Supervenience

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Supervenience Supervenience The notion of supervenience describes a relation between sets of properties. The central idea is that properties belonging to a set A supervene on properties belonging to a set B, the so-called supervenience base, iff any two individuals or possible worlds that are exactly alike with respect to B-properties are exactly alike with respect to A-properties. In other words, any two things that differ with respect to A-properties must differ with respect to B-properties. Mental properties supervene on physical properties, for instance, iff any two individuals that instantiate exactly the same physical properties must instantiate the same mental properties. The supervenience relation in its contemporary use first rose into prominence in metaethics. According to Richard M. Hare, any two persons or actions satisfying exactly the same non-moral description have to be ascribed the same moral attributes; otherwise, the logical rules for the use of terms like ‘good’ would be violated. Thus supervenience is employed to formulate adequacy conditions on the use of moral terms. Later, Donald Davidson introduced the notion into the philosophy of mind to describe the controversial relationship between the mental and the physical. Nowadays, philosophy of mind still is one of the most important fields of application of the supervenience relation. However, the notion also plays a central role in various other fields of analytic philosophy. In contemporary metaphysics, there are debates on whether modal properties supervene on non-modal properties and whether dispositions supervene on categorical properties. In ethics and aesthetics, supervenience is used to describe the relationship between normative and descriptive properties as well as between aesthetic and natural properties. 1 2. Definitions of supervenience 2.1. Weak and strong supervenience The intuitive definition of supervenience given above leaves open whether the supervenience relation relies on comparisons between single individuals or between whole possible worlds. Depending on how this issue is decided, one can spell out the definition of supervenience in different ways. If supervenience is taken to rely on comparisons between single individuals, the two standard notions are weak and strong supervenience, usually defined in the following way: Weak supervenience (WS): A-properties weakly supervene on B-properties iff for any possible world w and any individuals x and y, if x and y have the same B-properties in w, then x and y have the same A-properties in w. Strong supervenience (SS): A-properties strongly supervene on B-properties iff for all possible worlds w1 and w2 and any individuals x and y, if x in w1 has the same B-properties as y in w2, then x in w1 also has the same A-properties as y in w2. To illustrate the intuition behind (WS) and (SS), suppose that mental properties weakly supervene on physical properties and that x instantiates the mental property of being happy in some possible world w. Then, it follows from (WS) that all individuals who inhabit w and have the same physical properties as x are happy, too. The crucial difference between (WS) and (SS) is that the former only requires that individuals inhabiting the same possible world and having the same B-properties are alike with respect to A-properties, whereas strong supervenience involves cross-world comparisons between individuals. Accordingly, mental properties strongly supervene on physical properties iff any two individuals, whether they are 2 world-mates or inhabit different possible worlds, have the same mental properties if they are alike in any physical respect. (SS) hence implies (WS), i.e. whenever A strongly supervenes on B, then A weakly supervenes on B, but the converse does not hold. 2.2. Global supervenience In contrast to weak and strong supervenience, which rely on comparisons between single individuals, the notion of global supervenience takes the distribution of properties over whole possible worlds into account. The underlying idea is that A globally supervenes on B iff any possible worlds w1 and w2 that are exactly alike with respect to B are also exactly alike with respect to A. Suppose that Φ is a set containing properties and relations of a certain type, e.g. physical properties and relations. Then, the claim that w1 and w2 are exactly alike with respect to Φ is typically interpreted as the claim that there is a Φ-preserving isomorphism between w1 and w2, i.e. a one-one mapping Γ of the inhabitants of w1 onto the inhabitants of w2, such that for any Φ-property F, an individual x has F in w1 iff Γ(x) has F in w2, and for any Φ-relation R, the tuple <x1, ..., xn> instantiates R in w1 iff <Γ(x1), ..., Γ(xn)> instantiates R in w2. Accordingly, w1 and w2 are alike with respect to B iff there is a B-preserving isomorphism between them. The three standard definitions of global supervenience all rely on this