysical Determination 18 1.4.1 Understanding (E3) 19 1.4.2 Understanding (E2) 21 1.4.3 Understanding (E1) 23 1.4.4 Distinguishing physicalism and emergentism 25 1.5 A Problem with the Metaphysical/Nomological Distinction 27 1.5.1 Jessica Wilson’s objection 27 1.5.2 The core argument against Wilson’s objection 29 1.5.3 Refining the core argument—round 1: trans-ordinal laws as causal laws 32 i 1.5.4 Refining the core argument—round 2: a different understanding of emergent causation 35 1.5.5 Refining the core argument—round 3: property individuation and full-fledged dispositional essentialism 37 1.6 What is Physical? 40 1.6.1 A note on how to understand metaphysical necessity: focus on the base set 41 1.6.2 Hempel’s dilemma and the via negativa 44 1.6.3 Conflicting intuitions 47 1.6.4 The ultimate via negativa: physicalism relativised 51 Chapter 2: Physicalism about Consciousness and the Epistemic Gap 2.1 Conscious Experience 55 2.1.1 The phenomenal character of conscious experience 56 2.1.2 The hard problem 58 2.2 Epistemic Arguments against Physicalism about Consciousness 61 2.2.1 The general strategy 61 2.2.2 Levine’s explanatory gap 63 2.2.3 Chalmers’ conceivability argument 67 2.2.4 Jackson’s knowledge argument 71 2.3 The Entailment Thesis and A Priori Physicalism 74 Chapter 3: Phenomenal Concept Strategy 3.1 Introducing Phenomenal Concepts 77 3.1.1 There is something about Mary 78 3.1.2 Phenomenal Concept Strategy 79 3.1.3 A posteriori physicalism 81 3.2 The Locus Classicus: Brian Loar’s Account 82 3.2.1 Recognitional concepts 82 3.2.2 Conceptual independence 84 ii 3.2.3 Direct reference 86 3.2.4 Own mode of presentation 88 3.3 Elaborating on the Direct Reference Claim 90 3.3.1 The causal-recognitional account 90 3.3.2 The demonstrative/indexical account 94 3.4 Elaborating on the Own Mode of Presentation Claim 100 3.4.1 The higher-order experience account 101 3.4.2 The constitutional account 105 3.5 Phenomenal Concepts and Perception 111 3.5.1 Perceptual Concepts 111 3.5.2 Phenomenal Concepts 115 PART 2: THE MONADIC MARKER ACCOUNT Chapter 4: Monadic Markers 4.1 Three Observations about Conscious Experience 119 4.1.1 Structure in experiences 119 4.1.2 Structure and phenomenal character 124 4.1.3 Further defending the observations made 128 4.2 Three Claims about Perceptual Representations 133 4.2.1 Simple and complex representations 135 4.2.2 Representational hierarchy according to contemporary cognitive neuroscience 139 4.2.3 Refining the claims: representational hierarchy and central access 141 4.3 Monadic Markers 145 4.3.1 Unstructured representations 145 4.3.2 Unstructured representations due to sensitivity threshold and monadic markers 148 4.3.3 The Monadic Marker Account of conscious experience 152 iii Chapter 5: Monadic Markers in Action 5.1 Monadic Markers within Dretske’s Framework 158 5.1.1 The information-theoretic framework 158 5.1.2 Sensation, perception, and cognition within the information-theoretic framework 164 5.1.3 Monadic markers as the sensory bases of sensory/phenomenal concepts 171 5.2 Monadic Markers & Fodorian Psycho-Semantics 179 5.2.1 General Fodorian framework 179 5.2.2 Causal role exchange and functional un-analysability 182 5.2.3 Explaining the epistemic gap within the Fodorian framework 184 5.3 The Explanatory Power of the Monadic Marker Account 188 5.3.1 Explaining the primary-secondary quality distinction 189 5.3.2 Explaining functional un-analysability 193 5.3.3 Explaining the epistemic gap 196 PART 3: REDUCTIVE EXPLANATION Chapter 6: Reduction, Reductive Explanation, and Identities 6.1 Reduction and Reductive Explanation 203 6.1.1 Reduction and physicalism 205 6.1.2 Reductive explanation 207 6.2 Models of Reduction 210 6.2.1 Nagelian theory reduction 210 6.2.2 Hooker’s reduction 214 6.2.3 Functional reduction 217 6.3 Identities and Reductive Explanation 221 6.3.1 Identities are justified by reductive explanation 222 6.3.2 Identities do not need explanation 227 iv 6.3.3 Identities are justified by inference to the best explanation 235 6.3.4 Is the non-transparent model really a version of reductive explanation? 