In the Sphere of the Personal: New Perspectives in the of Persons

Edited by James Beauregard Rivier University

Simon Smith University of Surrey

Vernon Series in Philosophy

Copyright © 2016 Vernon Press, an imprint of Vernon Art and Science Inc, on behalf of the author.

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Vernon Art and Ascience Inc. www.vernonpress.com

In the Americas: In the rest of the world: Vernon Press Vernon Press 1000 N West Street, C/Sancti Espiritu 17, Suite 1200, Wilmington, Malaga, 29006 Delaware 19801 Spain United States

Vernon Series in Philosophy

Library of Congress Control Number: 2016941627

ISBN: 978-1-62273-063-6 Product and company names mentioned in this work are the trademarks of their respec- tive owners. While every care has been taken in preparing this work, neither the authors nor Vernon Art and Science Inc. may be held responsible for any loss or damage caused or alleged to be caused directly or indirectly by the information contained in it.

Table of Contents

Foreword 1

Biographical notes on the contributors 3

Introduction 9

Acknowledgements 29

Chapter 1 Personal Identity With and Without 31 Richard C. Prust

Chapter 2 Integral Experience: A New Proposal on the Beginning of Knowledge 41 Juan Manuel Burgos Translated by James Beauregard

Chapter 3 Neuroethics and Impersonalism: Value Revelation in Subjective Disclosure 59 Denis Larrivee

Chapter 4 Persons and Passions: The Mature Cartesian Account 81 Mark C. R. Smith

Chapter 5 Holy Robot? Discourse on Persons and Machines in German 95 Rolf Ahlers

Chapter 6 The Socio-historical Ordeal of Personhood: Nietzsche and Freud 121 Jeffrey M. Jackson

Chapter 7 No Free Pass: Pringle-Pattison on Personhood, the , and Personal Immortality 133 Robert F. DeVall, Jr.

Chapter 8 Self and Person: Distinctions in Bergson 153 Robert G. Feidler

Chapter 9 Legal Personhood, Prenatal Humans and Feticide Laws 165 Lawrence J. Nelson

Chapter 10 The Consolation of Philosophers: Rebuilding Dignity and Self After Sexual Assault 179 Mackenzie Lefoster

Chapter 11 Returning to Redemption as a Theory for Justifying Punishment 195 Brian J. Buckley

Chapter 12 Roma Integration: Existential Tension Between Public Policy and the Person 213 Philippe-Edner Marius

Chapter 13 “We Are Not Disposable”: “Psychiatric”/Psycho-Social Disabilities and Social Justice 223 Carol J. Moeller

Chapter 14 Personhood in the Boardroom: A Schellingian Critique of Corporate and Organizational Deviance 245 Myron Moses Jackson

Endnotes 263

Index 367

Foreword

Personalism has deep roots both in India and in the Western world. In the West its roots lie in the theological controversies in Christianity. There the word ‘person’ came into use when speaking of the three persons of the Trinity. Soon it was used when speaking of individual humans created by and, bearing God's image, acquiring a dignity not possessed by any other creature. As thought continued and Western science developed, the theological understanding of nature and persons was deeply undercut. It was in this context that formed to combat what became known as Impersonalism. The latter presented itself in two forms, a substructure such as materialism, as in the hands of Samuel Al- exander, or a superstructure, such as Being or God whose nature manifests itself in all found within it and to which all else, including persons, is subordinated. Spinoza’s thought is a case in point. Over a period of time, grand metaphysical systems lost their appeal, and philosophers became influenced by scientific devel- opments in brain sciences and mental health, in language studies, and political developments that subordinate persons and their freedom to the state, as in totalitarian systems. Such developments also called for rethinking the nature of the person. Since the formation of the International Forum on Persons, philosophers have presented a plethora of papers, whose central focus has been to defeat Impersonalism in all its forms, and to gain a clearer understanding of persons. Those papers have come from many fields of study, including Philosophy, Political Science, Lin- guistics, Psychology, and Physics. In this book, we find a wide range of topics, similar to previous meetings of the International Forum. Occasionally, a paper appears that attempts a new formu- lation of a classic aspect of Personalism. Such a case is Burgos’ search for a full epistemology, which he has not been done by Personalists in any thoroughgoing manner. He references Borden Parker Bowne’s Personalism and ignores A Theory of

Thought and Knowledge, which is a full account of Personalist epistemology, deeply influenced by Kant. Burgos, on the other hand, is building within Thomism and ultimately Aristotle. From that perspective,he provides a new formulation, and is to be con- gratulated. Regarding a new formulation of persons, Richard Prust continues to develop a theory rooted in resolve. Thus, making an original contribution. These strengths are offset by the omission of transhumanism, and global bioethics. Obviously, no conference can cover all topics, and we can hope that in future conferences, many more of significant contemporary importance will be ad- dressed.

Thomas O. Buford

Biographical notes on the contributors

Rolf Ahlers, a native of Germany, has attended Drew, Princeton, Hamburg and Heidelberg Universities. He has done post-doctoral work at Munich and Princeton universities on government grants. He has taught at a variety of universities in Germany and in the United States. Professor Ahlers has concentrated on German Ideal- ism during the last thirty years, participating in many specialized groups on Fichte, Reinhold and Hegel. He lectured widely at Rome, Munich, Berlin, Toulouse, Vancouver, Montreal, Boston and other cities. He has published four books and many articles and reviews. He is retired since 2010 and working on a new book and several articles and reviews.

Brian J. Buckley is a Lecturer in the Philosophy Department and Director of Pre-Law Advising at Santa Clara University. His research interests chiefly concern the political, moral, and legal aspects of what is owed to persons. This includes primarily ques- tions of justice (procedural and substantive), the rule of law, and the common good. He wrote both a Master’s thesis and Doctoral dissertation on moral issues concerning personhood.

Juan Manuel Burgos specializes in anthropology and personal- ism. He works as Full Professor at the University San Pablo CEU (Madrid). He is the Founder (2003) and President of the Spanish Association of Personalism, the Asociación Iberoamericana de Personalismo (2011) and the academic journal of personalist phi- losophy “Quién” (2015). He has developed the theory of Modern Ontological Personalism. He has been a guest professor and has delivered papers at conferences in Oxford, USA, Poland, Mexico, Sweden, Argentina, Chile, Colombia and many other countries. He has published many papers and books, such as Antropología: una guía para la existencia (5ª ed.), Repensar la naturaleza humana,

4 Biographical notes of contributors

Introducción al personalismo (to be published by CUA Press) and La experiencia integral. Some of his books have been translated into Polish and Portuguese. His thought is already being developed by Beauregard, Bermeo, Rocha and others.

Robert F. DeVall, Jr. lives in Kutztown, Pennsylvania with his wife Louise and their four children. He received his B.A. in Philos- ophy from Kutztown University and his M.A. in Philosophy from West Chester University. His M.A. thesis, “Historicism and its Dis- contents”, concerns Giambattista Vico’s influence on the philoso- phy of history of both Hegel and Marx, and argues that Vico’s idea, “eternal history”, explains the course of history better than the linear views of Hegel and Marx.

Robert G. Fiedler received an MA in philosophy from Southern Illinois University in August of 2015. Following graduation, and against his better judgment, he moved to Galesburg, Illinois with his wife and two cats. Currently, Robert spends his time as a word- farmer, though this past season all of his crops have died. His wife supports him on her lucrative high school art teacher’s salary, for which he is very grateful. He hopes that next year the crops will be better, so that perhaps he may eat (by) his words.

Jeffrey M. Jackson is Associate Professor of Philosophy and Chair of the Department of Social Sciences at the University of Houston – Downtown. He holds a PhD from Vanderbilt University and was a Fulbright Scholar at the Catholic University of Leuven. He is the author of Philosophy and Working-through the Past: A Psychoanalytic Approach to Social Pathologies, as well as numer- ous articles. His research and teaching focus on the history of 19th and 20th Century European Philosophy, especially Psychoanalysis, Phenomenology, and Critical Theory.

Myron Moses Jackson is Visiting Professor of Philosophy at Grand Valley State University in Grand Rapids, MI. With a real pas- sion for teaching and interdisciplinary research, he enjoys eclectic scholarly engagement. His current work relies on the process phi- losophy of A. N. Whitehead to investigate the civilizational aims of entertainment, both metaphysically and aesthetically, to cultivate

Biographical notes of contributors 5

peace, truth, beauty, art, and adventure among human societies. Another focus deals with the interaction and difference between human and computational selfhood. In another life he would take up journalism, as a food critic and op-ed writer, following the scoop wherever it may lead.

Denis Larrivee has been an assistant Professor of Neuroscience at Cornell University Medical College, New York City, and a visiting Professor in the Department of Biology at Purdue University. He is a former fellow of Yale University Medical School Departments of Opthalmology and Biological Sciences. His current affiliations include a Visiting Scholar appointment at Loyola University, Chi- cago, the International Association of Catholic Bioethicists, and the International Neuroethics Society. He is the author of 30 publi- cations and one book on neuroscience and neuroethics.

Mackenzie Lefoster graduated from Belmont University with a B.A. in Philosophy in 2014, and will be beginning her graduate studies in Autumn 2016. Her research interests include post- modernism, phenomenology, and , particu- larly in their capacity to give voice to the experience of oppressed and marginalized groups.

Philippe-Edner Marius is a Legislative Aide in the Senate of the State of New York. He earned his Baccalaureate degree in Anthro- pology from the City College of New York in 2012. Thereafter, he earned his Master’s degree in Public Policy from the Department of Public Policy at the Central European University, Budapest, spe- cializing in Higher Education Policy and Management. His aca- demic and intellectual interests are at the intersection of Existen- tialism, Public Policy and Anthropology.

Carol J. Moeller received her PhD in Philosophy from the Uni- versity of Pittsburgh in 1998, as well as Doctoral certificates in Women’s Studies and in Cultural Studies. She did her BA at Oberlin College. She was a Greenwall Fellow in Bioethics and Health Policy at Johns Hopkins and Georgetown Universities (01-03). Since 1997 she has taught at Moravian College in Bethlehem, PA, specializing in social justice.

6 Biographical notes of contributors

Lawrence J. Nelson is Associate Professor of Philosophy and a Faculty Scholar of the Markkula Center for Applied Ethics, Santa Clara University, Santa Clara, CA. He received a PhD in philosophy from St. Louis University in 1978 and a J.D. from the Yale Law School in 1981. Before joining the faculty at Santa Clara he prac- ticed health care law and provided bioethics consultation. Articles of his on bioethics have appeared in the Hastings Center Report, JAMA, Critical Care Medicine, Law, Medicine & Ethics, Lewis & Clark Law Review, Journal of Business Ethics Education, and Uni- versity of Denver Criminal Law Review.