notion: Weak global supervenience (WGS): A-properties weakly globally supervene on B-properties iff for any possible worlds w1 and w2, if there is a B-preserving isomorphism between w1 and w2, then there is an A-preserving isomorphism between w1 and w2. Intermediate global supervenience (IGS): A-properties intermediately globally supervene on B-properties iff for any possible worlds w1 and w2, if there is a B-preserving isomorphism 3 between w1 and w2, then there is a B-preserving isomorphism between w1 and w2 which is also an A-preserving isomorphism. Strong global supervenience (SGS): A-properties strongly globally supervene on B-properties iff for any possible worlds w1 and w2, any B-preserving isomorphism between w1 and w2 is an A-preserving isomorphism. The notions of global supervenience are all logically weaker than the notion of strong supervenience (SS). This becomes evident, for instance, if it is assumed that externalism about mental content is true. According to externalism, mental properties, such as beliefs, do not solely depend on an individual’s intrinsic physical properties, but also on the environment in which it is placed. In other words, if externalism is true, mental properties fail to strongly supervene on intrinsic physical properties. To see this, suppose that John living on Earth and Twin-John living on Twin-Earth instantiate exactly the same intrinsic physical properties. If then John and Twin-John both believe that the transparent liquid called ‘water’ in their community quenches thirst, John has a belief about H2O, whereas Twin-John has a belief about XYZ. According to externalism, this means that John and Twin-John are in different belief states and consequently have different mental properties. Thus, (leaving aside the fact that John’s body partially consists of H2O, whereas Twin-John’s body partially consists of XYZ), John and Twin-John have exactly the same intrinsic physical properties, but different mental properties and strong supervenience fails. The criterion of global supervenience is not violated, however. Earth and Twin-Earth, which can be considered as two different possible worlds, are radically different in some physical respect, viz. the chemical structure of the transparent liquid called ‘water’. Therefore, there is no isomorphism preserving physical 4 properties between them and none of the three criteria of global supervenience will be violated if John and Twin-John have different mental properties. In general, as long as there is no formal restriction on the structure of the properties contained in A and B, the three notions of global supervenience are logically distinct from (WS) and (SS). Karen Bennett shows, however, that each of the definitions of global supervenience is equivalent to strong supervenience if A and B contain intrinsic properties only. Moreover, Robert Stalnaker proposes a proof to the effect that if the supervenience base contains properties involving complete B-descriptions of possible worlds, (SS) is equivalent to (SGS). Yet, both Bennett’s and Stalnaker’s arguments are restricted to the case where A and B contain properties only. Oron Shagrir argues that if A and B contain relations, (SGS) is crucially distinct from (SS), since (SS) is defined for properties only and (SGS) can make claims about dependence relationships between sets of relations which cannot be made using (SS). 3. Supervenience and Other Relations Supervenience is a term of art which does not correspond to any common-sense notion. In particular, it cannot be equated with a causal or explanatory relationship. That supervenience cannot be equated with a causal relationship follows directly from the observation that supervenience is a synchronous relation, whereas causality is a diachronic relationship. That supervenience claims alone are not sufficient for grounding an explanatory relation becomes clear in view of the fact that supervenience is a reflexive relation – each set of properties trivially supervenes on itself according to all notions of supervenience specified above. However, identity does not count as an explanatory relationship. If Peter has the mental property of being happy, for instance, this cannot suitably be explained by the fact that Peter is happy. 5 Given that supervenience is not a causal or explanatory relationship, many authors claim that supervenience expresses a dependence relation: if A supervenes on B, then the properties contained in A are dependent on the properties contained in B. It is questionable, however, whether supervenience is strong enough to ground a dependence relation. If dependence is understood as an ontological priority relation, i.e. in such a way that A’s supervenience on B implies that the B-properties are ontologically prior to or more fundamental than the A-properties, supervenience cannot be equated with dependence. Suppose, for instance, that A = {being a father} and B = {being male, having at least one child}. Then, A supervenes on B and vice versa.