243 Chapter 7: Reductive Explanation and Prior Identities 7.1 Does transparent reductive explanation deliver? 251 7.1.1 From H2O to water 254 7.1.2 Kim’s functional reduction 263 7.1.3 The Chalmers-Jackson proposal 266 7.2 Reductive Explanation via ‘Prior Identities‘ 277 7.2.1 Mechanistic explanation and prior identities 279 7.2.2 Hooker’s model of reduction and prior identities 290 7.2.3 The role of prior identities in reductive explanations 295 7.3 Conclusion: the Monadic Marker Account as Reductive Explanation Via Prior Identities 302 Bibliography 306 v Declaration Hereby, I declare that this PhD thesis is my own work, and has not been submitted for any other professional degree or qualification. Peter Fazekas vi Note on Publication Parts of Chapter 5, Chapter 6, and Chapter 7 have been published, with support from Prof. Jesper Kallestrup. Parts of Chapter 5 (§5.2) were published as: Cognitive Architecture and the Epistemic Gap: Defending Physicalism without Phenomenal Concepts (2011). Philosophia, 39(1), 21-29. DOI: 10.1007/s11406-010-9274-5 Parts of Chapter 6 (§6.2) and parts of Chapter 7 (§7.2.2) were published as: Reconsidering the Role of Bridge Laws in Inter-Theoretical Reductions (2009). Erkenntnis, 71(3), 303-322. DOI: 10.1007/s10670-009-9181-y Parts of Chapter 7 (§7.2.1) were published as: Causation at Different Levels—Tracking the Commitments of Mechanistic Explanations (2011). [with Gergely Kertész] Biology and Philosophy, 26(3), 365-383. DOI: 10.1007/s10539-011-9247-5 vii Abstract Although having conscious experiences is a fundamental feature of our everyday life, our understanding of what consciousness is is very limited. According to one of the main conclusions of contemporary philosophy of mind, the qualitative aspect of consciousness seems to resist functionalisation, i.e. it cannot be adequately defined solely in terms of functional or causal roles, which leads to an epistemic gap between phenomenal and scientific knowledge. Phenomenal qualities, then, seem to be, in principle, unexplainable in scientific terms. As a reaction to this pessimistic conclusion it is a major trend in contemporary science of consciousness to turn away from subjective experiences and re-define the subject of investigations in neurological and behavioural terms. This move, however, creates a gap between scientific theories of consciousness, and the original phenomenon, which we are so intimately connected with. The thesis focuses on this gap. It is argued that it is possible to explain features of consciousness in scientific terms. The thesis argues for this claim from two directions. On the one hand, a specific identity theory is formulated connecting phenomenal qualities to certain intermediate level perceptual representations which are unstructured for central processes of the embedding cognitive system. This identity theory is hypothesised on the basis of certain similarities recognised between the phenomenal and the cognitive-representational domains, and then utilised in order to uncover further similarities between these two domains. The identity theory and the further similarities uncovered are then deployed in formulating explanations of the philosophically most important characteristics of the phenomenal domain—i.e. why phenomenal qualities resist functionalisation, and why the epistemic gap occurs. On the other hand, the thesis investigates and criticises existing models of reductive explanation. On the basis of a detailed analysis of how successful scientific explanations proceed a novel account of reductive explanation is proposed, which viii utilises so-called prior identities. Prior identities are prerequisites rather than outcomes of reductive explanations. They themselves are unexplained but are nevertheless necessary for mapping the features to be explained onto the features the explanation relies on.