Richard C. Prust lives in Chapel Hill, NC, where he putters away at a book on personal identity in moral and legal reasoning. He is active in the International Forum on Persons. Before retiring, he taught philosophy at St. Andrews University in North Carolina. His book, Wholeness: the Character Logic of Christian , is pub- lished by Rodopi Press.

Mark C. R. Smith teaches philosophy at Queen’s University in Kingston, Ontario. He did his doctoral work in the philosophy of mathematics, and has published work in that field, as well as on epistemology and Descartes’s philosophy. Mark teaches a range of subjects, including philosophy of mathematics, , epis- temology, and Descartes.

…and on the Editors

James Beauregard is a Lecturer in the psychology doctoral pro- gram at Rivier University, Nashua, New Hampshire. He teaches courses in Neuropsychology, Aging and the Biological Bases of Behaviour. He is also a Clinical Neuropsychologist with 20 years experience working with individuals with dementia and their fami- lies. He earned his graduate degrees at Northeastern University, Boston. His research interests include Neuroethics and Personalist philosophy in both the British and Continental traditions, includ- ing the intersection of these two fields in understanding person-

Biographical notes of contributors 7

hood. He is a member of the British Personalist Forum, and the International Neuroethics Society.

Simon Smith is the editor of Appraisal, journal of the British Personalist Forum. Many years ago, he fled the University of Sus- sex clutching a DPhil in trembling hands. Having taught Philoso- phy at the University of Southampton in the UK and the Modern College of Business and Science in Oman, he now belongs, body and soul, to the Open Research team at the University of Surrey. There, he works tirelessly to subvert the behemoth of scholarly publishing and dreams of a world of free scholarly communica- tion. Buried deep in the Surrey Downs, he occasionally pursues a more perfect alignment of science and through the diverse forms of personal analogy at work in modern physics and modern metaphysics.

Introduction

The articles in this collection were originally presented at the 13th International Conference on Persons, held at Boston University in August 2015. This biennial event, founded in 1989 by Thomas O. Buford and Charles Conti, attracts a host of international scholars, both venerable and aspiring. It is widely regarded as the premier event for those whose research concerns the philosophical tradi- tion known as “Personalism.” That tradition is, perhaps, best known today in its American and European manifestations, although there remains a small but fiercely defended stronghold in Britain. In America, the Boston School is well represented by Borden Parker Bowne, Edgar Shef- field Brightman, and its most famous student, Martin Luther King Jr. In Europe, the crop is somewhat more diverse, ranging as it does, transcontinentally, from ’s Paris to Max Scheler’s Munich, before heading eastwards to Karol Wojtyla’s Lu- blin. Britain, meanwhile, has its champions in the likes of John Macmurray, Austin Marsden Farrer, and Michael Polanyi. While the concept “person” lies close to the heart of the Abrahamic reli- gions and the which continue to grow out of them, Personalism is by no means an exclusively Western development. Its roots are also found in the Hindu traditions of India,1 as well as the Confucian and Buddhist philosophies of China and Japan. The ties that bind these disparate intellectual cultures may ap- pear very loose indeed. There is little, if any, methodological or doctrinal consensus among them. Writing in the early 1940s, , would find himself confronted by, “[n]ot a per- sonalist doctrine, but personalist aspirations….” “There are,” he observed, “at least, a dozen personalist doctrines.”2 Not a great deal has changed since then. Nevertheless, those aspirations are shaped by the desire to respond, and respond vigorously, to the impersonal and depersonalising forces perceived to be at work in

10 Introduction

philosophy and , and, most recently, the natural and polit- ical sciences. Their common aim is to place persons at the heart of these discourses, to defend the idea that persons are the meta- physical, epistemological, and moral “bottom line;” in the words of Thomas Buford, “the supreme value and the key to the measuring of .”3 Evidently, then, how one thinks about persons can shape the very foundations of our thought; a good thing too, since “personhood” has become the first and most fundamental con- cern of the twenty-first century. With increasing urgency, it cuts across the academic scene, from philosophy and theology to the hard sciences and everything in between. Beyond academe, it rais- es its head in the worlds of medicine and healthcare, social wel- fare, and social justice; often ignored, its presence can still be felt in the political and economic winds that continue to thrash, espe- cially, at the poor and the vulnerable. The authors in this collection do not simply reflect upon such things, they put them to work on a range of philosophical prob- lems, both classical and contemporary. Personal identity, the na- ture and meaning of “personhood” and of reality figure large, as might be expected. Alongside them, stand the very current con- cerns of neuroethics and social justice. Our author’s perspectives, too, are many and varied, offering insights into the central debates of other philosophical traditions, such as the Cartesian, the Kanti- an, and the Hegelian. For readers unfamiliar with the Personalist tradition, a word of explanation is doubtless in order. To usher in the philosophical feast that is to follow, therefore, we should like to offer a few reflec- tions on what we regard as the more important factors motivating Personalist thinkers. Given the degree of diversity within the tradition, the reader might be forgiven for wondering what value Personalism may have for those whose intellectual upbringing has taken place elsewhere. What, in short, will they gain from it? One answer may be found in the aspirations to which Maritain refers, aspirations that clearly unite those dedicated to what is, you

Introduction 11

may be assured, a “pearl of great price.” Of these, the one that does so most steadfastly is the need to resist reductivism in all its forms. By temperament and training, Personalists are profoundly averse to any thought or practice that seeks to limit our understanding and, in consequence, the actual nature of persons. By contrast, they aim to construct the richest and deepest description of “per- sonhood.” For many, this elevates Personalism far above the mere- ly theoretical, endowing the tradition with a keenly pragmatic edge, which keeps it in the vanguard of social and political activ- ism.4 Such notions are, as the reader will discover, of considerable importance to the authors in this volume. In pursuing those ends, both practical and theoretical, a differ- ent conception of persons is required; one not held hostage to common physical, psychological, and spiritual constraints. Selves must slip between the bars erected by the habits of thought, seek- ing, instead, the ampliatory and amplificatory mechanisms that embody a psychodynamic account of themselves. The very bold might slip the leash of modern materialist dogma altogether, fol- low a theological path in search of higher forms of dialectics: returned unto spirit, personality engaged in its own infinite exten- sions. Whether or not the authors in this collection would agree wholeheartedly with such high falutin’ suggestions, they would, we hope, concur with their general direction. It, or something like it, certainly seems to be implied by those who address themselves to questions of morality and social justice. Most obvious, perhaps, is Brian Buckley’s treatment of punishment and redemption below. For redemption to be meaningful, in the secular or spiritual sense, there must be greater possibilities open to us than standard social, psychological, and metaphysical determinations would allow. This may be why no official Personalist Doctrine can be de- vised. Doctrines can be limiting; they set the rails on which thought runs, determine what counts as evidence and explanation. So much, of course, is true of all theoretical frameworks, including those erected by Personalists. Hence, there is always the risk that,

12 Introduction

while pointing out the mote in another’s eye, we may miss the lumberyard lodged in our own. Being part of so rich and diverse a tradition, however, enables most Personalists to retain a high de- gree of sensitivity to such things. If official doctrines can be limiting, definitions may prove even more so. In devising them, the tendency to determine precisely what is meant by a construct, how it should be correctly used and understood, is undeniably strong. Definitions seem, to our mind at least, almost designed to set a construct in aspic. It is certainly true that philosophers, perhaps more than others, are easily tempted to fasten upon them, though it be always in the name of clarity and accuracy; in stasis there is much comfort for the human soul. Such may be the comfort of the idle and the shallow, however; defini- tions, like labels and other forms of jargon, frequently discourage careful thought. And, after all, the tendency to oversimplify its ma- terials doubtless is, as trenchantly remarked, an occupational hazard of the theorizing mind.5 But perhaps we are being too hard on the ancein dictionaire, particularly given the well-documented phenomenon of semantic shift. For a century or more, morphologists and other social scien- tists – not to mention the occasional philosopher – have been pointing out this phenomenon, along with the inherent flexibility of language it denotes. In light of that, it might seem capricious, even wilfully cryptic, to talk against definitions in this way. In fact, few Personalists would disagree with those clever and cunning linguists who map the ebb and flow of meaning within and across languages. That is precisely why they are so often chary of any attempt to draw the noose of definition too tightly around the neck of our concept “person.” More precisely, they are suspi- cious of the theory of language this practice denotes. Certainly, most would brook no truck with the alternative, that substantival philosophy of language which demands a logically watertight con- formity of word to world and vice versa. That, in truth, is what we fear lies behind the desire to pin down our concepts once and for

Introduction 13

all: the hope that by rigidly determining the one, it will be possible to rigidly determine the other. Dubbed by J. L. Austin with the Latin tag, unum nomen, unum nominatum,6 this grinding hangover from the heady days of Carte- sian Realism is one from which has never quite recovered.7 The belief that for each word, there is a perfectly corresponding thing, and only one thing per thing named, was the fatal flaw in and British Empiricism in general. Having passed the cup to the next generation of scholars, the old Russellian school left much and, what is infi- nitely worse, the modern sciences still laboring under the burden of this poisoned premise.8 Evidently, however, as we have been shown many times before, our definitions and descriptions cannot be limited as logical em- piricism demands. They cannot be circumscribed in such a way as to foreclose on our understanding and use of a construct or, more importantly, on the reality we seek to understand by its applica- tion. In short, the correlation between word and world cannot be made logically watertight. The most obvious reason for this, Frie- drich Waismann would call the “open ended-ness” or “essential incompleteness” of our descriptions and definitions.9 We may delineate our terms for the practical purposes of particular en- quiry, that is, but we cannot do so a priori. We cannot, because sooner or later experience will catch us unawares; once sat upon by that capacious a posteriori, our constructs will never be the same again. Indeed, we may rely on it, as Michael Polanyi ob- served. Any description, and perhaps most especially scientific description, will prove its accuracy (and value), not in its immedi- ate validation, but by manifesting in an “indeterminate range of yet unknown and perhaps yet unthinkable consequences.”10 Like- wise, that which our descriptions and definitions tell us is real, is real because it can be expected to “reveal itself indeterminately in the future.” “[F]act,” as Austin wittily quipped, is always “richer than diction.”11