Recommended publications
  • The Myth of Supervenient Microphysicalism
    The myth of supervenient microphysicalism Juan Diego Morales1 (Universidad de Cartagena) So my aim is only to establish conditional claims of the form: even if certain facts are emergent vis‑à‑vis the microphysical realm, Physicalism can still be true. Papineau, 2008: 132 1. What physicalism is Let us begin with the idea that physicalism is the ontological theory which claims that the entities that constitute our world are physical enti‑ ties, phenomena which the physical sciences must discover and articulate in their theories.2 Following the naturalistic trend of philosophy in recent times, con‑ temporary philosophers have considered that physicalism is both an a pos‑ teriori and contingent thesis. Its a posteriori sense derives from the fact of being a position that tries to overcome the problems of its direct predeces‑ 1 [email protected]. My thanks to Alejandro Rosas, Brian McLaughlin, Reinaldo Bernal, and Larry Shapiro, for helpful and clarifying comments on drafts of this paper. 2 Here I will use the general sense of “entity” and “phenomenon” for including both particulars (as objects, events, processes, and so on) and what many theorists take as universals (as properties, relations, and laws). Philosophica, 48, Lisboa, 2016, pp. 47-61. Philosophica 48.indd 47 22/11/2016 9:26:50 PM 48 Juan Diego Morales sor, materialism. The latter was established as a metaphysical doctrine that attempted to specify the entities of our world in an a priori way, in terms of a specific set of features that supposedly defined the material; features such as conservation, deterministic and on contact interaction, impenetrability, inertia, and solidity.3 But this a priori specification proved to be wrong.
    [Show full text]
  • Troubles on Moral Twin Earth: Moral Queerness Revived*
    TERENCE HORGAN AND MARK TIMMONS TROUBLES ON MORAL TWIN EARTH: MORAL QUEERNESS REVIVED* ABSTRACT. J. L. Mackie argued that if there were objective moral properties or facts, then the supervenience relation linking the nonmoral to the moral would be metaphys- ically queer. Moral realists reply that objective supervenience relations are ubiquitous according to contemporary versions of metaphysical naturalism and, hence, that there is nothing especially queer about moral supervenience. In this paper we revive Mackie's challenge to moral realism. We argue: (i) that objective supervenience relations of any kind, moral or otherwise, should be explainable rather than sui generis; (ii) that this explanatory burden can be successfully met vis-a-vis the supervenience of the mental upon the physical, and in other related cases; and (iii) that the burden cannot be met for (putative) objective moral supervenience relations. What is the connection between the natural fact that an action is a piece of deliberate cruelty - say, causing pain just for fun - and the moral fact that it is wrong? It cannot be an entailment, a logical or semantic necessity. Yet it is not merely that the two features occur together. The wrongness must somehow be "consequential' or "supervenient'; it is wrong because it is a piece of deliberate cruelty. But just what in the world is signified by this 'because'? (J. L. Mackie, 1977, p. 44) Moral realism is the doctrine that there are moral facts, and that these facts are objective rather than being somehow constituted by human beliefs, attitudes, or conventions. ~ This view is increasingly popular in recent philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • On Interpreting Strong Supervenience
    Western Michigan University ScholarWorks at WMU Master's Theses Graduate College 12-1996 On Interpreting Strong Supervenience Zachary J. Ernst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wmich.edu/masters_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Ernst, Zachary J., "On Interpreting Strong Supervenience" (1996). Master's Theses. 3475. https://scholarworks.wmich.edu/masters_theses/3475 This Masters Thesis-Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate College at ScholarWorks at WMU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at WMU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ON INTERPRETING STRONG SUPERVENIENCE by Zachary J. Ernst A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of The Graduate College in partial fulfillmentof the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts Department of Philosophy Western Michigan University Kalamazoo, Michigan December 1996 Copyright by Zachary J. Ernst 1996 ON INTERPRETING STRONG SUPERVENIENCE Zachary J. Ernst, M.A. WesternMichigan University,_ 1996 J aegwon Kim's definitionof strong supervenience has found application in such areas as the mind-body problem, aesthetics, morality, and the relationship between physics and the special sciences. The main reason forthe popularity of supervenience is that it purportedly has a long laundry list of virtues. For instance, it has been claimed that supervenience accounts are non-reductive, capable of empirical verification, simple with respect to ontology, and explanatorily powerful. In this paper, I examine Kim's definition of strong supervenience, arguing that a fundamental ambiguity in the definition makes it impossible for strong supervenience to possess all of these virtues simultaneously.