Recommended publications
  • Block.What.Psch.States.Not.1972.Pdf
    Philosophical Review What Psychological States are Not Author(s): N. J. Block and J. A. Fodor Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 81, No. 2 (Apr., 1972), pp. 159-181 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2183991 Accessed: 08/09/2009 16:04 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind Body Problem and Brandom's Analytic Pragmatism
    The Mind-Body Problem and Brandom’s Analytic Pragmatism François-Igor Pris [email protected] Erfurt University (Nordhäuserstraße 63, 99089 Erfurt, Germany) Abstract. I propose to solve the hard problem in the philosophy of mind by means of Brandom‟s notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. The explanatory gap between a phenomenal concept and the corresponding theoretical concept is a gap in the pragmatically mediated semantic relation between them. It is closed if we do not neglect the pragmatics. 1 Introduction In the second section, I will formulate the hard problem. In the third section, I will describe a pragmatic approach to the problem and propose to replace the classical non-normative physicalism/naturalism with a normative physicalism/naturalism of Wittgensteinian language games. In subsection 3.1, I will give a definition of a normative naturalism. In subsection 3.2, I will make some suggestions concerning an analytic interpretation of the second philosophy of Wittgenstein. In the fourth section, I will propose a solution to the hard problem within Brandom‟s analytic pragmatism by using the notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. In the fifth section, I will make some suggestions about possible combinatorics related to pragmatically mediated semantic relations. In the sixth section, I will consider pragmatic and discursive versions of the mind-body identity M=B. In the last section, I will conclude that the explanatory gap is a gap in a pragmatically mediated semantic relation between B and M. It is closed if we do not neglect pragmatics. 2 The Hard Problem The hard problem in the philosophy of mind can be formulated as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind-Body Dualism and Mental Causation
    A Dissertation Submitted to the Temple University Graduate Board In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree by Examining Committee Members: ii ABSTRACT The Exclusion Argument for physicalism maintains that since every physical effect has a sufficient physical cause, and cases of causal overdetermination (wherein a single effect has more than one sufficient cause) are rare, it follows that if minds cause physical effects as frequently as they seem to, then minds must themselves be physical in nature. I contend that the Exclusion Argument fails to justify the rejection of interactionist dualism (the view that the mind is non-physical but causes physical effects). In support of this contention, I argue that the multiple realizability of mental properties and the phenomenal and intentional features of mental events give us reason to believe that mental properties and their instances are non-physical. I also maintain (a) that depending on how overdetermination is defined, the thesis that causal overdetermination is rare is either dubious or else consistent with interactionist dualism and the claim that every physical effect has a sufficient physical cause, and (b) that the claim that every physical effect has a sufficient physical cause is not clearly supported by current science. The premises of the Exclusion Argument are therefore too weak to justify the view that minds must be physical in order to cause physical effects as frequently as they seem to. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ABSTRACT........................................................................................................................ii
    [Show full text]
  • Mind/Body Overview
    Mind/Body Overview 1. Physics and Folk Psychology a. Physics: hard-nosed, particles, observables, repeatable b. Folk Psychology: Beliefs, hopes, desires, sensations, subjective, consciousness 2. Issues a. Ontological 1. What are mental states and processes? 2. What are physical states and processes? 3. How are the mental and physical related? 4. Example: Replace NS with silicon starting at retina. Still conscious? b. Semantical 1. Where do propositional attitudes get their meanings? Ex: Belief; Belief that p. 2. Where do qualia get their meanings? Ex: pain, red, warmth 3. Where do other terms get their meanings? Ex: horse, electron c. Epistemological 1. How do we know anything? 2. How do we know if something has a mind? (Problem of other minds) 3. How do I know my own mental states? (Problem of self-consciousness) d. Methodological 1. What are appropriate methods for studying psychology? 2. What determines their propriety? 3. Ontologies a. Substance Dualism 1. Descartes: Mind is a distinct substance from matter 2. Matter: extended in space; has length, width, breadth, and position. 1 3. Mind: essence is thinking; has no extension or position in space. 4. Reasons: how could matter ever use language or reason mathematically? 5. Problem: How can mind interact with matter, and not violate conservation laws? 6. Problem: Electrons have no extension or determinate postion in space. Yet physical. 7. Eccles and Popper: mind affects probabilities of exocytosis at all synapses b. Popular Dualism 1. Mind is a “ghost in a machine”; machine=body; mind=spiritual substance 2. Mind is inside body (probably brain) 3. Mind interacts with brain by some form of energy exchange 4.