14 Introduction

Notably, Waismann takes us beyond this simple empirical prin- ciple. It is not just experience which refuses to be captured and caged by our concepts; the very concepts we use to understand, to make sense of experience are always ready to take flight. In Waismann’s particular idiom, this is Porosität der Begriffe, the “open texture” of language.12 Our definitions and descriptions are inherently “porous;” they cannot be sealed off, made “watertight,” to prevent meaning “leaking out,” or new meanings “leaking in.”13 Leakage is really only problematic, of course, when we forget that the limits we draw around our concepts are not set by God or the Natural Order. They are set by our field of enquiry and the direc- tion we pursue within it. In forgetting so, we foolishly convince ourselves that the furrows we plough across the field are the only legitimate furrows there are.14 Like any other philosopher, the Personalist, must, as T. S. Eliot said, continually “wrestle with words and meaning.”15 That scuffle may not be quite as intolerable as the poet imagined, however. For the Personalist is not without her allies. In the likes of Austin and Waismann she will find a philosophy of language that, although not exactly designed for the purpose, is nevertheless very well- suited to her particular requirements. By working with the grain of language and intelligent exploration, rather than against it, we are reminded that we cannot prescribe what will count as evidence for the presence of persons, nor preordain how our seemingly stable constructs might need moulding that we may recognize them. At its simplest, the difficulty we are attempting to describe is, as Don Marquis suggests, one of scope.16 Once we begin to define the scope of our principal categories and constructs, we run the very real risk of including either too much or too little. In some fields of enquiry, such risks may be trifling. What’s more, they are evidently not symmetrical. Even here, where our category is “person,” the dangers of having a scope large enough to include, for example, a number of non-human animals, are, perhaps, not very serious.17 What is likely to worry us far more is a lurch in the other direction, towards exclusion. Here, the consequences may be dire indeed, as Carol Moeller, Philippe-Edner Marius, and Lawrence Nelson are

Introduction 15

keen to remind us.18 The question they press upon us is of vital importance, and not only to Personalists. Who might justly de- mand whatever moral and metaphysical protection our category “person” might offer? How shall we judge? Perhaps we should draw up some such list of characteristics as proposed by Michael Allen Fox, decide according to whether we encounter in others “critical self-awareness; the ability to manipulate complex con- cepts and to use a sophisticated language.”19 Do so and a great many of our nearest and dearest might be ruled out of bounds. If we are honest, we might even admit that, on occasion, we our- selves would not be guaranteed to qualify. Besides, most normal people would regard the idea of ticking off items on a moral and metaphysical checklist absurd if not actually offensive; even some philosophers might balk at the idea. In the Western philosophical tradition, reason has commonly been judged the defining characteristic, indeed, the very , of persons. Once again, assuming that “reason” is no mere abstrac- tion, no empty concept, we are bound, it seems, to face the most serious scoping problems, particularly with regard to infants and those suffering from neurological, or psycho-social impairments. But there is another, more worrisome philosophical tendency at work here. Fortunately, the Personalist’s nose is a peculiarly sensi- tive instrument, ever on the alert for a sulphurous whiff of the re- ductive, the materialist, and the flatly impersonal. (Here, however, we may be forced to reassess our views in light of Rolf Ahler’s chap- ter below.)20 By placing undue, or worse, exclusive emphasis on reason we are left with a philosophical psychology too thin to be of lasting benefit in our search for self-knowledge, but quite sufficient to be of lasting damage. This is, perhaps, particularly obvious in the field of moral philosophy. Few, remotely sane, people would accept the utilitarian’s substitution of cost/benefit analysis – pre- sumed by some to be the acme of rational thought – for genuine ethics. There are those who would, when faced with suffering, pov- erty, and the concomitant demand for charity, advise a decrease in the surplus population. To them, we might reply, in proper Dick- ensian style, “Will you decide what men shall live, what men shall

16 Introduction

die? …O God! to hear the insect on the leaf pronouncing on the too much life among his hungry brothers in the dust!”21 So much is “wicked cant” we know; what of the other, who keeps divine com- pany on the flip side of this coin? As with any philosophical field in the Western tradition, few would deny his profound influence on Personalism; for example, in the keenly felt obligation to treat one another, not as objects, but as personal others. We should not overstate that influence, however; any moral system predicated on pure reason will, by virtue of its fundamentally impersonal nature, be unworkable for persons. Shall I, for instance, inform my wife that I intend to keep my promises to her, not out of affection or fidelity, but out of duty to the moral law within? Shall I tell her that to do otherwise would fail the test of universalizability, committing me to willing a contradiction and setting my face against reason itself? Not likely. Such humbug would, no doubt, be met with the very shortest of shrifts. Here too, Dickens has a word of warning for the wise: he who dedicates himself exclusively to his duty is liable to meet with a very bad end indeed.22 A degree of critical self- awareness or, more pertinently, quite crucial other-awareness might prevent pure reason having its head and landing us in con- siderable trouble. Evidently, there is much missing from the confirmed rational- ist’s moralising, and the psychology it implies, not least the ele- ment of emotion. Emotions, we have been schooled to suppose, contaminate our judgements; they lead us from the straight and narrow path of reason into the dark woods where lurks preference, partiality, and every kind of prejudice. Such de-personalising propaganda has no place in a proper understanding of persons, however. It is not remotely true that emotions are necessarily ei- ther anti- or irrational. Certainly, our feelings can be, as Macmur- ray puts it, “unreal;” that is to say, they may not harmonise well with the circumstances arousing them.23 Mortal dread in the pres- ence of ordinary house spiders is probably irrational; hence we dub it a phobia. We assume here that the phrase “ordinary house spiders” excludes those species capable of causing death. Should, however, one’s experience routinely include the Brazilian Hunts-

Introduction 17

man or those legendary fellows that live under Australian lavatory seats, then a degree of fear would not, one may suppose, be out of place. More importantly, passion and preference cannot be denied their place in our judgements; so much, William James eloquently demonstrated in “The Will to Believe.”24 The most hard-hearted of Kantians must care about his duty if he is to follow it. And not only the philosopher, but also the scientist, as Michael Polanyi reminds us: she too will be driven in her search for knowledge by her desire for it, her interest in her field, her love of her research.25 It is to be doubted whether anyone could undertake the years of gruelling work involved in scholarly research without a profound emotional attachment, both to the process and the subject matter. The sacri- fices are great, one must want the results very badly indeed. Oth- erwise put, Hume was quite correct when he dubbed reason the “slave of passion,” for reason alone does not move us to action.26 What’s more, the neurosciences appear to be catching up with James and Polanyi. Evidence suggests that, when those parts of the neural network concerned with emotions are damaged, the ability to make sensible and intelligent judgements is likewise impaired.27 Feelings and emotions are a crucial element of our philosophi- cal psychology; we exile them from our talk and thought about persons at our peril. In neither case, however, do we rely on feeling alone. What matters most of all, perhaps, is the pragmatic effect, what we do about our emotions; for, as Austin Farrer observed, “the doing, not the feeling, is the empirical test”28 of peril and pref- erence and everything in between. “[T]he doing,” too, is the test of our understanding of persons; indeed, action, personal action, will provide the empirical key to our conception of “personhood.” Perhaps the safest course, for philosophers at least, would be to avoid creating divisions and difficulties where none exist and, like Farrer, strive to keep “heart and head in dynamic balance.”29 As the old saw goes, a picture paints a thousand words; and the “word-picture” is no exception. Anyone with the remotest sensitiv- ity to language knows full well that there is truth in the poetic im-

18 Introduction

age. If we are to follow Farrer’s example, then we must have a head and a heart to balance. If, that is, “the doing” and not “the feeling” is to tell the tale, persons must have the wherewithal to do; they must be equipped with the apparatus of physical activity. What, after all, could they do without it? Very little, as Stuart Hampshire averred. Since it is unlikely that, sans physicality, one could distin- guish oneself from anything else, it is difficult to imagine how one would go about identifying oneself as a self at all.30 For Personalists, as with thinkers in other fields, bodily instan- tiation holds a special place in their conversations. It is, of course, vitally important to moral thinking, including that undertaken within these pages. It is difficult to imagine what point or purpose ethics might have if our actions made no practical impact on oth- ers.31 Equally, as Juan Manuel Burgos suggests, below, embodi- ment is an integral element of a sound epistemology.32 As one might expect, however, the precise nature of the connection be- tween persons and their physicality remains moot. Some, like R. T. Allen, resist the slightest hint of entailment relations; and, perhaps for the Christian philosopher, one can perfectly well understand why.33 Others appear to draw the connection tighter, insisting that the “human person is totally unthinkable without the body.”34 We should be wary of drawing the connection too tight, howev- er, lest we over-strain the logic of “personhood” and open the way to the very depersonalising forces we set out to combat. We expect too much of our bodily encounters when we demand they deliver, unerringly and with absolute certainty, the person hopefully em- bodied. Such certainty is not the province of our empirical or expe- riential encounters. A single contrary instance and the entire con- struct is undone. In short, the connection described by the term “embodiment” need not, indeed cannot, be logically necessary. At best, the infer- ence is only presuppositional; that is, not necessary but adequate. An encounter with a body presupposes the presence of a personal agent: the doer of the deed. Likewise, an encounter with persons presupposes an experience of personal acts bodied forth in some-

Introduction 19

way. Each one, person and embodiment, is the minimum condi- tion needed to make sense of the other.35 Besides the risk of defaulting on the logic of “personhood,” any attempt to make watertight the inference from body to person raises the spectre of a still more pernicious form of reductivism. If our primary experience is of the body, then the empirically minded will doubtless want to know what need have we of any inference to the personal at all. “The body is… the physical, organic or material dimension of the person. My hands, my feet, my heart have a measure, a volume profile and a size;” so Burgos reminds us; and who would deny it? Why, then, those empirical minds will wonder, must we complicate matters with these additional and, apparently unnecessary, metaphysical entities? Is the physicality we have be- fore us not sufficient? It is, after all, the only thing we have any hope of getting into our objective sights. Should we, at this point, attempt to separate personality from the body, the empirical oper- ation will be all the easier. Suspected of trying to raise the ghost of Descartes’ ego-isolationism, we shall find ourselves ridiculed for our superstition; or at least, in the words of one who appreciated his ghost stories, invited to save up our nursery tales for a season or two and frighten our cook-maids at the appropriate time.36 Once upon a time, the next step might have been that philo- sophical behaviourism, which P. F. Strawson described as a kind of inverted or paradoxical Cartesianism: “a dualism of one subject – the body – and one non-subject.”37 Dubbing it the “no ownership doctrine of the self,”38 Strawson’s response went straight to the heart of the matter. The philosophical behaviourist, or no- ownership doctrinaire, is in no position to explain either what per- sonal pronouns are for or how they came about. They cannot, in short, tell us what the word “your” is doing in the phrase “your acts.” And they cannot claim that such phrases are simply mean- ingless; ask whether it is your cup of tea, your turn to do the wash- ing up, your fault that the dog ate my Spanish teacher, and we all know perfectly well what is meant. Ownership is inquired about and, in the end, assigned, not to a body, nor any other physical object, but to the person instantiated thereby.