    [Show full text]
  • The “Supervenience Argument”: Kim's Challenge to Nonreductive Physicalism
    The “Supervenience Argument”: Kim’s Challenge to Nonreductive Physicalism AUSONIO MARRAS University of Western Ontario [email protected] JUHANI YLI-VAKKURI McGill University [email protected] ABSTRACT. Jaegwon Kim’s “supervenience argument” purports to show that epiphenomenalism about the mental follows from premises that any nonreductive physicalist should find acceptable. Kim regards his argument as a reductio ad absurdum of nonreductive physicalism. We reconstruct and evaluate the latest version of Kim’s argument. We argue that the premises of Kim’s argument are much less innocent than they may appear. In particular, we single out for criticism an unstated assumption about the identity conditions of events, and we argue that this assumption could be seen as all by itself implying that nonreductive physicalism is false, thus begging the question against that position. It is also dubious, we argue, whether Kim’s unstated assumption is even consistent with one of the stated assumptions of his argument, “the principle of causal exclusion”, given a standard understanding of causal overdetermination. We conclude with some polemical remarks about the conception of causation presupposed by Kim’s argument—a conception that appears to depart from that at work in science and commonsense discourse. 1. Introduction1 Many philosophers have worried that physical causation may “exclude” mental causation—physical and mental causes “compete” for efficacy, and because of some principle (the causal closure of the physical domain, for example), physical causes inevitably “win”. This picturesque language is common, but explicit arguments, which identify prima facie plausible principles from which epiphenomenalism about the mental would logically 1 We would like to thank Ian Gold for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Between Saying and Doing: Towards an Analytic Pragmatism
    Brandom 4/30/2006 Between Saying and Doing: Towards an Analytic Pragmatism Lecture One (May 3, 2006) Extending the Project of Analysis1 My principal aim in these lectures is to present a new way of thinking about language, and about the relations between meaning and use, or between what is said and the activity of saying it. To that end, I will introduce a new metatheoretic conceptual apparatus, and develop it through applications to a number of sorts of locution that have properly been the focus of intense philosophical interest: logical and semantic vocabulary, indexical vocabulary, modal, normative, and intentional vocabularies. The concerns that animate this enterprise arise from a way of thinking about the nature of the general project pursued by analytic philosophy over the past century or so, and about its confrontation with Wittgensteinean pragmatism. Justifying that rendering of the tradition would take me far afield, but it will be well to begin with at least a sketch of that motivating picture. Section 1: The Classical Project of Analysis I think of analytic philosophy as having at its center a concern with semantic relations between what I will call ‘vocabularies’. (I use the term ‘vocabulary’ here in a very general and relaxed 1 Throughout its gestation, this project has been generously supported by the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation, first through their funding of a research year at the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, at Stanford University, and more recently, and even more lavishly, through their Distinguished Achievement in the Humanities Award. Whatever I have been able to accomplish here would not have been possible without that support, and the extended time for concentrated attention that it has afforded me.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mind–Body Problem: an Overview
    The Mind–Body Problem: An Overview Chapter 1 The Mind–Body Problem: An Overview Kirk Ludwig I have said that the soul is not more than the body, And I have said that the body is not more than the soul, And nothing, not God, is greater to one than one’s self is. Walt Whitman 1.1 Introduction Understanding the place of thought and feeling in the natural world is central to that general comprehension of nature, as well as that special self-understanding, which are the primary goals of science and philosophy. The general form of the project, which has exercised scientists and philosophers since the ancient world, is given by the question, ‘What is the relation, in general, between mental and physical phenomena?’ There is no settled agreement on the correct answer. This is the single most important gap in our understanding of the natural world. The trouble is that the question presents us with a problem: each possible answer to it has consequences that appear unacceptable. This problem has traditionally gone under the heading ‘The Mind–Body Problem.’1 My primary aim in this chapter is to explain in what this traditional mind–body problem consists, what its possible solutions are, and what obstacles lie in the way of a resolution. The discussion will develop in two phases. The first phase, sections 1.2–1.4, will be concerned to get clearer about the import of our initial question as a precondition of developing an account of possible responses to it. The second phase, sections 1.5–1.6, explains how a problem arises in our attempts to answer the question we have characterized, and surveys the various solutions that can be and have been offered.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mind and the Problem of Free Will in the Light of Quantum Mechanics
    Philosophy of Mind and the Problem of Free Will in the Light of Quantum Mechanics. Henry P. Stapp Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory University of California Berkeley, California 94720 Abstract Arguments pertaining to the mind-brain connection and to the physical effectiveness of our conscious choices have been presented in two recent books, one by John Searle, the other by Jaegwon Kim. These arguments are examined, and it is explained how the encountered difficulties arise from a defective understanding and application of a pertinent part of contemporary science, namely quantum mechanics. The principled quantum uncertainties entering at the microscopic levels of brain processing cannot be confined to the micro level, but percolate up to the macroscopic regime. To cope with the conflict between the resulting macroscopic indefiniteness and the definiteness of our conscious experiences, orthodox quantum mechanics introduces the idea of agent-generated probing actions, each of which specifies a definite set of alternative possible empirically/experientially distinguishable outcomes. Quantum theory then introduces the mathematical concept of randomness to describe the probabilities of the various alternative possible outcomes of the chosen probing action. But the agent-generated choice of which probing action to perform is not governed by any known law or rule, statistical or otherwise. This causal gap provides a logical opening, and indeed a logical need, for the entry into the dynamical structure of nature of a process that goes beyond the currently understood quantum mechanical statistical generalization of the deterministic laws of classical physics. The well-known quantum Zeno effect can then be exploited to provide a natural process that establishes a causal psychophysical link within the complex structure consisting of a stream of conscious experiences and certain macroscopic classical features of a quantum mechanically described brain.