    [Show full text]
  • The “Supervenience Argument”: Kim's Challenge to Nonreductive Physicalism
    The “Supervenience Argument”: Kim’s Challenge to Nonreductive Physicalism AUSONIO MARRAS University of Western Ontario [email protected] JUHANI YLI-VAKKURI McGill University [email protected] ABSTRACT. Jaegwon Kim’s “supervenience argument” purports to show that epiphenomenalism about the mental follows from premises that any nonreductive physicalist should find acceptable. Kim regards his argument as a reductio ad absurdum of nonreductive physicalism. We reconstruct and evaluate the latest version of Kim’s argument. We argue that the premises of Kim’s argument are much less innocent than they may appear. In particular, we single out for criticism an unstated assumption about the identity conditions of events, and we argue that this assumption could be seen as all by itself implying that nonreductive physicalism is false, thus begging the question against that position. It is also dubious, we argue, whether Kim’s unstated assumption is even consistent with one of the stated assumptions of his argument, “the principle of causal exclusion”, given a standard understanding of causal overdetermination. We conclude with some polemical remarks about the conception of causation presupposed by Kim’s argument—a conception that appears to depart from that at work in science and commonsense discourse. 1. Introduction1 Many philosophers have worried that physical causation may “exclude” mental causation—physical and mental causes “compete” for efficacy, and because of some principle (the causal closure of the physical domain, for example), physical causes inevitably “win”. This picturesque language is common, but explicit arguments, which identify prima facie plausible principles from which epiphenomenalism about the mental would logically 1 We would like to thank Ian Gold for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • A DEFENSE of NON-REDUCTIVE PHYSICALISM a Dissertation
    A DEFENSE OF NON-REDUCTIVE PHYSICALISM A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Matthew Christian Haug May 2007 © 2007 Matthew Christian Haug A DEFENSE OF NON-REDUCTIVE PHYSICALISM Matthew Christian Haug, Ph. D. Cornell University 2007 I develop a novel formulation of, and argument for, non-reductive physicalism – roughly, the view that mental properties are natural properties that are realized by, but not identical to, neural and other low-level physical properties. Non-reductive physicalism has long been the dominant view in the philosophy of mind but has recently been challenged from two main directions. The first type of attack, the causal exclusion problem, points out an apparent inconsistency in non-reductive physicalism. The second type of attack focuses on the multiple realizability of mental properties: questioning either its prevalence or its efficacy in blocking reduction. In response to the exclusion problem, I first argue that one of the claims used to formulate the problem, the completeness of physics, has two parts and that there is no single domain of physical entities that is the smallest domain of which both parts are true. The conflation of these two parts has made it appear that non-reductive physicalism is inconsistent. I then show how to use the two completeness claims as part of an argument for a form of physicalism that need not be reductive. In response to the second type of attack, I provide a novel basis for the irreducibility of mental properties.