20 Introduction

Today, of course, the sciences dominate both popular and scholarly discussion of such matters. Under the circumstances, philosophical behaviourism is unlikely to be the obvious port of call it once was. Modern empiricists appear to have learned an important theological lesson; our prating of machine-dwelling ghosts aside, it seems that Personalism, like , “adds nothing to .” Quite so, comes the reply, and let that be an end to it.39 Must the Personalist surrender the ground so easily then? Given the fact that the materialist case is itself hardly intelligible, perhaps not. Here too, there is a kind of Cartesianism at work, a dualism of one subject and one non-subject. In this instance, however, the subject is not the body but the materialist herself, while the non- subject is the whole vast sweep of creation. In other words, the materialist must, if she is serious, suppose herself to be a subject, a personal agent, of precisely the kind which she denies exists. This is a direct consequence of her (alleged) materialism and the con- comitant denial of personality. For if creation is made up exclu- sively of physical forces impacting on one another then so too is the personal agency which seeks to describe creation exclusively in terms of physical forces; if personal agency is an illusion, then so too is the personal agency that tells us so. To mitigate the risk of self-contradiction, the materialist must discount herself from the list of things constituted exclusively by physical forces, that is, from the world. The difficulties which beset the resulting “god’s eye view” are many and notorious; not least, of course, it offers the inquirer a view from no place in space or time, from nowhere at all, in fact.40 In effect, the materialist hasn’t eliminated personal agency as she supposes; she has merely removed it from the system of nature. By doing so, materialism transforms personal agency and the mean- ingfulness of its actions into an epiphenomenon. And epiphenom- enalism, Farrer reminds us, is a blind alley: it refutes the question to which it is supposed to be an answer. Indeed, epiphenomenal- ism “counters the whole assumption of logical study, by denying that meaning governs the formation of discourse.”41 Meaningful

Introduction 21

discourse cannot be a mere supervenient quality of physical forces colliding. If it were, we would have no notion of the personality that the materialist denies. Otherwise put, the meaning of the ma- terialist claim cannot be a mere by-product of the sounds and symbols in which it is expressed. Deny this, said Farrer, and we are “maintaining a paradox.” That, if we may be so bold, is an under- statement. Given that the materialist leaves us unable to explain ourselves or anything else, “outright self-contradiction” might be more appropriate. Indeed, the very scientific thinking which seeks to explain how we came to be the kind of creatures we are is fatally undermined by such a view. Take evolutionary biology, for example: Homo sapiens are understood to be a product of natural, evolutionary forces. Conceived as an epiphenomenon, the personal agency which describes those forces is isolated from them, it does not belong to this evolving world. Under the circumstances, personali- ty can have no “survival value,” no “natural utility.” Without “natu- ral utility,” however, neither is there natural explanation. Since personal agency adds nothing to our evolutionary development, it can only be a “treat” bestowed upon us by evolution, a notion which explicitly contradicts the whole science of evolution. “Sur- vival values,” Farrer pointed out, “flourish in an impersonal world; but we must personify Nature with a vengeance, before we can begin to think that anything is more likely to happen because it is a treat.” If, as it seems personification is the order of the day, perhaps personality itself is a gift from someone else; perhaps that is the real lesson of evolutionary biology. The upshot of this is, echoing Strawson, that the materialist, like the behaviourist, cannot explain the meaning and function of personal pronouns, no more than she can explain the personal activity which constitutes her own explorations and explanations. This does not, of course, mean that we deny the immense value and importance of scientific description; we should not wish to be thought so hidebound as that. We merely note the limitations of

22 Introduction

such descriptions and so avoid restricting our analysis and under- standing of persons. We should not, after all, wish to find ourselves in the position of one who says “of a machine whose function one does not appreciate, that all it does is to generate a little heat by friction.”42 Such a view is, as G. C. Stead remarked, “understanda- ble, but may be misleading. It will not do to say that a roulette- wheel is really a kind of stove.” If the tenor of our observations thus far has seemed negative, this is, perhaps, not entirely surprising. Our aim has been to show the anti-reductive ambitions that motivate much Personalist thought and, in doing so, offer the reader some sense of its role as a badly needed corrective to much modern thinking. In Feuer- bachian vein, one function of Personalism may be to act as a ther- apeutic to the objectifying and depersonalising tendencies of Western philosophy and theology.43 Nevertheless, perhaps it is time we offered something more positive in the way of person-talk, something more constructive, for that too is a frequent character- istic of Personalism. Our aim, when we foregather, is not – or not entirely – to beat one another about the head and neck with our philosophies; it is to learn from one another. To briefly recap, then, Personalists commonly reject the notion that persons may be understood as pure reason, sheer noesis; no more, for that matter, than they can be pure spirit. (It is worth re- membering that the bumptious reasoning entailed by inflationary makes for quite as bad philosophy as any reductiv- ism.) We have said that the bodily is a vital dimension of person- hood, “the first manifestation of the person;”44 equally, we stand shoulder to shoulder with Burgos when he tells us that personal embodiment cannot be merely physical. Otherwise put, the im- portance of the bodily to our self-conceptions cannot be due to its sheer materiality any more than to its mere solidity.45 The notion of “body,” pure and simple, a physical thing with which we are presented, remains inert and, therefore, unable to supply a robust criterion of identity. Our knowledge of what it is would depend entirely on how it appears, how we perceive it. But

Introduction 23

appearances are not reliable, as everyone knows. We have all seen far too many car chases on television and planets being destroyed in the cinema to fall for that. Fortunately, the body is not inert matter, as those still unaccountably wedded to Newton’s billiard room physics would have us believe. Like everything else in the , our bodies are made up of interpenetrating patterns of energy or activity; the interplay of forces which constitutes the cosmos, constitutes us likewise. Carl Sagan was right, “[t]he cos- mos is… within us; we are made of star-stuff.”46 So much, Einstein told us a century ago, a cosmic shift in thinking, which both Whitehead and Farrer eagerly appropriated in their development of a modern (anti-metaphysical) metaphysics. The crucial differ- ence of course, is that the patterns of activity which constitute our bodies are not only physical, i.e. causal; they are also, and most importantly, personal, i.e. intentional. We have already suggested that action will be essential to our understanding of “personhood.” That is, action in the proper sense, the full and personal sense: acts owned and authored; acts intended, deliberately executed; acts that carry those intentions and deliberations, that carry meaning, just as these words, this communicative act, carries meaning. Such acts, indeed, are the primary manifestation of “personhood.” For, in personal action, we find the much coveted criterion of identity. It is by their acts that we learn to distinguish our friends from statues and shop manikins, not to mention evil twins and even more evil robot rep- licants. Persons are known by their fruits, by what they do, both to oth- ers and to themselves. I may come to know both that you are a person (as opposed to an evil robot doppelganger) and what kind of person you are by the ways in which you choose to interact with me. Will it be constructive and creative or destructive and deper- sonalising? Equally, I come to know myself in the same way, through those same interactions. It is, of course, a commonplace that personalities are shaped and molded by others in their envi- ronment; but just as important are the ways in which that person- ality expresses itself, so appropriates its environment. I may, for

24 Introduction

example, regard myself as the very soul of warmth and generosity, a fellow who’s guiding light is peace and goodwill to all living crea- tures. However, should I once begin to reflect on my habit of kick- ing stray dogs and shoving elderly ladies in front of moving cars, I will be forced to acknowledge the inaccuracy of my self- assessment, the dire limitations of my self-knowledge. More important than my own reflections, however, are the self- reflections that others offer me; not just how I act, but how my actions are understood, recognised, responded to, these are the vital clues to my identity. Our actions, that is, are ordinarily public, performed for an au- dience. Whether we appreciate it or not, this carries an obligation to reckon with the impact we have on others. If we are sensitive, we think before we act, anticipating consequences in the hopes of learning a lesson the easy way. We may listen to ourselves before speaking or, more commonly, reprise our actions through what Charles Conti describes as our “moral ‘playback’ function.”47 Reg- istering aftershock in the face of the other, I seek to make amends, to reinterpret and resubmit my actions for further review. I hope, in short, to qualify my intentions, so mitigate unintended effects. These are the lessons we re-invest in our self-enactments. In so doing, as Conti elegantly puts it, “[w]e gather the rosebuds of expe- rience so as to remove the thorns of further disgrace.” We live our lives in the garden of other people’s hearts and so must learn to watch where we put our big, flat feet. In future, I shall intend my act-consequences with greater care. By acts of oversight and over- seeing, we reveal ourselves, our true nature; more, we become the selves we hope to be: “[w]e perform our being as we experience it.” Philosophically speaking, we participate in the transformative dia- lectics of self and other; passing ourselves through the mirror of some other, we embark upon the development of our own selves. In locating our criterion identity, we begin to see the full import of Robert Spaemann’s words; the central question of his Persons: The Difference Between “Someone” and “Something” is not “What is a person?” but “Who is a person?”48

Introduction 25

At first blush, the answer seems obvious. Surely, I have it, if not actually at my fingertips, then just beyond them. To identify a per- son, I need only point to whoever is sitting next to me on the train or on the other side of the dinner table. If such ill-mannered be- haviour does not satisfy, we might adopt a mode more figurative and “point” to you, the reader, by referring to you here and now. Implied in this act of communication is the presupposition that you are a person like me; someone sufficiently well-equipped to reciprocate with whatever it is that makes a person a person; at the very least, some reflective and self-reflective capacity. But in answering that apparently trivial question, how many more profound ones suddenly arise? How do I know you are a per- son? For that matter, how do I know I am one? If I am a person, how did I get to be one in the first place? These are the questions we are beginning to ask when we ask “who is a person?” From the little acorn of one, seemingly simple question, a profoundly im- portant metaphysical, moral, and existential oak tree grows. Pro- foundly important because it concerns much more than the ways in which we understand ourselves; it concerns the ways in which we become the selves we are. Taking the first question, “how do I know you are a person?”, those who would insist upon isolated interiority for the real sub- ject, the utterly unknown “I” at the centre of our selves, have no answer to give.49 (Out of respect for Mark Smith’s reappraisal of Descartes, below, it seems only fair to leave the French philoso- pher out of it, at least until the reader has had the opportunity to judge for him or herself.) Others have attempted to throw an ana- logical bridge across the gap between self and other. Of course, one might be very wary indeed of crossing so insubstantial a struc- ture. After all, how can we be sure that there will be anything on the other side? Our bridge might prove to be, as James Joyce quipped, nothing but a pier, and a very short pier at that.50 Unfor- tunately, the evidence of another inside can only be judged by ex- ternal criteria. I know you are a person like me because you behave like me: you appear to be like me, therefore you are like me. Evi-