    [Show full text]
  • Emergence, Reduction and Supervenience: a Varied Landscape
    Emergence, Reduction and Supervenience: a Varied Landscape J. Butterfield Trinity College, Cambridge University, Cambridge CB2 1TQ; email: [email protected] Abstract This is one of two papers about emergence, reduction and supervenience. It expounds these notions and analyses the general relations between them. The com- panion paper analyses the situation in physics, especially limiting relations between physical theories. I shall take emergence as behaviour that is novel and robust relative to some comparison class. I shall take reduction as deduction using appropriate auxiliary definitions. And I shall take supervenience as a weakening of reduction, viz. to allow infinitely long definitions. The overall claim of this paper will be that emergence is logically independent both of reduction and of supervenience. In particular, one can have emergence with reduction, as well as without it; and emergence without supervenience, as well as with it. Of the subsidiary claims, the four main ones (each shared with some other au- thors) are: (i): I defend the traditional Nagelian conception of reduction (Section 3); (ii): I deny that the multiple realizability argument causes trouble for reduc- tions, or “reductionism” (Section 4); (iii): I stress the collapse of supervenience into deduction via Beth’s theorem (Section 5.1); (iv): I adapt some examples already in the literature to show supervenience arXiv:1106.0704v1 [physics.hist-ph] 3 Jun 2011 without emergence and vice versa (Section 5.2). 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Definingterms.................................. 3 1.1.1 Emergence as novel and robust behaviour; reduction as deduction; supervenienceasdetermination . 3 1.1.2 Avoidingcontroversy .......................... 4 1.1.3 Themiddleofaspectrum ......................
    [Show full text]
  • An Axiological Theory of Pain
    Bad by Nature: An Axiological Theory of Pain This chapter defends an axiological theory of pain according to which pains are bodily episodes that are bad in some way. Section 1 introduces two standard assumptions about pain that the axiological theory constitutively rejects: (i) that pains are essentially tied to consciousness and (ii) that pains are not essentially tied to badness. Section 2 presents the axiological theory by contrast to these and provides a preliminary defense of it. Section 3 introduces the paradox of pain and argues that since the axiological theory takes the location of pain at face value, it needs to grapple with the privacy, self-intimacy and incorrigibility of pain. Sections 4, 5 and 6 explain how the axiological theory may deal with each of these. Before starting, two methodological caveats are in order. First, the goal is here to understand what pains are: we want to spell out the nature of pains, that is, their essence or real definition (Fine, 1994). Perhaps that nature is multifaceted: perhaps pains have several essential features. To express these, I shall use the following expressions interchangeably: “one essential feature of pain is to be F”, “pains are essentially F”, “part of the nature of pains is to be F”, “what it is to be a pain is in part to be F”.1 Second, the following purports to shed light on the nature of pain from the stance of descriptive metaphysics. One working assumption is therefore that at least part of the nature of pain is correctly captured by our pre-theoretical conceptions.