    [Show full text]
  • What Could Anti-Realism About Ordinary Psychology Possibly Be?*
    Draft for NYU Mind and Language Seminar, April 3, 2001. Not for further circulation. What Could Anti-Realism About Ordinary Psychology Possibly Be?* CRISPIN WRIGHT University of St. Andrews and Columbia University 1 Descartes observed that you could not lucidly doubt that you exist nor that you are a thinking thing. It would follow that there can be no lucid doubt about the reality of those psychological states and attributes whose possession is distinctive of thinkers, par excellence their being subject to the various kinds of doxastic and conative states involved in goal-directed thought. Thus it seems a short step from the Cogito to a form of realism about ordinary psychology. Yet many leading modern philosophers—for instance, Dennett, Stich, the Churchlands and, above all, Quine—have been united, notwithstanding other differences, in a tendency to scepticism about the reality of (explanation in terms of) intentional states. The connection with the Cogito explains why such scepticism seems like a contradiction of the obvious. It seems to flout the characteristic self-evidence of intentional states—the fact that a subject’s being in such a state is, as it seems, in typical cases effortlessly, non-empirically and non- inferentially available to them. Surely each of us does have—really have—beliefs, desires, hopes, intentions, wishes, and so on. Can't we each just tell that we do? Don't we do so all the time? * Specific acknowledgements are footnoted in the normal way but I'd like to record one general debt at the outset. My paper is in effect a sequel to Paul Boghossian's "The Status of Content", The Philosophical Review XCIX (1990), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • On Physical Multiple Realization
    ON PHYSICAL MULTIPLE REALIZATION BY RONALD P. ENDICOTT Perhaps no argument has done more to set the direction of contemporary philosophy of mind than the “multiple realizability argument.” First championed by Hilary Putnam and later reformulated by Jerry Fodor, the argument begins with the observation that a given psychological property can be realized by any number of diverse physical systems, and then ends with the conclusion that psychological properties are irreducible vis-à-vis the physical sciences.^ Its target, in other words, is type physicalism and the unity of science, as traditionally conceived. According to one popular criticism, however, the multiple realizability argument has been discredited by the fact that physical properties are also multiply realized} But this, I believe, is a mistake. While the criticism does serve to bring a number of important issues into better focus, it can be shown that the facts about physical multiple realization are perfectly consistent with the Putnam-Fodor style argument, and that, when such facts are rightly understood, they do not vitiate the original point about the irreducibility of psychological properties. /. Multiple Realization In spite of much talk about multiple realization, philosophers have generally been content to leave this central concept unanalyzed. I shall try to remedy this situation by indicating the two most salient features of the concept. First, there is the idea that a property is realized by a number of diverse states, which I take to mean that different state types can provide lawfully sufficient conditions for the instantiation of the multiply realized property. And second, there is the idea that among this range of diverse Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (1989) 212-224 0279-0750/89/0300-0212 $01.30 Copyright © 1989 University of Southern California ON PHYSICAL MULTIPLE REALIZATION 213 states, there are no lawfully necessary and sufficient conditions for the instantiation of that property.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mind Contents
    w 页码,1/177(W) Philosophy of Mind Jaegwon Kim BROWN UNIVERSITY Westview Press A Subsidiary of Perseus Books, L.L.C. -v- Dimensions of Philosophy Series All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopy, recording, or any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. Copyright © 1998 by Westview Press, Inc., A subsidiary of Perseus Books, L.L.C. Published in 1996 in the United States of America by Westview Press, Inc., 5500 Central Avenue, Boulder, Colorado 80301-2877, and in the United Kingdom by Westview Press, 12 Hid's Copse Road, Cumnor Hill, Oxford OX2 9JJ A CIP catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 0-8133-0775-9; ISBN 0-8133-0776-7 (pbk.) The paper used in this publication meets the requirements of the American National Standard for Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials Z39.48-1984. 10 9 8 -vi- Contents Preface xi 1 INTRODUCTION 1 Minds as Souls: Mental Substances , 2 Mental Properties, Events, and Processes , 5 Philosophy of Mind , 7 Supervenience, Dependence, and Minimal Physicalism , 9 Varieties of Mental Phenomena , 13 Is There a "Mark of the Mental"? 15 Further Readings , 23 Notes , 24 2 MIND AS BEHAVIOR: BEHAVIORISM 25 Reactions Against the Cartesian Conception , 26 What Is Behavior? 28 Logical Behaviorism: Hempel's Argument , 29 A Behavioral Translation of "Paul Has a Toothache," 31 Difficulties