26 Introduction

dently, the conclusion does not follow at all and we are left facing, once again, the brainless bio-mechanical brute of behaviorism. Surely, this will not do. The sceptic who questions the efficacy of the analogy may have a point, as far as he goes; but once he has reached the end of this “disappointed bridge,” he has nowhere to go. Perhaps he has asked the wrong question. Perhaps the ques- tion is not “how do we know that the analogy applies?” but “where did the analogy come from in the first place?” Shifting the inflection, let us reappraise our first question. How do I know you are a person? And that raises the second: for that matter, how do I know that I am one? In other words, if I know what persons are like from my own case, then I must ask where my own case comes from. Logically minded readers will surely point out that we know the answer to that perfectly well. The likes of Strawson and Wittgen- stein long ago revealed to us the primary conditions for self- identification within those who taught us how to do it and what it means. Another puzzle for the hardened materialist: not only must she exile herself from the universe of merely physical forces; it seems she must also exile all those who taught her. The very lan- guage in which she frames her scientific scepticism is a legacy of those who taught her how to speak and, insofar as she does, how to think. Thus, the argument from analogy is really an argument back to those who taught us how to be persons in the first place. There is, of course, more to life than logic. Let us heed Farrer’s timely reminder instead: “[i]t is not as though we believed in our neighbour’s personality because logical philosophers are able to exhibit the self-contradiction involved in denying it.”51 Indeed not. Other persons are not a puzzle to be solved by rational or scientific minds. They are a practical matter; and an urgent one too, given that, from our very first breath, we are entirely dependent upon them. In Macmurray’s words, we are “‘adapted’…to being una- dapted,” that is, “‘adapted’ to a complete dependence” on others.52 Farrer (who was a student of Macmurray’s at Balliol) concurred, adding, “[f]rom first infancy our elders loved us, played us, served

Introduction 27

us and talked us into knowing them.” To such, literally, personify- ing transactions we are very well “adapted,” perfectly so. We are, as Macmurray says, “made to be cared for;” and cared for we must be if we are to survive. From this, it follows that there is really no need for arguments and analogies to the other hidden away inside. For those who “talked us into knowing them” permeate and saturate our every experience of personhood. By their grace and gift do we become the persons we are. Deny the transformative transactions embod- ied by those gifts and we embrace, not reasonable doubt, but stul- tifying scepticism; we are, not persons, only “mindless imbe- ciles…innocent of all communication.” Most of us, fortunately, do not remain either innocent or utterly dependent on others for very long. The parents of teenage children might disagree vehemently with the second half of this suggestion; however, even they must admit that it usually takes a child only a few, short years to master the basics. Efforts to learn how to walk and talk and think usually bear at least some fruit before a child is five years old. Getting food from a plate into one’s mouth without spreading it all over one’s face appears to take a little longer, as anyone who has eaten with a philosopher may attest. Growing older, the content of these dialectical transactions inevitably changes, just as the people who join us in them inevitably change. In their essentials, however, in their shape and structure, the dia- lectic pursues the same fundamental course.53 Others continue to contribute to our development throughout our lives, if we are clev- er enough to allow them to. They teach us about ourselves and our world and, perhaps most importantly, how to learn about our- selves and our world. Many are those who have, at one time or another, left their mark on your editors’ philosophical and person- al development. Most exciting, perhaps, in being taught to participate in our own development, we are simultaneously taught how to partici- pate in the development of others. This marks the most significant shift in the psychodynamic interplay of personhood: our active

28 Introduction

appropriation and embodiment of it. Creative participation in the becoming of others: quite possibly the acme of personal acts. In- deed, what could be more characteristically personal? For some, it is the meaning of “personhood” itself. For others, such as Buford, despite appearing to be innate, it is, in fact, our “second nature;”54 second and better. And in such creative participations we find a healthy and constructive philosophical psychology, one by which persons may understand themselves and their world in all its rich- ness and depth. It is a way of thinking and talking about persons that does not rely on those psychologies incapable of expressing themselves in except in the most antediluvian of polarities: matter and (non)spirit; mind and body; perhaps worst of all, us and them. Ultimately, that is why we shall resist to the last ditch reductivism in all its forms, materialist, rationalist, economic, and political. Finally, and at very, very long last, it is in an effort to honour that philosophical psychology that your editors offer their pro- found thanks to all those who have been involved in this volume. To our authors, of course; and to those who work tirelessly to en- sure that the International Conference on Persons continues to be a place where such creative participations and everyone who un- dertakes them can blossom, we are grateful. And that, dear reader, is all the song we have to sing.

Acknowledgements

In addition to the somewhat vague sentiments above, the editors would like to thank all those who contributed to the crafting and shaping of this volume. To Thomas O. Buford, John F. Hofbauer, and Orla Smith, in particular, we are grateful for sage advice and ever-helpful suggestions. To the organising committee of the In- ternational Conference on Persons, we are deeply indebted, not only for organising the conference which brought us all together in the first place, but also for their support during the preparation of this book and, most especially, for granting us the opportunity to put it together. They are: Randall E. Auxier, Jan Olof Bengtsson, Thomas O. Buford (again), Ralph Ellis, Richard C. Prust, Robert C. Neville, and Kevin C. Keith.

Chapter 1 Personal Identity With and Without Monotheism

Richard C. Prust

Historically, identity as an individual person is a creature of west- ern monotheism; and since we no longer appeal to monotheism explicitly in moral and legal reasoning, the practice of identifying persons (rather than identifying vital somebodies) has become suspect for people who think systematically about human behav- ior. This poses a problem for societies that purport to be person- respecting, particularly because identifying persons is crucial in moral and legal reasoning. Accordingly, in the interests of defend- ing the judgments we make about persons as reasonable we are obliged either to defend a monotheistic grounding for identity or provide a reasonable account of identifying persons on a non- monotheistic basis. In this essay I propose to do both. With or without monotheism, I will try to show that it makes sense to iden- tify persons as individual characters of resolve. What belief in mon- otheism contributes, and what seems to be unavailable on other grounds, is a basis for believing in moral integrity, in its conceiva- bility, its actuality, and its attainability. Without that belief, the actual being of persons gets systematically diminished in a variety of ways, three of which I will discuss: first, without belief in the attainability of moral integrity, it becomes riskier to trust others; second, without that belief, calling another person by name evokes only the presence of his compromised active being; and third, without that belief, what persons do has less historical importance. Few who attended the International Conference on Persons in Boston will think me presumptuous for insisting that there must

32 Personal Identity With and Without Monotheism

be a reasonable way to identify persons. But we are also aware that “personal identity” is thought to be an incoherent conceit by many. The reigning consensus seems to be that there is no rational way to determine the being of a “person.” At very least that means there is no rational way to determine which of somebody’s actions are actions for which he takes personal responsibility. As far as I know, no British analytic account of identity has proven useful for moral or legal purposes and continental thinkers celebrate the contingency of meaning in a way that makes any claim about iden- tity, personal or impersonal, naïve. But these ways of dismissing personal identity share a faulty as- sumption that, for anyone interested in moral and legal reasoning, should seem suspect from the start. They all take on the challenge of identifying a person as one of determining what set of experi- ences properly counts as his. What should make us suspicious about this assumption is that in legal and moral matters the range of a person’s experiences is less relevant to who he is than the range of actions for which he bears personal responsibility. In forensic matters we identify persons according to what they do, not what they experience; specifically, I would argue, we identify and judge them as characters of resolute action. When we re-frame the challenge of identifying a person as one of characterizing somebody’s acts instead of categorizing his expe- riences, I believe we make the notion of personal identity not only coherent but relevant to forensic purposes. (Indeed, I would argue – though I cannot do so here – that characterizing somebody’s re- solve does the only thing necessary in those contexts: it determines the range of somebody’s personal responsibility.) Identifying a person by characterizing somebody’s agency ra- ther than by delimiting his experience can only make sense if our characterization somehow covers a multitude of actions. After all, as a person you are an individual, but you are not presently sitting there simply as a hearer or a reader of this paper. Who you are also includes an ongoing range of engagements, projects and relation- ships. You could, I am sure, rattle off dozens of undertakings that

Personal Identity With and Without Monotheism 33

you have begun in the past but have not yet completed. All of them are part of who you presently are, all of them elements in your active presence. Accordingly, any characterization able to identify you personally would have to have implicit in it at least some of the items on your present-tense list. This poses a formal question: how can a set of characterizations depicting somebody’s present ac- tions (plural) conceivably characterize an individual (singular) agent. The answer becomes evident when we consider what such a list of your undertakings, however complete, would not convey about you. The old way of trying to distinguish a person as a set of experi- ences would presumably allow for a “list” of his experiences to stand as his personal identity, but it is easy to see that a mere list of your actions would not tell us who you are. There must also be something adverbially true of your actions if they are to sustain your personhood: they must be manifestly projected to accommo- date one another. You are, after all, using your imagination to steer a course in which the various things you are doing are projected so as to allow for their mutual accommodation; in short you are form- ing resolve. The imaginative act of forming resolve involves something like making up a story, a story of how our actions going forward are going to resolve our intentional life. Our aim in narrating our un- dertakings, however sketchily, is to draw them into coordination, into narrative coherence. That seems to be what enables the mul- tiplicity of somebody’s intentions to enjoy the unity required for personal individuality. As a purely practical matter, since we are multi-intentioned agents (there being multiple items on our list of present undertakings) it is reasonable to think that our being is actualized most when we achieve the most comprehensive resolu- tion we can imagine. Our most self-actualizing personal story – our most intention-satisfying life – is the one that best coordinates our intentional life as a whole. That makes each of us the protagonist of a course of resolve that promises to integrate him better than any of the alternatives he can imagine.