    [Show full text]
  • From Adamsian Axiology to Theistic Natural Law Theory*
    From Adamsian axiology to theistic natural law theory Mark C. Murphy Robert Adams argues that God is not only good, God is the Good (F&IG, p. 28). Adams proceeds from this starting point to a Platonist account of goodness and a voluntarist account of rightness. My aim in this paper is to explain why one who is highly sympathetic with Adams‟s axiology might find oneself nevertheless drawn toward theistic Aristotelian positions on the good and the right rather than toward Adams‟s own views. I. Goodness Within theistic ethics we can distinguish between two sets of argumentative considerations that underwrite the explanation of moral matters in theistic terms: explanandum-focused and explanans-focused. Explanandum-focused considerations are the more familiar and are employed within theistic ethics in pretty much the same way that they are employed within ethics generally. The idea is that there are a variety of features of moral judgments or moral facts that call for explanation, either individually or in tandem; and the moral philosopher‟s job is to provide some explanation as to how it is possible or actual or necessary that moral judgments or moral facts have those features. The distinctive feature of theistic ethics with respect to explanandum-focused considerations is not in the method employed, which is held in common with nontheistic 1 ethicists, but in the conclusions reached: that the features of moral judgments or moral facts that need explanation are best explained theistically.1 But it is important that there is another approach to ethics that theistic ethicists have taken.
    [Show full text]
  • Supervenience and Dependence
    Supervenience and Dependence Philipp Keller, 6th May 2004 6th May 2004 The idea To say that the A-properties or facts are supervenient on the B-properties or facts is to say that the A-facts are, in a sense, redundant, since they are already implicitly specified when one has specified all the B-facts. A-facts are not fact ‘over and above’ the B-facts, not something ‘separate’. To state an A-fact, or ascribe an A-property, is to describe the same reality in a different way, at a different level of abstraction, by carving the same world at different joints. (Stalnaker 1996: 87) Three key ingredients: 1. covariance 2. dependence 3. nonreducibility Intra-world supervenience: nonreductionism without covariance Definition 1 (Intra-world supervenience). A set of properties A intra-worldly supervenes upon a set of properties B iff, for any possible world w, if x and y are B-indiscernible in w, then they are A-indiscernible in w. (1) 2∀x∀F ∈A(F x → ∃G∈B(Gx ∧ ∀y(Gy → F y))) Intra-world supervenience does not capture relational dependencies and does not support coun- terfactuals. The covariance might be purely accidental. Inter-world supervenience: covariance without non-reductionism Definition 2 (Inter-world supervenience). A set of properties A inter-worldly supervenes upon a set of properties B iff, for any worlds w and v and any individuals x and y, if x has the same B-properties in w than y has in v, then x has in w the same A-properties than y has in v.
    [Show full text]
  • On Moral Supervenience Ramon Alvarado University of Texas at El Paso, [email protected]
    University of Texas at El Paso DigitalCommons@UTEP Open Access Theses & Dissertations 2014-01-01 On Moral Supervenience Ramon Alvarado University of Texas at El Paso, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.utep.edu/open_etd Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Alvarado, Ramon, "On Moral Supervenience" (2014). Open Access Theses & Dissertations. 1574. https://digitalcommons.utep.edu/open_etd/1574 This is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@UTEP. It has been accepted for inclusion in Open Access Theses & Dissertations by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@UTEP. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ON MORAL SUPERVENIENCE RAMÓN ALVARADO Department of Philosophy APPROVED: Marc Moffett, Ph.D., Chair Caroline Arruda, Ph.D. Jean-Paul Vessel, Ph.D. Bess Sirmon-Taylor, Ph.D. Interim Dean of the Graduate School Copyright © by Ramón Alvarado 2014 To Isaac, Alejandra, and Blanca. ON MORAL SUPERVENIENCE by RAMÓN ALVARADO, B.A. Philosophy THESIS Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of The University of Texas at El Paso in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS Department of Philosophy THE UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS AT EL PASO May 2014 Acknowledgements First and foremost I want to thank Dr. Caroline Arruda. Her caring mentorship gave me the moral, emotional, and intellectual support to ultimately produce this project. I am forever in debt to her for having taken me under her considerate guidance and for taking the time to share her vast knowledge and expertise with me. I can only hope to repay this by striving to someday become as good a mentor and philosopher as she is.
    [Show full text]