    [Show full text]
  • Introductory Lectures: the Nature and History of Cognitive Science Chapter 4: Philosophy’S Convergence Towards Cognitive Science by Dr
    Introductory Lectures: The Nature and History of Cognitive Science Chapter 4: Philosophy’s Convergence Towards Cognitive Science By Dr. Charles Wallis Last revision: 9/24/2018 Chapter Outline 4.1 Introduction 4.2 The Scientific Explosion of the Early 20th Century 4.3 The Logical and Mathematical Explosion of the Early 20th Century 4.4 The Rise Logical Empiricism 4.5 Logical Behaviorism 4.6 Three Problems for Logical Behaviorism 4.7 Identity Theories: Reduction Through Reference Equivalence Rather Than Meaning Equivalence 4.8 Identity Theories: Type-Type Identity 4.9 Two Arguments For Type-Type Identity Theory 4.10 Identity Theories: Token-Token Identity 4.11 Functionalism 4.12 Computationalism 4.13 Property Dualism 4.14 Eliminative Materialism 4.15 Glossary of Key Terms 4.16 Bibliography The 20th Century and the Semantic Twist 4.1 Introduction Recall that ontological frameworks provide a general framework within which theorists specify domains of inquiry and construct theories to predict, manipulate, and explain phenomena within the domain. Once researchers articulate an ontological framework with sufficient clarity they begin to formulate and test theories. Chapter two ends with the suggestion that oppositional substance dualists face two major challenges in their attempt to transition from the articulation of an ontological framework to the formulation and testing of theories purporting to predict, manipulate, and explain mental phenomena. On the one hand, oppositional substance dualists have problems formulating theories providing explanations, predictions, and manipulations of the continual, seamless interaction between the mental and the physical. Philosophers often call this the interaction problem. On the other hand, the very nature of a mental substance--substance defined so as to share no properties with physical substance--gives rise to additional challenges.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Science Results of Evaluations Physicalism Physicalism GQ 2.1 Discussion Ramachandran 2005, Ch
    Agenda Pomona College LCS 11: Cognitive Science Results of evaluations Physicalism Physicalism GQ 2.1 discussion Ramachandran 2005, ch. 1–2 Jesse A. Harris • Face blindness (prosopagnosia) • Capgras syndrome February 15, 2013 • Phantom limb Jesse A. Harris: LCS 11: Cognitive Science, Physicalism 1 Jesse A. Harris: LCS 11: Cognitive Science, Physicalism 2 Physicalism Ways of being a physicalist In a nutshell Can cash out the relationship of mental states to physical ones Everything (mental) is physical! in whole host of (not necessarily mutually exclusive) ways: Physicalism Related to other doctrines, including materialism, often interchanged, but have slightly diUerent histories. 1. Identity variety 1.1 Type Brief questions 1.2 Token 2. Reduction 1. What are some intuitive motivations for physicalism? 2.1 Eliminative 2. How is it related to behaviorism? 2.2 Reductive 3. How does it diUer? 2.3 Nonreductive Jesse A. Harris: LCS 11: Cognitive Science, Physicalism 3 Jesse A. Harris: LCS 11: Cognitive Science, Physicalism 4 Type vs. Token Physicalism Ways to be a reductionist Terminology Reductive/Eliminative physicalism What is meant by the term type? How does it diUer from a Mental states are a mere Vction; part of a ‘folk psychology’ token? that can be eliminated once neuroscience is complete enough; Type Physicalism Mental states map onto or reduce entirely to physical ones. Each type of mental state is identical to a particular type or kind of physical state. Nonreductive physicalism Token Physicalism All is physical, but mental states cannot be explain solely in terms of physical ones. Each token of mental state has a physical realization.
    [Show full text]
  • The Myth of Nonreductive Materialism Author(S): Jaegwon Kim Source: Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, Vol
    The Myth of Nonreductive Materialism Author(s): Jaegwon Kim Source: Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, Vol. 63, No. 3 (Nov., 1989), pp. 31-47 Published by: American Philosophical Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3130081 . Accessed: 24/03/2011 08:49 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=amphilosophical. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. American Philosophical Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association. http://www.jstor.org THE MYTH OF NONREDUCTIVE MATERIALISM Jaegwon Kim Brown University PresidentialAddress delivered before the Eighty-seventhAnnual Central Division Meeting of the AmericanPhilosophical Association in Chicago,Illinois, April 28, 1989.
    [Show full text]