34 Personal Identity With and Without Monotheism

I realize this is an extremely austere and underdeveloped ac- count of personal identity but it is enough for our purposes here. In identifying a person as the present character of somebody’s resolve we have what we need to determine which of his actions count as his for moral and legal purposes: a person’s actions are all and only the actions determined in character by his resolve. In any case, that is the understanding of personal identity this analysis depends upon so I hope it gains plausibility for you as our discus- sion proceeds. I said earlier that what distinguishes a monotheist’s from a non- monotheist’s understanding of personal identity is that the former determines the possibility that anyone can (conceivably) have moral integrity. Integrity would take the form of a complete resolu- tion of somebody’s intentional life. For that integrity to be moral integrity, it would have to be the case that in leading her life of integrity she always accords with the best interests of the persons she interacts with. I suggested earlier that this notion of moral integrity emerged in the West in the context of monotheistic stories and that this fact makes it suspect in the eyes of many people who try to understand human behavior. But it would be premature to give up on it be- cause of where it came from without seeing what it meant formally in that context. proves formally antithetical to individ- uality (as a character of resolve) because the presence of multiple each of whom has a claim on somebody puts him under in- compatible obligations. That precludes a singularity of intentional bearing from emerging in the way he projects his intentional life. When a protagonist of an ancient tragedy steps forth from the cho- rus as a pretender to identifiable character he is always dissolved, ritually torn apart as an agent and sacrificed on the altar of Diony- sus. Monotheism, in contrast, imposes one consistent and coherent obligation, that of pursuing God’s agenda in the world. In its founding texts the stories about individual characters of resolve emerged in stories about people coordinating their lives in a di-

Personal Identity With and Without Monotheism 35

vine-human partnership. The matrix of human individuality as a character of action was contextualized in this partnership, so per- sons can only be narratively identified as bearing a relationship between personal stories. To get clarity on why persons are intrinsically relational, we need to notice how human personal-resolve stories are related to the divine Story in which God’s action was characterized. There are three features of that relationship that are important for under- standing the meaning of moral integrity. First, among monotheistic Storytellers, anybody could be re- solved as a person in partnership with God. Second, to be in partnership with God means to be wholly re- solved, resolved in such a way that no part of one’s intentional life moves in discord with any other. It is interesting to note that in the dawn of personal individuality, which is to say in the dawn of Sto- rytelling (and storytelling), the individual human person partner- ing with God was the corporate person Israel. Wholeness in that first human person’s intentional life meant coordination among the tribes and classes who made up Israel. When Israel the corpo- rate person was obedient in her partnership with God, she was whole/holy in her corporate life: the poor were taken care of, hos- pitality was practiced, the tribes cooperated, the rituals were pure, etc. When she became disobedient she disintegrated: falling in battle, suffering under corrupt kings and wayward priests, endur- ing strife between rich and poor, etc. But – and this is the crucial point for our purposes – the possibility of a return to whole/holiness was always present, even in her periods of disobe- dience and disintegration. Or, more formally put, it was under- stood to be implicit in Israel’s present narrative possibilities that she could return to advancing the Story and be made whole as a people again. Later in Israel’s history and still later in the Christian Storytell- ing that developed out of it, personal integrity was actualized in two ways, as the complete coordination of somebody’s intentional

36 Personal Identity With and Without Monotheism

life, typically spoken of as “grace,” and as communal integrity, a “fellowship of believers.” This brings us to the third birthmark of personhood: these two modes of integrity, the personal and the inter-personal, can only be actualized together. That is to say, persons who emerged in mono- theistic stories as whole/holy also emerged as interpersonally healthy. Assuming that healthy relationships constitute moral ones, monotheistically identified persons enjoy (as part of what it means for them to be a person) the hope of actualizing moral in- tegrity with others. To put the matter negatively, persons are iden- tified in a way that makes it inconceivable for a person of integrity to exploit others. Now then, if I am right in seeing the notion of an individual person as the offshoot of monotheistic Storytelling and moral in- tegrity as hard-baked into monotheistically-identified persons, then a loss of belief in monotheism threatens people’s confidence in the human possibility of moral integrity. One could greet such news with a shrug. Why should it matter whether moral integrity is understood to be within a person’s narrative possibilities? In the remainder of this essay I want to suggest several ways it does. If moral integrity drops out as a human possibility, first, it becomes riskier to trust people, second, calling them by name is drained of moral meaning, and, third, there is diminished historical signifi- cance for what we do. Consider first the matter of trusting people. On what grounds should I trust you? Surely part of the answer is the very nature of healthy interactions. Even the most impersonal of them has a fidu- ciary component in as much (barring the unforeseen) we have to trust those we interact with to persist with us until we finish doing what we are doing. Of course when an interaction is personal there is normally more at stake since the betrayal of personal trust in- flicts more damage to the betrayed party. This is actual damage since part of his intentional life will have been rendered unsatis- fied and, at least for the present, unsatisfiable. That is why when one partner breaks trust the other typically feels “crushed,” “let

Personal Identity With and Without Monotheism 37

down,” “brought low,” “depressed” and “deflated,” all these terms recording an active awareness of being diminished in the range of movement characterized by one’s resolve. With so much at stake we learn to be careful about trusting people. We ponder whether we know somebody well enough to vouch for his stability and we reflect on previous interactions to consider whether they all manifest his good will toward us. But our risk assessment depends on something else too. It depends on whether we have to allow for the fact that someday he might have to exploit us for the sake of his own greatest self-actualization. Imagine a situation where Jones, Smith’s long-time friend, asks Smith for a large un-secured loan to help him build a retirement home in a far-away country with no extradition treaties. Smith has known Jones long enough to be confident that he bears him good will and sincerely intends to pay him back. But would it be reason- able for Smith to trust that Jones will always remain loyal? If Smith cannot assume that moral integrity is possible for Jones – whether because the idea just doesn’t make sense to him or because he thinks it’s a wistful conceit – then he has to allow for the possibility that someday Jones, in order to sustain his own greatest intentional satisfaction, may have to be disloyal. Even if Jones has been a faithful friend for years, not only does that not guarantee he won’t have to betray Smith someday, it isn’t even a very strong reason for believing that he won’t. It being a natural obligation for any multi-intentioned agent to project his action in the most intention-satisfying way, no personal obligation could conceivably stand in his way if Jones found it expedient to renege on the loan and turn their relationship unhealthy. And if that hap- pened, Smith could hardly blame him. As a self-actualizing charac- ter of resolve himself, he knows he would do the same or more if his greatest intentional satisfaction required it. But if Smith was confident in the ever-present possibility of Jones’s moral integrity, confident that Jones’s path to greatest self- actualization could never require him to turn his relationship with Smith unhealthy, the basis for trust would be enhanced. The risk

38 Personal Identity With and Without Monotheism

does not entirely dissipate since it is always possible for Jones to fail to grasp his best interests and betray Smith out of bad judg- ment. But Smith can be confident that Jones will never have to do so in order to achieve the most satisfying resolution for his inten- tional life. If moral integrity is every person’s narrative possibility then treachery can never determine his most satisfying course. The second way a loss of belief in moral integrity would dimin- ish us personally has to do with the way we use a person’s name. To be addressed by name, even impersonally, is to be initiated into an interaction. (“Listen to me, Jay! “The doctor will see you now, Kay.” “Take a seat, Bea.” “Hey, You, get off my lawn.”) It is to be invited to move in some course of action the addresser has in mind (like lending an attentive ear, taking a seat, rising and following, or fleeing never to return). When an interaction is impersonal (like the examples here), it engages the parties in a discrete and immediate undertaking but presumably nothing more. When it is personal, it represents two courses of resolve engaging one another. Consider, in this frame of reference, how the possibility of per- sonal integrity affects the way we initiate personal interactions. According to the monotheistic construction of personhood, every person has the capacity (which is to say the narrative capacity) to lead a life of wholeness and relational health. That means that for every person there is a character of resolve, distinctively hers, wherein this holy/whole/interactively healthy life could be actual- ized thereby constituting her greatest self-actualization. Accord- ingly, when a believer in moral integrity addresses another person by name he addresses him not only as a story that patches together his compromised life but as a distinctive character of moral integ- rity that also signifies his present possibility. This duplexity in what a personal name names has been made explicit in various ways throughout the reign of biblical monothe- ism. We hear it in the second names of characters called by God for a particular task (Abram/Abraham, Simon/Peter), in the “Chris- tian” name people are baptized with when it reflects a saintly life, a

Personal Identity With and Without Monotheism 39

Storied character perhaps or a peculiar virtue of . We hear it in the Pauline and Augustinian descriptions of our present being as simul justus et peccator. This evocation of a person’s possible integrity, which rings in the addressing of another by name, falls away when one becomes skeptical about moral integrity. Then one neither hears nor gives voice to any summons to actualize some more momentous pre- sent possibility. To put it in Luther’s terms, being “called” by name can no longer mean being summoned to a “vocation.” Many today would insist that this ship has already sailed, that whatever historical grounding this practice may have had, it has been largely abandoned. But I would contend that the evocative force of calling another by his personal name is by no means dead in present-day sensibilities. We “appeal” to one another in a spe- cial, moral way when we appeal by name. Think of all the people who report that Mom always called them by their nicknames ex- cept when they were in trouble. They heard a summons to moral behavior loud and clear. Finally, without belief in moral integrity the historical signifi- cance of what a person does would be systematically diminished. We have hinted at how personal partnerships represent the char- acter of one person’s resolve inflecting another’s movements inter- actively. This of course can be for good or ill; the inflection can enhance or deplete the other’s success. But there is another di- mension in which the character of somebody’s resolve actualizes moments of intentional satisfaction beyond itself and that is in the lives of successors who have found their narrative capacities en- hanced because of what they did. When people say that the legacy of Martin Luther King “lives on” they are saying that his resolve continues to characterize some of what people do now. King doesn’t just “live on in their memories.” His resolve continues to coordinate their movement, their way of doing things, in certain venues. That is why celebrants of his life memorialize him by doing something King-like on MLK Day. King’s life (i.e., King) can thus be said to have personal historical importance according to how his

40 Personal Identity With and Without Monotheism

character of resolve inflects the character of our contemporaries’ actions for their good. One thing more needs to be noted about the meaning King’s ac- tion had for him. Because it was predicated on the telling of a Story it was predicated on the possibility of moral integrity. King’s short- hand version of that divine Story of achieving moral integrity was that “the arc of the moral universe is long but it bends toward jus- tice.” We should not lose sight of the fact that the accomplishment of that “bending toward justice” puts King’s work and the work of people who work in his name into the context of a transcendent accomplishment of moral integrity, what monotheism recognizes as a divine accomplishment, the accomplishment the Character of Resolve they call “God.” Without being able to frame their life by that agenda, human lives can find historical import only on a more modest and mundane scale. Lacking in the ultimate significance of the arc-bending accomplishment King had in mind, they could not dwell its transcending moment. Thus, for want of this blessing they are diminished. I have been arguing that people naturally strive to self-identify as an individual character of resolve, i.e., as a person, because that is the most effective way to self-actualize for any multi-intentioned agent. Whether integrating one’s life in the most intention- satisfying way always takes a healthy turn with others is a matter we can judge for ourselves. Furthermore, I have tried to show that it is important to do so: if we determine that moral integrity is pos- sible we can trust one another more completely, be morally evoca- tive in addressing one another by name, and take comfort in an ultimate significance for at least some of what we do.

PAGES MISSING

FROM THIS FREE SAMPLE

Index

A nihilo nihil fit, 116 Annihilation, 321 Able-bodiedness, 223 Anselm, 300 Able-mindedness, 223 Anthropocentric, 58, 59 Abortion, 163, 164, 165, 166, Anthropology, 94 169, 170, 172, 173 Anti-foundationalism, 115 Abortion rights, 164, 169 Anti-metaphysics, 286 Absolute, 109, 110, 115, 299 Antispinozism, 112 Absolute negativity, 296 Antonio Gramsci, 221 Absorption, 143 Apatheia, 289 Abstract, 101, 102, 110, 115, Apeiron, 295 296, 310 Apragmosyne, 289 Abyss, 99, 106, 109, 111, 112, Aquainas, T., 300 115, 315 Aristotle, 94, 99, 198, 221 Accidental, 291, 320 Arndt, 299, 302, 315, 317 Acosmism, 115 Asmuth, 302, 310 Action, 15, 21 Ataraxia, 289 Actor Network Theory, 58 , 100, 101, 104, 105, Adaequatio, 108 107, 115, 280, 291, 300, Adams, 280 301, 309 Adiaphora, 289 Atom, 111 Ahlers, 279, 299, 302, 320 Atone, 199, 201, 205, 208 Alcoff, Linda Martin, 225 Atonement, 197, 199, 207, Al-Ghazzali, 177, 179, 180, 209, 210, 346, 347 181, 183, 184, 185, 338, Attachment, 119, 121, 122, 339, 340 123 Alienation, 212 Audre Lorde, 222 Allen, R. T., 13, 16, 261, 264, Augustine, 177, 179, 180, 185, 266, 267 300, 340, 341, 342 Alzheimer's, 149 Auschwitz, 278 Americans with Disabilities Austin, J. L., 11, 12, 15, 261, Act, 226 262, 263, 265, 266, 268 Anglican, 142

368 Index

Awards. See honors, See Bowne, B. P., 47, 48, 49, 50, honors, See honors, See 51, 52, 270, 271 honors Bradshaw, 315 Axiology, 57, 63 Brandom, 306 Bad, 324 Brinkmann, 278 Bad infinite, 139 Bruno, 112, 321 Bader, 297 Bryan Turner, 239 Baier, 79, 80, 81, 83, 90, 274, , 304 275 Buford, Thomas O., 7, 8, 26, Bardili, 292 261, 265, 268, 269 Bartuschat, 325 Burnyeat, 297 Bataille, 310 Büttner, 316 Baum, 307, 315, 326 Calvin, 300 Becoming, 295, 296, 310, 319 Capacities, 108 Begierde, 287 Cartesianism, 131 Begriff, 109 Cause, 106, 114 Behaviourism, 17, 93 Center for Independent Being, 102, 110, 295, 296, 308, Living, 233 310 Centripetal, 111 Beneficiaries, 211, 212, 215, Certainty, 95, 99, 108, 110, 219 288, 289 Beneficiary, 63 Chorismos, 296, 315, 316 Berthold-Bond, 327 Christendom, 142 Bible, 94, 107, 288 Christianity, 137, 304 Bipolar disorder, 222 Churchill, 94 Body, 94, 101, 111 Churchland, 281 , 177, 178, 179, 180, Clayton, 295, 307 187, 337, 338, 340, 341, Cobben, 279 342, 343 Cognitive authority, 222 Bondeli, 278 Coincidentia, 291 Boredom, 114 Compatibilism, 86, 87 Bosanquet, B., 132, 140, 141, Composite, 111 142, 143, 144, 145, 146, Concept, 106, 111, 296 147, 148, 150, 331, 332, Concrete, 101, 102 333 Condition, 99, 288 Bowman, 297, 326 Conditional, 291 Conditioned, 109

Index 369

Confession, 185, 186 Denker, 310 Consciousness, 134, 145 Depression, 227 Consolation, 178, 191 Descartes, R., 79, 113, 133, Constitution, 165, 167, 171, 289, 294, 297 335 Descartes, Rene, 17, 23, 261, Conti, Charles, 7, 22, 265, 262 266, 267 Desire, 287 Contingency, 114, 320 Destiny, 288 Contradiction, 93, 99, 103, Destruction, 111, 112, 315 109, 111, 112, 114, 115, Determinacy, 115 116, 288, 305, 308, 316 Determinate, 109, 111, 295, Convalescence, 119, 124, 125, 321 126, 127, 128, 129 Determination, 114, 308 Corporations, 243, 245, 249, Deus absconditus, 277 253, 255, 256 Deuser, 314, 321 Correspondence theory of Developmentally challenged, language, 11 149 Creatio ex nihilo, 115, 321 Diagnostic and Statistical Creation, 317, 321 Manual, 224 Creative participation in Dialectic, 115, 287, 314 others, 26 Dickens, Charles, 14, 264 Creativity, 108, 114, 298, 306 Didonai, 290 Crenshaw, 232 Difference, 320 Criterion, 288, 298 DiGiovanni, 281 Culture, 119, 122, 123, 126, Disabilities, 221 128 Disability Studies, 221 Dachau, 279 Disability Theory, 224 Dahlstrom, 278 Divine, 136 Dante, 138 Divine Comedy, 138 De Vos, L., 279, 286, 312 Dogmatic, 100 Death, 110 Doubt, 289 Death- resurrection, 287 Drüe, 317 Decade of Roma Inclusion, DuBois, W. E. B., 229 211, 212, 213, 218, 219, Duff, R. A., 198, 346, 347 354, 355 Duns Scotus, 300 Deconstruction, 105 Duration, 151, 152, 153, 154, Deleuze, 310 159, 160, 161, 162, 334

370 Index

Economic, 300 Experience, 102 Ecstacy, 113 Fact, 108, 308, 315, 325 Education, 214, 217, 218 Faith, 94, 95, 113, 280, 287, Edwards, 300 301 Effect, 113 Falke, 286, 312 Electron, 111 False, 103, 112, 278, 288 Eliot, T. S., 267 Farrer, Austin Marsden, 7, 15, Elisabeth of Bohemia, 81, 83, 16, 18, 19, 21, 24, 262, 263, 85, 86, 87, 89, 275, 276 265, 266, 267, 268 Elisha, 141 Fatalism, 314, 327 Elizabeth Kamarck Minnich, Feeling, 109, 110, 113, 282, 223 318 Embodiment, 16 Ferreira,Phillip, 332 Emotion, 14 Feticide, 163, 168, 169, 170, Enforcement Guidance on 171, 172, 173 the Americans with Feuerbach, Ludwig, 267, 299 Disabilities Act and Fichte, 94, 102, 115, 287, 288, Psychiatric Disabilities, 292, 301, 306, 324 226 , 301 Enlightenment, 94 Fiduciary Trusts, 74 Epiphenomenalism, 18 Finite, 99, 109, 113, 114, 115, Epistemic cooperation, 233 287, 295 Epistemology, 101, 102, 107 Flourishing, 222 Epistemology of ignorance, Fox, Michael Allen, 13, 264 230 Freedom, 93, 94, 99, 107, 108, Equal Employment 109, 110, 111, 113, 114, Opportunities 115, 116, 119, 123, 317 Commission, 226 Freud, 119, 120, 121, 122, , 100 123, 124, 125, 126, 127, Essence, 102, 109 128, 224, 328, 329 Eternity, 116 Friendship, 181, 184, 343 Evil, 93, 247, 279, 280, 362, Gabriel, 291, 294, 297, 315 364, 365 Gawoll, 286, 288, 312 Ex nihilo, 115, 116, 298, 310, Generosity, 86, 88, 90, 91 317, 321 Genesis Problems, 59, 60 Existence, 106 Genetics, 111 Existential, 212, 213, 214, 220 Geometry, 113

Index 371

Gerhard, 286 286, 287, 290, 291, 296, German Idealism, 94, 99, 280, 299, 301, 306, 307, 309, 286, 297, 301, 307, 319 310, 312, 315, 324, 331, Geronides, 315 361, 362, 364, 365 Gethmann-Siefert, 317 Hegelianism and Personality, God, 99, 102, 108, 110, 111, 333 114, 140, 142, 144, 146, Hegemonic, 221 149, 179, 182, 184, 185, Heidemann, 286, 325 186, 188, 278, 309, 331, Hell, 138 333, 339, 341, 342 Hen kai pan, 109 God’s eye view, 18 Henrich, 318 Good, 279, 322 Hess, 299 Goodman, N., 231 Hölderlin, 287, 307 Grace, 108 Holocaust, 93, 279, 280 Graham, 315 Holy, 93, 94 Gregory of Nyssa, 300 Holz, 325, 326 GRIP, 197, 207, 208, 209, 210, Homicide, 164, 168, 171, 172 352, 354 Hönigswald, 113 Ground, 95, 99, 106, 110, 111, Honneth, 310 112, 115, 291 Honors, 187, 190 Habermas, 68, 69, 70, 74, 75, Hühn, 302 76, 77, 272, 273, 310 Husserl, E., 48, 53 Hackenesch, 317 Hysteria, 224 Halbig, 306 Hysterical Neurosis, 224 Hamann, 322 Icarus Project, 233 Hames-Garcia, M, 232 Idea, 109 Hammacher, 281 Idealism, 125, 126, 128 Hampshire, Stuart, 16 Identity, 95, 108, 224, 278, Harm Reduction, 238 307, 319 Hartshorne, 320 Ideology of ability, 222 Heaven, 138, 142 Illies, C., 279 Hegel, G. W. F., 94, 96, 97, 99, Image, 154, 156, 157, 159, 100, 101, 102, 103, 105, 161, 334 110, 111, 112, 113, 115, Immanent, 300 116, 139, 244, 245, 247, Immaterial, 111 248, 249, 250, 255, 256, 257, 260, 278, 279, 280,

372 Index

Immediacy, 95, 102, 103, 106, Jaeschke, W., 281, 286, 299, 109, 110, 298, 299, 312, 305 317 Jagland, T., 216 Immediate, 296 James, W., 10, 15, 63, 261, Immortality, 132, 137, 139, 264, 266, 267, 268 140, 146 Jamme, 280 Impersonalism, 57, 272 Japp, 302 Incapacitation, 194 Jean Paul, 115, 323 Indeterminate, 114, 310, 321, Jesus, 288, 289 326 John Dewey, 232 Indifference, 100, 114, 115, Jonas, 93, 277, 278 288, 289, 296, 307, 319 Jonkers, 286, 312, 316 Individual, 114 Jordan River, 141 Induction, 45, 46, 270 Judaism, 304 Infinite, 95, 99, 113, 114, 115, Judgment, 279, 298 295 Jüngel, 294 Insight Out, 207 Justification, 99, 108, 194, Integral Experience, 39, 40 197, 288, 290, 345 Integration, 211, 212, 213, Kant, I., 43, 44, 50, 93, 96, 214, 217, 218, 219, 220 101, 106, 107, 111, 139, Intellect, 111 277, 297, 306, 315 Intrinsic Values, 57 Kelly, 310 Intuition, 282 Kierkegaard, S., 70, 71, 75 Inverted world, 287 King, M. L., 37, 332 Irenaeus, 300 Knepper, 290 Irony, 105, 302 Knowledge, 40, 45, 113, 287 Irrational, 110, 280, 312 Knowledge of other persons, Islam, 304 23 Israel, 33 Kobusch, 290, 291, 306 Izsák, R., 215 Koran, 94 Jacobi, 94, 95, 96, 97, 99, 100, Krijnen, 286, 325 102, 106, 107, 108, 110, Lacan, J., 310 112, 113, 116, 280, 286, Lamb, H. Richard, 237 287, 290, 291, 292, 297, Law, 112 298, 299, 301, 306, 310, Leap, 99, 111, 115, 287, 324 312, 317, 319, 321 Legal status, 165, 167, 171 Leibniz, 102

Index 373

Leinkauf, 316 Matache, M., 214, 218, 219, Lessing, 108, 314, 325 355, 356 Life, 110, 115, 310 Materialism, 9, 13, 18, 19, 26 Light, 298 McCord, 280 Locke, 133, 134, 135, 136, McWorld, 247, 248, 254, 257, 305, 330, 331 362 Logic, 102, 111, 305 Mediation, 99, 102, 103, 106, Logical Positivism, 11 109, 110 Logon, 290 Medieval scholastics, 131, Logon didonai, 306 133, 138 Lorenz, K., 280 Memory, 155, 156, 157, 158, Loss, 119, 120, 121, 122, 123, 159, 161, 334 124 Mental disabilities, 221 Love, 79, 83, 89, 90, 91, 110, Mentally challenged, 149 121, 122, 123, 127, 328 Metaphysics, 94, 97, 105, 111, Lugones, M., 231 112, 113, 286, 304, 315, Luther, 100, 107, 292, 300, 322, 325 303 Metaphysics-Anti- Machine, 94, 101, 107, 108, metaphysics, 286 113, 287, 314 Mill, 305 MacIntyre, A., 205, 206, 352 Mills, Charles, 230 Mackie, 93, 280 Minoritization, 225 Macmurray, John, 7, 14, 24, Minoritized, 225 25, 264, 268 Modern Ontological Mad At School, 221 Personalism, 40, 50, 51, Mad Maps, 238 52, 269 Madness, 116 Money, 188, 189, 190 Madness & Oppression, 239 , 307 , 315 Monotheism, 104 Mander, William, 142, 144, Moral status, 169, 170, 174, 145, 332, 333 335 Marcel, G., 39 Morality, 93, 281 Maritain, Jacques, 7, 8, 261 Moses, 94, 297, 301 Marquis, Don, 12, 263 Mourning, 119, 120, 121, 122, Maruna, Shadd, 203, 204, 123, 124, 125, 126, 127, 205, 208, 209, 350, 351, 128, 129 352 Moya, P, 232

374 Index

Multiculturalism, 232 Occam, William of, 300 Multinational Corporations Old and new, 114 (MNCs), 244, 245, 246, Ontological proof, 101, 102, 248, 252, 256, 257, 258, 297 259 , 102, 106, 109 Naaman, 141 Opinion, 100, 112, 116, 304, NAMI, 233 315 National Alliance for the Origin, 324 Mentally Ill, 233 Origination, 108, 109, 296, Naturalism, 94, 104, 291, 295 298, 317 Nature, 94, 104, 108, 182, 188, Pannenberg, 320 190, 191, 296, 344 , 106, 107, 115, Necessity, 108, 314, 320 288, 301, 303, 323 Neeb, 314, 325 Pantheist, 109 Negation, 99, 103, 111, 112, , 94, 112, 308, 289, 295, 297 309, 315 Neiman, 93, 280 Pascal, 323 Neo-Confucianism, 320 Pätzold, 325 Neoplatonism, 105 Paul, 324 Neurodiversity, 222 PBS, 208 Neuroenhancement, 59, 60, Peace, 288 61, 62, 65, 66, 67, 72, 73, Perry, John, 136, 331 74, 75 Person, 93, 94, 104, 108, 109, Neuroethics, 58 110, 111, 113, 116, 119, Neurology, 94 120, 121, 122, 123, 127, Neuroscience, 93, 281 151, 154, 158, 159, 160, Neville, 281, 304, 308, 309, 161, 162, 295, 296, 310 319, 325 Personal identity, 133, 134 Nicomachean Ethics, 198 Personhood, 164, 165, 167, Niethammer, 113, 286 169, 171, 174, 175, 221, Nietzsche, 119, 124, 125, 126, 336 127, 128, 329 Persson and Savulescu, 66, , 115, 280 67, 68, 75, 76 Non-Being, 319 , 94, 99, 100, 102, 105, Nothing, 111, 115, 296, 308, 112, 138, 287, 290, 298, 309, 310 315 Nucleus, 111 Plotinus, 102, 324

Index 375

Polanyi, Michael, 7, 11, 15, 110, 111, 113, 114, 116, 262, 264 181, 182, 183, 184, 185, Polytheism, 32, 100 187, 278, 280, 305, 341 Popova, Z., 211, 216, 219, Reasonable 354, 355, 356 accommodations, 226 Porositat der Begriffe Reciprocal, 105, 302 Open texture, 12 Recognition, 189, 318, 344 Post-metaphysical, 68, 70, 71, Reflection, 122, 123 77 Rehabilitation, 195, 196, 208, Postmodern, 93, 310 347, 348, 349 Post-Traumatic Stress Reinhold, 102, 115, 287 Disorder, 222 Religion, 111 Presence, 178, 341 Religious, 94 Presuppositionlessness, 298 Renz, 318 Price, M., 221 Repentance, 197, 207, 210, Pringle-Pattison, 131, 132, 346, 349 133, 134, 135, 136, 138, Replicants/Twins, Evil, 21 139, 140, 143, 144, 145, Republic, 138 146, 149, 329, 331, 332, Ressentiment, 126, 127, 128, 333 129 Prisacariu, M. R., 215, 216, Restorative Justice, 194, 195, 355 196, 344, 346, 350 Providence, 314 Retribution, 198, 349 Psychiatric, 221 Revelation, 95 Psychology, 305 Rideau, W., 200, 201, 349 Punishment, 193, 194, 195, Robot, 93, 94, 107 196, 197, 198, 199, 207, Rohstock, 291 209, 210, 344, 345, 346, Root Error, 223 347, 348, 349, 350 Rorke, B., 219, 356 Purgatory, 138 Rorty, 297 Pyrrho, 288 R-Relation, 135 Quante, 306 Ruge, 299 Rauch, 310 Rühle, 286, 312, 314 Rawlesian, 70, 71 Sacred, 296 Reality, 101, 102 Sagan, Carl, 21, 267 Reason, 93, 94, 95, 99, 102, San Quentin, 197, 207, 353 104, 106, 107, 108, 109,

376 Index

Sandkaulen, 280, 286, 305, Society, 95 313, 316, 317, 318, 324 Sonderegger, 291 Satya P. Mohanty, 225 Sophocles, 288 Schelling, F. W. J., 102, 243, Sosthenia, 289 244, 245, 247, 248, 249, Soul, 106, 111 250, 251, 252, 254, 255, Soul-substance, 131, 132, 257, 260, 296, 299, 308, 133, 135 309, 310, 319, 324, 361, Spaemann, Robert, 22 362, 363, 364, 365 Speculation, 115, 116 Schick, 305 Speer, 315 Schlegel, 327 Spinoza, 94, 95, 96, 97, 105, Schleiermacher, 301 106, 107, 109, 112, 113, Scholtz, 324 115, 116, 278, 286, 287, Schults, 299, 300, 301, 308 288, 289, 297, 301, 307, Schulze, 100, 289, 290 309, 316, 318, 321, 325 Schumann, 324 Spinoza-Antispinoza, 107, Science, 100, 103, 107, 112, 286, 303 281 Spirit, 104, 106, 107, 108, 109, Second person, 79, 80, 82, 86, 110, 114, 279 90, 91 Spiritual, 287 Secular Redemption, 197, Stead, G. C., 20, 267 207, 208, 209, 210, 350 Stirner, 299 Secularism, 301 Strawson, P. F., 17, 19, 24, Self, 151, 152, 153, 154, 155, 266 156, 157, 158 Structuralism, 105 Sextus, 100 Subject, 110, 114, 310 Sexual assault, 177, 186, 188, Subjectivity, 60, 64, 72, 73 338, 339 Substance, 95, 106, 107, 108, Sherman, 310 109, 110, 112, 114, 322 Sickness, 124, 125, 126 Suffering, 119, 123, 124, 128, Siebers, T., 224 129 Siep, 306 Summerell, 310 Singer, Peter, 265 Supernatural, 104, 110, 295, Skepsis, 99, 100, 112, 116, 296 288, 289, 297, 315 Swinburne, 295 Skinner, 94, 280 Tanner, 315 Social Justice, 221

Index 377

Taylor, C., 202, 203, 204, 349, Unfit for the Future, 66 352 Ungrounded, 106 Telos, 140 Unlimited, 295 Testimony, 182, 185, 187 Validity, 325 Theism, 104, 105, 295, 304 Value, 111 , 93, 277, 278, 279, Value Independence, 57 280 Vanderjagt, 325 Theogony, 104, 105 Vernunft, 94, 99, 108, 109, Theolysis, 105 111, 280, 281, 305 Tillich, 295, 299, 301, 309, 319 Verstand, 99, 109, 111, 280, Time, 114, 319 281 Torrance, 315 Vico, 108, 306 Totality, 310 Vieweg, 289, 302, 316, 326 Transcendent, 68 Virtue, 190, 191, 339, 343, 344 Transcendental a priori, 298 Void, 321 Trappe, 302 Vulnerability, 126, 127, 129 Trinity, 110 Waibel, 318, 325 Truth, 56, 100, 103, 107, 108, Waismann, Friedrich, 11, 12, 112, 177, 182, 183, 185, 262 186, 188, 191, 278, 288, Webster, 315 298, 306, 311, 315, 325, Wechselerweis, 105 340, 341, 342, 344 Weinreich, 302 Ultimate, 295 Whitehead, 320 Unconditional, 101, 102, 106, Whole, 297, 298 107, 109, 111, 288, 291, Wildman, 294, 296, 299, 301, 304, 326 307, 308, 310, 315 Unconscious, 120, 121, 122, Wojtyla, K., 40, 41, 46, 269, 123, 125 270 Understanding, 44, 46, 99, Yaffe, Gideon, 135, 331 109, 111, 112, 280 Yovel, 325